ebook img

The Rei(g)n of ‘Rule’ PDF

139 Pages·2010·1.228 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The Rei(g)n of ‘Rule’

To Jonathan Dana Riesenfeld The Rei(g)n of ‘Rule’ APORIA Apori/a HRSG. VON / EDITED BY Jesús Padilla Gálvez (University of Castilla-La Mancha) Alejandro Tomasini Bassols (National Autonomous University of Mexico) ADVISORY BOARD Pavo Barišić (University of Split) Michel Le Du (Université de Strasbourg) Guillermo Hurtado (National Autonomous University of Mexico) Lorenzo Peña (Spanish National Research Council) Nuno Venturinha (New University of Lisbon) Nicanor Ursua Lezaun (University of the Basque Country) Pablo Quintanilla (Pontifical Catholic University of Peru) Aporia is a new series devoted to studies in the field of philosophy. Aporia (Aπορία) means philosophical puzzle and the aim of the series is to present contributions by authors who systematically investigate current problems. Aporia (Aπορία) puts special emphasis on the publication of concise arguments on the topics studied. The publication has to contribute to the explanation of current philosophical problem, using a systematic or a historic approach. Contributions should concern relevant philosophical topics and should reflect the ongoing progress of scientific development. Band 2 / Volume 2 Dana Riesenfeld The Rei(g)n of ‘Rule’ Bibliographic information published by the Deutsche Nationalbibliothek The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbibliografie; detailed bibliographic data are available in the Internet at http://dnb.d-nb.de. North and South America by Transaction Books Rutgers University Piscataway, NJ 08854-8042 [email protected] United Kingdom, Ireland, Iceland, Turkey, Malta, Portugal by Gazelle Books Services Limited White Cross Mills Hightown LANCASTER, LA1 4XS [email protected] Livraison pour la France et la Belgique: Librairie Philosophique J.Vrin 6, place de la Sorbonne; F-75005 PARIS Tel. +33 (0)1 43 54 03 47; Fax +33 (0)1 43 54 48 18 www.vrin.fr 2010 ontos verlag P.O. Box 15 41, D-63133 Heusenstamm www.ontosverlag.com ISBN 978-3-86838-085-9 2010 No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in retrieval systems or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, microfilming, recording or otherwise without written permission from the Publisher, with the exception of any material supplied specifically for the purpose of being entered and executed on a computer system, for exclusive use of the purchaser of the work Printed on acid-free paper FSC-certified (Forest Stewardship Council) This hardcover binding meets the International Library standard Printed in Germany by buch bücher.de Table of Contents Introduction 1 I. Rules, norms, conventions and necessity 1 Why norms are not conventions and conventions are not norms 1.1 The tension of normativity 11 1.2 Two concepts of arbitrariness: Saussure and Lewis 13 1.3 Can conventions become norms? 22 1.4 Rules 25 2 Cavell on normative necessity 2.1 “I am less interested now in the ‘mean’ than I am in the ‘must’” 29 2.2 “Here the pantomime of caution concludes” 31 2.3 “the hopelessness of speaking, in a general way, 33 about the ‘normativeness’” II. Rules as conventions vs. rules as norms in the rule-following debates 3 What is a rule and what ought it to be 3.1 The reduction of rules to conventions 39 vs. the reduction of rules to norms 3.2 Kripke: The reduction of rules to conventions 40 3.3 Baker & Hacker: The reduction of rules to norms 52 3.4 Meredith Williams: On normative necessity 63 3.5 Cora Diamond: Rules and their right place 75 III. Twisted Language 4 Davidson on rules, conventions and norms 4.1. Normativity without conventionality 83 4.2 Communication without rules or conventions 83 4.3 “The second person” vs. the community view 90 4.4 Two kinds of normativity 93 4.5 The unpacking of ‘ought’ 99 4.6 Normativity without norms 102 5 Searle on rules 5.1 The shortcut argument against rule 109 5.2 Is language a rule governed form of behavior or is it not? 110 5.3 (No) Rules of conversation 111 5.4 Background brought to the foreground 116 Conclusion 119 The Rei(g)n of ‘Rule’ “We seem to be dealing with an especially messy cluster concept” (Lewis (1969: 105), on ‘rule’) 1. Rules, Norms and Conventions Philosophy in general and the linguistic analytic tradition in particular have been reigned by the concept of ‘rule’. Forefathers of the analytic philoso- phy of language – Frege and Wittgenstein – considered rules to be funda- mental in any attempt to understand our language and thought. Writers such as Carnap and Sellars all agree on the importance and centrality of ‘rules’, but differ on the definition and role assigned to language-related rules. Contemporary philosophers of language such as Searle and Brandom follow the analytic tradition both in assigning rules an essential function and in disagreeing on how this function operates. Philosophy has not only been reigned by rules, it has also been reined by them. While ‘rules’ are central in nearly every theory on or per- spective of language, the concept ‘rule’ is not sufficiently defined – being used to mean different things and assigned with different tasks by different philosophers. This situation, though, is not coincidental. It reveals a sig- nificant feature of the concept of ‘rule’: it is a concept that (at least as re- lated to language) evades definition. ‘Rule’ cannot be well defined, clearly and sharply delineated, as perhaps those who use it had hoped. This book is first and foremost an attempt to argue this, to present the conceptual im- possibility of clearly defining rules and to proclaim ‘rule’ a philosophically ill concept. The aim of this study is to diagnose the illness before offering a remedy. The concept ‘rule’ is situated at the busiest crossroad of the philoso- phy of language. Every other significant concept in this field is connected to rules and most philosophers assume, explicitly