THE RECEPTION OF ARISTOTLE’S METAPHYSICS IN AVICENNA’S KIT$B AL-S[IF$" ISLAMIC PHILOSOPHY THEOLOGY AND SCIENCE Texts and Studies EDITED BY H. DAIBER VOLUME LXIII THE RECEPTION OF ARISTOTLE S METAPHYSICS IN ’ AVICENNA S KIT$B AL S[IF$" ’ - A Milestone of Western Metaphysical Thought BY AMOS BERTOLACCI BRILL LEIDEN •BOSTON 2006 This book is printed on acid-free paper Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Bertolacci, Amos. The reception of Aristotle’s Metaphysics in Avicenna’s Kit§b al-’if§": a milestone of Western metaphysical thought / by Amos Bertolacci. p. cm. — (Islamic philosophy, theology, and science, ISSN 0169-8729 ; v. 63) Revision of the author’s thesis (Ph.D.)—Yale University, 2005. Includes bibliographical references (p. ) and index. ISBN-13: 978-90-04-14899-4 ISBN-10: 90-04-14899-X (hardback : alk. paper) 1. Avicenna, 980-1037. Ilahiyat. 2. Aristotle. Metaphysics. 3. Aristotle—Influence. 4. Philosophy, Islamic—Greek influences. 5. Metaphysics—History. I. Title. II. Series. B751.Z7B47 2006 181’.5—dc22 2006-44005 ISSN 0169-8729 ISBN 90 04 14899 X © Copyright 2006 by Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, The Netherlands Koninklijke Brill NV incorporates the imprints Brill Academic Publishers, Martinus Nijhoff Publishers and VSP. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, translated, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without prior written permission from the publisher. Authorization to photocopy items for internal or personal use is granted by Brill provided that the appropriate fees are paid directly to The Copyright Clearance Center, 222 Rosewood Drive, Suite 910 Danvers MA 01923, USA. Fees are subject to change. printed in the netherlands CONTENTS Introduction ................................................................................ vii Abbreviations .............................................................................. xv PART ONE The Arabic Reception of the METAPHYSICS before Avicenna Introduction ................................................................................ 3 Chapter One—The Arabic translations of the Metaphysics: a new assessment on account of the evidence provided by Avicenna ............................................................................ 5 Chapter Two—Beyond al-Kindì and al-Fàràbì: Avicenna’s position in the history of the Arab reception of the Metaphysics ................................................................................ 37 Chapter Three—Between Ammonius and Avicenna: al-Fàràbì’s treatise On the Goals of Aristotle’s Metaphysics .... 65 PART TWO The Scientific Profile of the METAPHYSICS According to Avicenna Introduction ................................................................................ 107 Chapter Four—Avicenna’s conception of the theme of the Metaphysics: “existent qua existent” as the subject-matter, the first causes and God as the goal of metaphysics .......... 111 Chapter Five—Avicenna’s reworking of the structure of the Metaphysics: metaphysics as the discipline dealing with the species, the properties and the principles of “existent” ...... 149 Chapter Six—Avicenna’s elaboration of the method of the Metaphysics: metaphysics as a demonstrative, analytical, non-dialectical science ............................................................ 213 vi contents Chapter Seven—Avicenna’s view of the relationship of the Metaphysics with the other parts of the Aristotelian corpus: metaphysics as the founding discipline ................................ 265 PART THREE The Content of the METAPHYSICS According to Avicenna Introduction ................................................................................ 305 Chapter Eight—The quotations of the Metaphysics in the Ilàhiyyàt .................................................................................... 309 Chapter Nine—The main source of Avicenna’s conception of metaphysics as a science: book G and its quotations .... 375 Chapter Ten—Avicenna’s attitude towards dialectic: book B and its quotations .................................................................. 403 Chapter Eleven—The other sources of the Ilàhiyyàt .............. 441 Conclusion .................................................................................. 471 Appendices Appendix A: Towards a critical edition of the Ilàhiyyàt: list of corrections of the Cairo printed text .............................. 483 Appendix B: Index of authors and works quoted in the Ilàhiyyàt .................................................................................... 559 Appendix C: Overview of the main works by Avicenna on metaphysics in chronological order ...................................... 581 Appendix D: Names for Aristotle’s Metaphysics and metaphysics as a discipline in Avicenna’s works .......... 593 Appendix E: The style of the Kitàb al-”ifà" ............................ 607 Appendix F: The terminology for “property” in the Ilàhiyyàt .................................................................................... 613 Bibliography ................................................................................ 617 Index of Names and Places ...................................................... 655 Index of Aristotle’s Works with Passages Cited ...................... 665 Index of Avicenna’s Works with Passages Cited .................... 666 Index of Manuscripts ................................................................ 669 Index of Texts, Outlines, Tables .............................................. 