ebook img

The Question of Being in Husserl’s Logical Investigations PDF

211 Pages·1981·5.759 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The Question of Being in Husserl’s Logical Investigations

The Question of Being in Husserl's Logical Investigations PHAENOMENOLOGICA COLLECTION FONDEE PAR H.L. V AN BREDA ET PUBLIEE SOUS LE PATRONAGE DES CENTRES D'ARCHIVES-HUSSERL 81 JAMES R. MENSCH The Question of Being in Husserl's Logical Investigations Comite de redaction de la collection: President: S. IJsseling (Leuven); Membres: M. Farber (Buffalo), E. Finkt (Freiburg i. Br.), L. Landgrebe (Kaln), W. Marx (Freiburg i. Br.), J.N. Mohanty (New Yark), P. Ricoeur (Paris), E. Straker (Kaln), 1. Taminiaux (Louvain), K.H. Volkmann-Schluck (Kaln); Secretaire: J. Taminiaux. JAMES R. MENSCH The Question of Being in Husserl's Logical Investigations 1981 SPRINGER-SCIENCE+BUSINESS MEDIA, B.V. This volume is listed in the Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data ISBN 978-90-481-8264-0 ISBN 978-94-017-3446-2 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-017-3446-2 Copyright © 1981 by Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht Originally published by Martinus NijhoffPublishers bY, The Hague in 1981 Sottcover reprint of the hardcover 1s t edition 1981 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, without the prior written permission of the publisher, Springer-Science+Business Media, B. V. This book is dedicated to the memory of Jacob Klein "Denn der Geist allein ist unsterblich" ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I wish to acknowledge my gratitude to Professor James Morrison of the University of Toronto for his encouragement and aid in the preparation of this work. His generosity is an example of the genuine philosophic spirit. I should also like to thank Ernie and Frauke Hankamer as well as Hugo and Ruth Jakusch whose kind ness sustained us in Munich and Dief~en. Finally, mention must be made of the Canada Council without whose financial aid this book would not have been possible. TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION I. THE REFUTATION OF PSYCHOLOGISM 9 Remark 24 II. ESTABLISHING THE GUIDING MOTIVATION: THE REFUTATION OF SCEPTICISM AND RELATIVISM 27 III. THE CATEGORY OF THE IDEAL 35 1. The Category in the Context of Ideen I 35 2. The Category in its own Context 42 IV. THE BEING OF THE IDEAL 53 V. SUBJECTIVE ACCOMPLISHMENT: INTENTION- ALITY AS ONTOLOGICAL TRANSCENDENCE 73 VI. THE SUBJECT -OBJECT CORRELATION 95 VII. CATEGORIAL REPRESENT A TION 133 VIII. ONTOLOGICAL DIFFICULTIES AND MOTIV A TING CONNECTIONS 149 NOTES 193 BIBLIOGRAPHY 207 NAME INDEX 209 SUBJECT INDEX 210 INTRODUCTION This study proposes a double thesis. The first concerns the Logische Untersuchungen itself. We will attempt to show that its statements about the nature of being are inconsistent and that this inconsis tency is responsible for the failure of this work. The second con cerns the Logische Untersuchungen's relation to the Ideen. The latter, we propose, is a response to the failure of the Logische Untersuchungen's ontology. It can thus be understood in terms of a shift in the ontology of the Logische Untersuchungen, a shift motivated by the attempt to overcome the contradictory assertions of the Logische Untersuchungen. In this sense our thesis is that, in the technical meaning that Husserl gives the term, the Logische Untersuchungen and the Ideen can be linked via a "motivated path." We can, by way of an introduction, clarify our theses by regard ing three elements. The first is the relation of epistemology to ontology. The second is the notion of motivation as Husserl conceives the term. The third is the fundamental distinctions that are to be explained via the notion of motivation. 1. We should begin by remarking that the goal of the Logische Untersuchungen is explicitly epistemological; it is that of answer ing "the cardinal question of epistemology, the question concerning the objectivity of knowledge" (LU, Tub. ed., I, 8; F., p. 56V For Husserl, his other questions - i.e., that of the theoretical bases of logic and that of the relation of logic to psychology - "essentially coincide" with this "cardinal question" (Ibid.). An important point here is that as Husserl conceives this question it has a certain regressive character. The inquiry is not just whether such know ledge can exist, but how it can. The inquiry is thus formulated in terms of the "conditions of the possibility of science in general" and "knowledge in general" - both being understood in the strong, objective sense of the terms (LU, "Prolegomena," §65, §66). 