ebook img

The Pythia’s Drunken Song: Thomas Carlyle’s Sartor Resartus and the Style Problem in German Idealist Philosophy PDF

86 Pages·1978·2.936 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The Pythia’s Drunken Song: Thomas Carlyle’s Sartor Resartus and the Style Problem in German Idealist Philosophy

THE PYTHIA'S DRUNKEN SONG ARCHIVES INTERNATIONALES D'HISTOIRE DES IDEES INTERNATIONAL ARCHIVES OF THE HISTORY OF IDEAS Series Minor 19 JERRY A. DIBBLE THE PYTHIA'S DRUNKEN SONG THOMAS CARLYLE'S SARTOR RESARTUS AND THE STYLE PROBLEM IN GERMAN IDEALIST PHILOSOPHY Directors; P. Dibon (Paris) and R. Popkin (Washington Univ., St. Louis) Editorial Board: J. Aubin (Paris); J. Collins (St. Louis Univ.); P. Costabel (Paris); A. Crombie (Oxford); I. Dambska (Cracow); H. de la Fontaine-Verwey (Amsterdam); H. Gadamer (Heidelberg); H. Gouhier (Paris); T. Gregory (Rome); T.E. Jessop (Hull); P.O. Kristeller (Columbia Univ.); Elisabeth Labrousse (Paris); A. Lossky (Los Angeles); S. Lindroth (Upsala); J. Orcibal (Paris); I.S. Revaht (Paris); Wolfgang Rod (Miinchen); J. Roger (Paris); G.S. Rousseau (Los Angeles); H. Rowen (Rutgers Univ., N.J.); c.B. Schmitt (Warburg Institute, London); G. Sebba (Emory Univ., Atlanta); R. Shackleton (Oxford); J. Tans (Groningen); G. Tonelli (Binghamton, N.Y.). THE PYTHIA'S DRUNKEN SONG THOMAS CARLYLE'S SARTOR RESARTUS AND THE STYLE PROBLEM IN GERMAN IDEALIST PHILOSOPHY by JERRY A. DIBBLE • 1978 MARTIN US NIJHOFF THE HAGUE! BOSTON! LONDON © 1978 by Martinus Nijhojj; The Hague, Netherlands Solkover reprint of the hardcover 1s t edition 1978 All rights reserved, including the right to translate or to reproduce this book or parts thereof in any form ISBN-13: 978-90-247-2011-8 e-ISBN-13: 978-94-009-9672-4 001: 10.1007/978-94-009-9672-4 CONTENTS Acknowledgements VII I. THE HISTORICAL BACKGROUND OF Sartor Resartus I. The Kantian Compromise 7 2. Kant, Fichte, and the Dilemma of Idealism 15 II. Sartor Resartus AND THE HISTORICITY OF IDEALISM 35 I. The Style of Dogmatic Idealism 37 2. Carlyle's "British Reader" and the Structure of Sartor Resartus 50 III. CARLYLE AND HEGEL 57 List of Texts Cited 76 Index 77 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I should like to thank Stanford University and the German Academic Exchange Service for research grants which made this study possible, and Professor Helmut Bonheim and the staff of the Englisches Seminar, Universitat zu K61n, for their unfailing hospitality during the academic year 1967-68. I also owe my thanks to Professors Lucio Ruotolo, Kurt Muller-Vollmer, and David Halliburton of Stanford University, without whose interest and encouragement the study would never have been begun, and to my former colleagues, Professors David Erdman, Thomas Maresca, and Gerald Nelson of SUNY Stony Brook for their patient and helpful criticism of the finished manuscript. Most of all, however, I am indebted to Barbara, Sam, and my parents, for their love, unceasing good cheer, and loyal support in the face of adversity. Portions of this study originally appeared in the pages of the Bulletin of the New York Public Library and Texas Studies in Language and Literature, to whose editors I am grateful for permission to reprint them here. Clarence Center, New York May; 1977 CHAPTER I THE HISTORICAL BACKGROUND OF SARTOR RESARTUS He is writing a book on metaphysics, and is really cut out for it; the clearness with which he thinks he understands things and his total inability to express what little he knows will make his fortune as a philosopher. W.K. Clifford These men, dissimilar in almost all else, agreed in being closet-students - secluded in a peculiar degree, by circumstances and character, from the business and intercourse of the world: and both were, through a large portion of their lives, regarded by those who took the lead in opinion (when they happened to hear of them) with feelings akin to contempt. But they were destined to renew a lesson given to mankind by every age, and always disregarded - to show that speculative philosophy, which to the superficial appears a thing so remote from the business of life and the outward interests of man, is in reality the thing on earth which most influences them, and in the long run overbears every other influence save those which it must itself obey. John Stuart Mill, On Bentham and Coleridge As Carlyle's friend John Sterling was the first to point out, the proper context for understanding the style of Sartor Resartus is not the swirl of contemporary events, important as they are to the work itself, but the dilemma of serious literature in an age of radical dissent and impending social disorganization. For Carlyle, indeed, the question of style was so closely tied to the problematic character of the age that he never discussed one without reference to the other, and rarely mentioned either without referring to the whole of the modem period - which he and other Victorians saw as a vast stretch of time between the Middle Ages and the present, between an idealized remote age of belief, authority, and social order and the crumbling precarious edge of an agonizing succession of epochs of progress and fragmentation. 2 HISTORICAL BACKGROUND OF SARTOR RESARTUS Thus, while present-day critics have made much of the differences between the styles of Carlyle and of Johnson, the picture of Johnson which emerges from Carlyle's Heroes and Hero-Worship and from his essay on Boswell's Life ofJ ohnson is not that of a stylistic antagonist; it is the portrait of a literary companion in arms, a lonely man fighting a rearguard action against spiritual emptiness and the perennial problems of the modern man of letters - incipient poverty, commercial pressure, and audience prejudice born of confusion and uncertainty. Carlyle recognizes that Johnson's "wondrous buckram style," based on literary values "long since obsolete," is radically different from his own; his interest, however, is in the historical environment that gave rise to the two styles, and that, as Carlyle describes it, remains exactly the same: It was a wholly divided age, that of Johnson. Unity existed nowhere in its Heaven or in its Earth. Society through every fibre, was rent asunder: all things, it was then becoming visible, but could not then be understood, were moving onwards, with an impulse received ages before, yet now first with a decisive rapidity, towards that great chaotic gulf, where, whether in the shape of French Revolutions, Reform Bills, or what shape soever, bloody or bloodless, the descent and engulfment assume, we now see them weltering and boiling.' For Carlyle, the impulse which had begun the engulfment of social order was clearly skepticism. And in the wake of skepticism, as he saw it, had followed a host of other social and intellectual evils: wonder and awe before the things of the world had degenerated into lifeless materialism; communal purpose and religious feeling had given way to mutual distrust and the anxiety of self-consciousness; the stability of monarchy, once revered, had been threatened, in one instance altogether replaced, by the anarchy of an uncontrolled, unenlightened democracy. Nor had the writer and his profession escaped their share of the general blight; for where literature had once pleased by its power to express the beliefs men held in common, it now lay languishing and paralyzed under a night of dissension and unbelief. Like most nights identified by Victorian writers, however, this one, too, was not without the glimmer of a new day. And the horizon on which Carlyle believed he could detect the first rays of the coming dawn was - Germany. Carlyle had read little of Kant, probably no more than the first 150 pages of the Kritik der reinen Vernunft. But he knew enough about the principal ideas of the critical philosophy to see clearly its connection with the resurgence of German literature - a literature, as he described it, of such "calm, harmonious strength" that it had not only managed to absorb into 1 Thomas Carlyle, Works, ed. H.D. Traill (New York, 1904), XXVIII, 104. Subsequent references to Carlyle's essays are to this edition and will be cited parenthetically in the text. HISTORICAL BACKGROUND OF SARTOR RESARTUS 3 itself the truth of science and skepticism, but had done so without sacrificing the old nobleness and sense of purpose that had elsewhere been lost sight of 250 years before. Not surprisingly, then, we find the majority of Carlyle's energies during the period preceding the publication of Sartor Resartus (1833-34) absorbed by repeated attempts, in the form of essays, reviews, and translations, to bring home to his countrymen the achievement of deep thinking Germany. There were nevertheless certain inherent difficulties involved in trans planting the fragile bloom of German idealism to the soil of an England still very much under the influence of Locke and the Empiricist tradition. Although Kant's critical philosophy, for example, had been recognized and discussed in England since the year of Carlyle's birth, its reception had been almost universally poor. In part, the lukewarm English response was attributable to a series of incomplete and inadequate translations, which, coupled with some equally inadequate and wrong-headed commentaries, had conspired to produce a generally mistaken notion as to the value and purpose of the first Critique. A more significant obstacle, however, was the character of German idealism itself, a school of metaphysics which, as one reviewer of Coleridge's Statesman's Manual put it, was "foreign equally to our language and philosophy." Just how foreign can be gathered from the reviewers' response to Coleridge's philosophical writings. "Mystical lan guage," "metaphysical jargon," "incomprehensible metaphysics," "mys ticism," "German metaphysics, or metaphysics, if possible, still more obscure and unintelligible" - these and other such phrases appeared time after time, interrupted on rare occasions by a voice of reason, pointing out that it was less than fair to link Kant with Jacob B6hme and Swedenborg under the common heading of "mystics," or that there might be some reason to question the English notion, enshrined since the beginning of the eighteenth century, that any true philosophy ought to be firmly enough based on common sense to be readily understood by one's cook.2 The general state of affairs had not improved markedly ten years later, when Carlyle'S first essays began to appear in periodicals like the Edinburgh Review and the Foreign Review. If anything, it had worsened somewhat in response to social disturbances like those that led to Peterloo, and the general xenophobia occasioned by the talk of impending reform. (In 1828, for example, one translator felt it necessary to assure his readers that the critical philosophy had collapsed in the face of superior English moral training and that there was consequently "little reason to apprehend that 2 The reviews in which the quoted phrases and comments appear have been collected and reprinted, together with other early reviews of Coleridge's work, in J.R. de J. Jackson, ed., Coleridge: The Critical Heritage (New York, 1970). 4 HISTORICAL BACKGROUND OF SARTOR RESARTUS any evil can arise in our country from the principles or writings of Kant. ")3 It is to Carlyle's credit that he was among the first to confront publicly the problem of English hostility to German culture and to identify accurately the basic sources of the antagonism. Part of the problem, he notes in "The State of German Literature" (r827), resulted from notions of German literary production based on too much familiarity with Kotzebue and the sensational horrors of Gothic fiction and on too little knowledge of the work of writers such as Goethe, Schiller, and Novalis. Partly responsible, too, are prevailing conceptions of the Germans as semi-barbarous, rude, and delighting in coarse excitements - in short, generally wanting in tact and good taste. But most of all, the problem can be traced to the accusation of "mysticism," which as Carlyle rightly perceived was less an attempt at classification than a way of rejecting out of hand philosophical ideas uncongenial to one's own way of thinking. So long as one is dealing with the material and visible objects of everyday experience, Carlyle notes, the few obstacles to communication are easily overcome. It is a different matter, however, when one deals with an "invisible idea," especially when the idea expressed is different from, and perhaps even at war with, the ordinary conception of things; Here it will require long, patient and skilful effort, both from the writer and the reader, before the two can so much as speak together; before the former can make known to the latter, not how the matter stands, but even what the matter is, which they have to investigate in concert. He must devise new means of explanation, describe conditions of mind in which this invisible idea arises, the false persuasions that eclipse it, the false shows that may be mistaken for it, the glimpses of it that appear elsewhere; in short, strive by a thousand well-devised methods, to guide his reader up to the perception of it; in all which, moreover, the reader must faithfully and toilsomely cooperate with him, if any fruit is to come of their mutual endeavour. Should the latter take up his ground too early, and affirm to himself that now he has seized what he still has not seized; that this and nothing else is the thing aimed at by his teacher, the consequences are plain enough: disunion, darkness and contradiction between the two; the writer has written for another man, and this reader, after long provocation, quarrels with him finally, and quits him as a mystic. (XXVI, 72) Under the circumstances, the apologist for Germany was clearly in need of a special kind of rhetorical strategy, one which would work toward com munication and persuasion and yet, paradoxically, would also manage to delay full comprehension until the whole of the writer's message could be set fairly before his audience. Moreover, considering the strength of English prejudices against German metaphysics, even the most sensitive attempt at communication was bound to prove a failure unless a way could be found to 3 Charles Hodge, in the Preface to his translation of Phillip Albrecht Stapfer's Life ofK ant. Cited in Rene Wellek, Immanuel Kant in England (Princeton, 1931), p. 246.

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.