or implicitly, that rules are an essential part of the very definition of language. One of the basic ideas shared by philosophers of language is that the phenomenon called language is essentially a system of rules and that therefore an understand- ing of language essentially involves an understanding of the rules of lan- guage. Both of these claims – the ontological (‘rules exist’) and the epis- temic (‘understanding language is the understanding of the rules of lan- 2 guage’) – are closely related via the functional role rules are assigned. Functionality is supposed to answer the question of how rules operate in language and how they achieve their task. Yet in addition to an absence of a clear definition of ‘rule’ in theories of language, there is no clear-cut an- swer to the functionality of rules. The demands and expectations from rules are multiple and varying; e.g., philosophers tend to think of rules as a key concept in understanding understanding, in shedding light on how we communicate with one another. They appeal to rules in explaining, justify- ing and guiding our (language-related) actions and in explaining first or second language acquisition. Meaning itself, some contend, is dependent on the assumption of the existence of rules. If language has anything to do with distinguishing between correct vs. incorrect uses of language, it is ar- gued, then we must treat it as essentially rule-bound. I claim not only that the expectations and demands from rules are multifaceted, but more importantly that some of the most fundamental de- mands contradict each other; in other words, some of the demands of rules cannot be met by one and the same concept. Philosophers not only require too much of rule, they also demand that it perform conflicting tasks. This is the general diagnosis of the philosophical illness of ‘rule’. In this study I attempt to spell out and illustrate the symptoms of this illness, as they ap- pear in a number of varieties of the disease. The basic tension within the concept of rule is that philosophers wish for it to be on the one hand a normative concept, and on the other, a de- scriptive one. By ‘normativity’ I am alluding to the basic, rudimentary definition of normativity; i.e., that normativity distinguishes between the realm of ought and the domain of is. Unlike within other philosophical ter- rains, in the philosophy of language, the normative distinction carries with it no moral implications. Rather, it is the duty of linguistic norms to pry apart correct and incorrect uses of language. Rules, it is said, tell us how we ought to talk, how we ought to act linguistically. The normativity of linguistic rules grants meaning to the idea that we are sometimes wrong and that we can be corrected by others or ourselves. The normative dimen- sion of language accounts for our predisposition to appeal to rules as a canon of correctness and to view rules as guiding our actions. Along with the aspiration to provide a normative account of rules, philosophers simultaneously expect rules to be descriptive concepts, i.e., to portray as accurately as possible our actual use. I call this aspect the con- ventionality of rules. I chose the term “convention” since it captures the ar- bitrariness of rules, the fact that rules, unlike natural laws, embody a sense 3 of contingency and option. The conventional dimension of rules ties rules to actual uses, regular habits, tradition of use and customs, while maintain- ing the rule’s descriptive nature. At first, perhaps the tension I’m referring to does not make itself ob- vious. For why can’t the concept of rule be both normative and descrip- tive? And indeed, there is no general reason why the two functions cannot coincide. My argument is slightly different. Although it is not impossible that normative rules would also be descriptive and that descriptive rules would also be normative, it is not necessary. In other words if the rules of language are both normative (set a standard of correctness, tell us how we ought to speak or to act linguistically) and descriptive (present a relation, describe, as fully as possible, the way we actually use language) the con- nection between those two functions is contingent. Philosophers, I have no- ticed, tend to emphasize either the normative dimension of rules, or their descriptive dimension. Moreover, emphasis typically leads to a reduction. So ‘rules’ are in general reduced to either norms or conventions, depending on the philosopher’s choice of emphasis. Each reduction has its advantages as well as its disadvantages, which are summarized in the following table: Rules as norms Rules as conventions + Maintain the rule’s con- Maintain the rule’s con- nection to correctness nection to actual uses ― Waive a necessary connec- Derive ought from is, or tion to actual uses waive ‘correctness’ as a concept related to rules The main advantage of the reduction of rules to norms is the ability of such reduction to preserve one of the rule’s main intuitive tasks, that of serving as a guide of correct (vs. incorrect) uses of language. The main dis- advantage of such reduction is that the concept of rule we get loses a nec- essary connection with the actual way people use their language. The rea- son is conceptual; nothing guarantees that the way in which we ought to act is the way in which we indeed act. This allows for the possibility that no one follows linguistic rules. On the other hand, the reduction of rules to conventions guarantees that the concept of rule is the one employed, by and large, by the linguistic community. However, the main shortcoming of the reduction to conven- tions is that since the way people indeed act does not necessarily corre- spond to the way they ought to, rules seen as conventions either give up on any notion of correctness or perform a type of naturalistic fallacy by as-

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.