2 INTRODUCTION The relation of epistemology to ontology is set by HusserI's repeated assertion that metaphysics - a science of being qua being - is posterior to epistemology and in some sense can be thought of as growing out of the latter. 2 Given this formulation and given the Logische Untersuchungen's explicit goal of securing the objectivity of knowledge, it is obvious that the ontology Husserl puts forward must be shaped by this goal. The relation, however, is more intimate than this suggests. It is such that HusserI's ontology and epistemology must be considered a related, organic whole. If we follow Husserl when he divides the conditions for knowledge into subjective and objective conditions, we find that they are ultimately ontological conditions. The question faced by HusserI is, what must the being of both subjects and objects be if objective knowledge is to be at all possible? The conditions for the possibility of objective knowledge are, as we shall see, ulti mately understood as ontological conditions. In this regressive procedure in which we proceed from the assumption of objective knowledge to its essential ontological conditions, the intimacy of the relation is hereby expressed. In our view, it is such that onto logical conditions so laid down serve as a consistency test for the Logische Untersuchungen's conception of what it means to know. Granting this, we can clarify our first thesis which sees the failure of the Logische Untersuchungen as a failure of its ontology. If the ontological conditions for knowledge are contradictory, then, according to the above, the whole project of the Logische Untersuchungen, its fundamental motivation of providing an answer to the problem of the objectivity of knowledge, is not satisfied. 2. The relationship of the Logische Untersuchungen and the Ideen has been subject to a number of interpretations without any clear consensus of opinion.3 In HusserI's view, the works are dif ferent. There is a conceptual shift that takes place in the original interpretation of the Logische Untersuchungen. After the Logische Untersuchungen was written, " ... there occurred not just additions but transvaluations (nicht blo{3 Ergiinzungen, sondern Umwer tungen) in the original sphere of research" (LU, Tub. ed., I, viii-ix; F., p. 44). The reference of these remarks is the Ideen's doctrine of transcendental idealism. The move to this latter position, according to HusserI, is to be understood in terms of a "motivated INTRODUCTION 3 path" that begins with the problem of the objectivity of know ledge ("Nachwort," Ideen III; ed. W. Biemel, Husserliana V, The Hague, 1971, p. 150). To grasp Husserl's conception of this move, it is first necessary to understand the way in which he uses the terms "motivation" and "motivated path." In his developed phenomenology, the terms bear a certain technical sense. In constitutive phenomenology, for example, he speaks of the motivations that allow us to posit entities on the basis of evidence (See Ideen J, §52; ed. W. Biemel, Husserliana III, The Hague, 1950, p. 124). The source of the evidence is the interconnections of our perceptual experience. To make sense of our experience, to view it as the experience of relatively stable objects is, on the one hand, to be sensitive to the motivations arising from experience. On the other hand, it is to engage in what Husserl calls the thesis of rationality; the thesis is that the world is rational, that it presents itself as a collection of relatively stable objects which are there to be experienced, objects allowing of certain definite predicates. At its basis, the thesis is that our perceptual experience allows of inference, that we can infer objects, predicates and relations from it and thus come up with a world about which we can reason or infer (See Ibid., §§136-37, §139, §142; Biemel ed., pp. 335-36, 341, 348-39). More importantly for our own theme, the notion of motivation also plays a role in the explanation of the genesis of intellectual constructions: theories, sciences, ideologies, and so forth. It is in the context of this notion that Husserl's rather celebrated remark must be understood: The reigning dogma of a separation in principle between epistemological explanation and historical, even humanistic psychological explanation, between epistemological and genetic origin is basically mistaken - at least insofar as we do not in the usual way inadmissibly limit the notions of "history," "historical explanation," and "genesis" ("Beilage III," Krisis; ed. W. Biemel, 2nd ed., Husserliana VI, The Hague, 1962, p. 379). The inadmissible limitation referred to is the leaving out of account the notion of teleology. Thus, Husserl distinguishes his own account of philosophy from "that of a historical explanation

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.