670 INTRODUCTION “[...] there is as yet no metaphysics at all. [...] a complete reform or rather a rebirth of meta- physics [...] is inevitably approaching” (I. Kant, Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics, Preface, transl. G. Hatfield, pp. 6–7) “Insofar as a thinking devotes itself to the path of experiencing the foundation of metaphysics [...] in a certain way it has abandoned metaphysics” (M. Heidegger, What is Metaphysics?, Introduction) The history of the reception of Aristotle’s Metaphysics can be por- trayed as a sequence of “reforms”, ending in its definitive “aban- donment”. The “reforms” started from the very beginning, with the first “edition” of the Metaphysics by Andronicus of Rhodes in the I century BC (a collection of scattered Aristotelian material on meta- physics), and were mainly performed by the commentators (Greek, Arab and Latin) of Late Antiquity and the Middle Ages. Its “aban- donment”, on the other hand, can be ascribed to the original thinkers on metaphysics of the Modern Era. The reforms by commentators aimed at improving the Aristotelian account of this discipline (as in Andronicus’ edition), by either clarifying its content, or elucidating its articulation, or refining its method, or enlarging its scope to encompass other perspectives on metaphysics, like those of Neoplatonic philosophy and Christian or Islamic faith. These efforts of amelio- ration and expansion, however, conveyed a progressive departure from the Metaphysics, thus preparing the ground for the subsequent dismissal of this work together with the type of metaphysics it expressed. In accordance with the spirit of the “scientific revolution”, the main concern about metaphysics in Modern times was to provide a rad- ical foundation of this discipline as a science: once scholars realized that this goal could not be attained by means of partial adjustments of Aristotle’s dictate, but required a complete revision of traditional metaphysics, they abandoned the Metaphysics in its entirety as the normative text on metaphysics, and explored new directions of research. The “post-Aristotelian” stage of metaphysics, starting with viii introduction Descartes, followed two distinct paths: either the complete neglect of this discipline as inevitably non-scientific (as in Hume), or the attempt to reconstruct it as a rigorous science on a totally different basis (as in Kant), relegating the Aristotelian heritage to a function little more than terminological. Avicenna (Ibn Sìnà, 980 ca.–1037 AD) plays a key-role in this overall process. His attitude towards Aristotle’s Metaphysics marks the transition from the stage of exegetical “reform” to that of self-assertive “abandonment”. On the one hand, Avicenna’s metaphysical oeuvre is the last and widest of a series of transformations of Aristotle’s Metaphysics that took place during the Middle Ages. On the other hand, within the Peripatetic tradition it constitutes the first concrete replacement of this work with an original treatment on metaphysics, thus allow- ing metaphysics the possibility of an autonomous progress. In so far as Avicenna’s most important works on metaphysics are constitu- tively linked with the Metaphysics, take into account all the previous reflection on this work, and keep the non-Aristotelian components of metaphysics (Neoplatonic and theological) within the boundaries of Aristotle’s original framework, they are an expression of the Medieval Peripatetic tradition. But in so far as they are not com- mentaries on the Metaphysics (neither literal exegeses nor paraphrases), but original reworkings of it, and display epistemological concerns about metaphysics that are largely foreign to Aristotle, they antici- pate the Modern approach to metaphysics. The impact of Avicenna’s thought on Descartes (the “father” of Modern metaphysics), recently pointed out by scholars, cannot be coincidental.1 Whereas in the East the substantial progress represented by Avicenna’s metaphysics in comparison to Aristotle’s homonymous writing was immediately perceived, and the former somehow substituted the latter (either to be accepted and commented upon, or to be criticized), in the West Aristotle’s Metaphysics kept on being the textbook on metaphysics for a few centuries, and Avicenna’s point of view was inserted in the commentaries on the Metaphysics, in different amounts and degrees, until the definitive abandonment of this work, as described above. In sum: Avicenna’s metaphysics is both continuous and discon- tinuous with Aristotle’s Metaphysics. While being Aristotelian in its guidelines, it goes far beyond Aristotle in its overall purport. As a 1 See Druart [1988]; Mc Tighe [1988]; Hasnawi [1997b]; Jolivet [1997]. introduction ix synthesis of both respects, it is unprecedented in the history of the reception of the Metaphysics, and can be compared to Proclus’ meta- physics with regard to the previous Platonic tradition. In this per- spective, it is not exaggerated to regard Avicenna as the second authority on metaphysics, after Aristotle himself, within the Aristotelian school, and the initiator of a new phase of the history of this discipline. Reform and abandonment, continuity and rupture, tradition and innovation: this two-fold attitude of Avicenna towards Aristotle’s Metaphysics is the essence of his “interpretation” of this work. Avicenna’s interpretation of the Metaphysics in his most important work on meta- physics—the Ilàhiyyàt ([Science of ] Divine Things) of the Kitàb al-”ifà" (Book of the Cure)—is the object of the present study. * * * The imperfect state of Aristotle’s writings—a situation poignantly described by contemporary Aristotelian scholars as a contrast between “ideal” and “achievement” in Aristotle’s philosophical system2—has not escaped Aristotelian interpreters throughout history. In the Intro- duction of one of his philosophical summae, the Ma“riqiyyùn (Easterners), Avicenna states that the Aristotelian corpus presents “loose ends”, “breaches”, “imperfections” and “defective theories”, and is in need of “addition”, “correction”, and “revision”; the required restoration— he continues—was not accomplished by previous Aristotelian schol- ars, and only Avicenna himself “perfected” what Aristotle and his successors “meant to say but fell short of doing, never reaching their aim in it”.3 The defects of Aristotle’s writings, of which Avicenna shows a keen perception, are especially puzzling in the case of the Metaphysics. This work elicits two main categories of problems. The first regards what we can call the “form” of the Metaphysics, namely the scientific profile of the discipline it contains. To this rubric belong issues such as what the metaphysics deals with, how it is structured, what method it follows, how it relates to the other sciences of the Aristotelian corpus etc. What Aristotle says in all these regards is often either ellip- tical, or ambiguous, or, even worse, inconsistent. The second category 2 Barnes [2000], pp. 59–63. 3 Ma“riqiyyùn, pp. 2, 14–3, 5; pp. 3, 13–14. English translation in Gutas [1988], pp. 45–47.
Description: