ebook img

The Politics of Beauty: A Study of Kant's Critique of Taste PDF

84 Pages·2022·2.565 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The Politics of Beauty: A Study of Kant's Critique of Taste

S h This Element examines the entirety of Kant’s Critique of Taste e l (in Part One of the Critique of Judgment) with particular l emphasis on its political and moral aims. Kant’s critical treatment of aesthetic judgment is both an extended theoretical response to influential predecessors and contemporaries, including Rousseau and Herder, and a practical intervention The Philosophy of in its own right meant to nudge history forward at a time of Immanuel Kant civilizational crisis. Attention to these themes helps resolve a number of puzzles, both textual and philosophic, including the normative force and meaning of judgments of taste and the relation between natural and artful beauty. T The Politics h e P o lit ics Of Beauty O f B e a u t y About the Series Series editors This Cambridge Elements series provides Desmond Hogan an extensive overview of Kant’s philosophy Princeton and its impact upon philosophy and University Susan Meld Shell philosophers. Distinguished Kant Howard Williams specialists provide an up-to-date summary University of Cardiff of the results of current research in their Allen Wood sserP y fields and give their own take on what Indiana tisre they believe are the most significant University vinU debates influencing research, drawing e g d original conclusions. irb m a C y b e n iln o d e h silb u P 0 4 8 6 2 0 9 0 0 1 8 7 9 /7 1 0 1 .0 1 /g ro .io d Cover image: Grafissimo/Getty //:sp IISSSSNN 22359174--93486214 ((opnrilnint)e) tth sse rP y tisre v in U e g d irb m a C y b e n iln o d e h silb u P 0 4 8 6 2 0 9 0 0 1 8 7 9 /7 1 0 1 .0 1 /g ro .io d //:sp tth ElementsinthePhilosophyofImmanuelKant editedby DesmondHogan PrincetonUniversity HowardWilliams UniversityofCardiff AllenWood IndianaUniversity THE POLITICS OF BEAUTY ’ A Study Of Kants Critique Of Taste Susan Meld Shell sse rP y Boston College tisre v in U e g d irb m a C y b e n iln o d e h silb u P 0 4 8 6 2 0 9 0 0 1 8 7 9 /7 1 0 1 .0 1 /g ro .io d //:sp tth UniversityPrintingHouse,CambridgeCB28BS,UnitedKingdom OneLibertyPlaza,20thFloor,NewYork,NY10006,USA 477WilliamstownRoad,PortMelbourne,VIC3207,Australia 314–321,3rdFloor,Plot3,SplendorForum,JasolaDistrictCentre, NewDelhi–110025,India 103PenangRoad,#05–06/07,VisioncrestCommercial,Singapore238467 CambridgeUniversityPressispartoftheUniversityofCambridge. ItfurtherstheUniversity’smissionbydisseminatingknowledgeinthepursuitof education,learning,andresearchatthehighestinternationallevelsofexcellence. www.cambridge.org Informationonthistitle:www.cambridge.org/9781009011808 DOI:10.1017/9781009026840 ©SusanMeldShell2022 Thispublicationisincopyright.Subjecttostatutoryexception andtotheprovisionsofrelevantcollectivelicensingagreements, noreproductionofanypartmaytakeplacewithoutthewritten permissionofCambridgeUniversityPress. Firstpublished2022 AcataloguerecordforthispublicationisavailablefromtheBritishLibrary. ISBN978-1-009-01180-8Paperback ISSN2397-9461(online) ISSN2514-3824(print) sse CambridgeUniversityPresshasnoresponsibilityforthepersistenceoraccuracyof rP URLsforexternalorthird-partyinternetwebsitesreferredtointhispublication y tisrev anddoesnotguaranteethaactcaunraytecoonrteapntproonpsruiacthe.websitesis,orwillremain, in U e g d irb m a C y b e n iln o d e h silb u P 0 4 8 6 2 0 9 0 0 1 8 7 9 /7 1 0 1 .0 1 /g ro .io d //:sp tth The Politics Of Beauty AStudyOfKant’sCritiqueOfTaste ElementsinthePhilosophyofImmanuelKant DOI:10.1017/9781009026840 Firstpublishedonline:August2022 SusanMeldShell BostonCollege Authorforcorrespondence:SusanMeldShell,[email protected] Abstract:ThisElementexaminestheentiretyofKant’sCritiqueofTaste (inPartOneoftheCritiqueofJudgment)withparticularemphasisonits politicalandmoralaims.Kant’scriticaltreatmentofaestheticjudgment isbothanextendedtheoreticalresponsetoinfluentialpredecessors andcontemporaries,includingRousseauandHerder,andapractical interventioninitsownrightmeanttonudgehistoryforwardatatimeof civilizationalcrisis.Attentiontothesethemeshelpsresolveanumberof puzzles,bothtextualandphilosophic,includingthenormativeforce andmeaningofjudgmentsoftasteandtherelationbetweennatural andartfulbeauty. Keywords:Kant,beauty,aesthetics,politics,culture ©SusanMeldShell2022 ISBNs:9781009011808(PB),9781009026840(OC) sserP ISSNs:2397-9461(online),2514-3824(print) y tisre v in U e g d irb m a C y b e n iln o d e h silb u P 0 4 8 6 2 0 9 0 0 1 8 7 9 /7 1 0 1 .0 1 /g ro .io d //:sp tth Contents 1 Introduction:ReflectionandRevolution 1 2 TheElementsofBeauty 6 3 ArtisticBeauty 25 4 RhetoricandtheAntinomyofTaste 37 5 ThePoliticsofBeauty 50 6 SummaryandConclusion 68 References 70 sse rP y tisre v in U e g d irb m a C y b e n iln o d e h silb u P 0 4 8 6 2 0 9 0 0 1 8 7 9 /7 1 0 1 .0 1 /g ro .io d //:sp tth ThePoliticsOfBeauty 1 1Introduction:ReflectionandRevolution Althoughtherelationbetweenpoliticsandaestheticsisasubjectofperennial interest, the political implications of Kant’s Critique of Taste (in Part One of the Critique of Judgment) have not previously been the focus of a sustained study. That omission is all the more striking given Kant’s attention to the issue, from the 1760s onward, in response to Rousseau’s famous charge that progress in the arts and sciences was inimical to moral health and collective human happiness. Kant’s Critique of Taste, as I here argue, represents his definitiveresponsetoRousseau’schallenge.Idonotmeantoclaimthatthisis all that Kant’s Critique aims to accomplish; nor do I claim to offer a comprehensive account of his theory of taste. Still, a concentration on this neglected theme has two distinct advantages: first, it enables one to better locateKant’saestheticworkwithinthelargerpoliticalprogramhelaidoutin the years following the French Revolution, from the Critique of Judgment (1790) to the later Metaphysics of Morals (1798). Second, it brings new clarity to two much-contested interpretive issues: namely, the relation betweenaestheticjudgmentsofnaturalandartisticbeautyandthenormative force and significance of aesthetic judgment as such. Despitethe profusionofinsightful scholarly workonKant’saesthetics and politics, little has been written on their interrelation. The dramatic exception that proves the rule is Hannah Arendt, whose Lectures on Kant’s Political Philosophy replaces his most overtly “political” philosophic work, namely, the Doctrine of Right (which she dismisses as a product of senility), with his critiqueofaestheticjudgment,whichshetendstoreadasthepoliticalworkthat sserP Kantwouldorshouldhavewritten(Arendt,1992).Tobesure,thereareobvious ytisre practicalimplicationsofKant’saesthetictheorytowhichhehimselfexplicitly vin points,andthathavebeendulynotedintheliterature.Theseinclude,butarenot U eg limited to, the “discipline” of weaning us from our dependence on crudely d irbm sensualpleasureandmakingournaturaldrivetosociabilitymoredecorousand a C y “civilized,” with implications for political life that are seemingly obvious. At b en thesametime,thepreciserelationbetweenKant’saestheticsandhispractical iln o d philosophymoregenerallyisoneoftheoutstandingunsettledscholarlyissues e h silb currentlybeingdebated,withsomeclaimingthatthenormativebasisofKantian u P 0 aestheticsisultimatelymoralandotherstreatingsuchconcernsasincidentalto 4 86 Kant’scentralargument. 2 0 90 Inconflating,indefianceofKant’sowntext,the“commonsense”ofaesthetic 0 1 87 judgmentwithonedirectlypertinenttopolitics,Arendt(1992:64–72)mayhave 9 /710 beenrespondingtoWalterBenjamin’sfamousjuxtapositionoffascism,under- 1 .0 1 stood as the aestheticization of politics, and communism understood as the /g ro .io d //:sp tth 2 ThePhilosophyofImmanuelKant politicizationofaesthetics.Ashe writesat theend of “Art in the AgeofIts TechnicalReproducibility”:“‘Fiatars–pereatmundus’,saysFascism,and, asMarinettiadmits,expectswartosupplytheartisticgratificationofasense perceptionthathasbeenchangedbytechnology....Thisisthesituationof politics which Fascism is rendering aesthetic. Communism responds by politicizing art” (Benjamin, 1968:242). Arendt had good reason to seek a more moderate, republican alternative to these two horns, and evidently thought she had found it in the unwritten Kantian text she attempted to compose. But there are alternative political lessons to be drawn from Kant’sCritiqueofTastethatarebothtruertoKant’smeaningandultimately more compelling, as I will argue, than those drawn either by Arendt or by somelater,moretextuallyfaithfulscholars.1 The sections that make up this study aim to chart the political conse- quences Kant hoped would flow from a critical doctrine of taste. (I mainly exclude Kant’s treatment of the sublime, on whose political implications much has indeed been written, which is only indirectly the object of judg- ments of “taste” – e.g., in “beautiful” representations of the sublime.) Section2(“TheElementsofBeauty”[CJ#1–40])takesuptheearliestand mostcommonlystudiedsectionsoftheCritiqueofTaste,includingboththe “deduction” of taste at #38 and Kant’s discussion of our “empirical” and “moral” interests in the beautiful. Sections 3 and 4 (“Artistic Beauty” [CJ #41–52] and “Rhetoric and the Antinomy of Taste” [CJ #53–57]) consider Kant’s treatment of fine art in greater detail. Rather than either downplay these sections (like Guyer in his earlier work) or make it the sse central focus of Kant’s doctrine of taste (like Crawford), I argue that rP y judgments of artistic beauty make a distinctive normative claim, requiring tisre itsownindependent“deduction,”andthatsuchtaste(unlikeatasteforfree v inU beautiesofnature)developsonlyunderspecificsocialconditions.Assuch, e g dirb judgments of artistic beauty have a normative character that is distinctly ma their own (and hence not exhausted by Kant’s earlier deduction of pure C yb e judgmentsofnaturalbeauty).Section5(“ThePoliticsofBeauty”[CJ#58– n iln 60]) discusses the final sections of the Critique of Taste, including both o deh beautyas“symbol”andthepeculiarrelation,asitseemstoKantduringthe silbu earlymonthsoftheFrenchRevolution,betweentasteandthesolutiontothe P 0 4 problemofestablishingastate. 8 6 2 0 Insum:thisismainlyastudyofPartOneoftheCritiqueofJudgment(minus 9 0 01 Kant’s treatment of the sublime). Unlike other such studies, mine especially 8 7 9 /7 focusesonwhatKantaimedtoaccomplishpracticallyandpoliticallythrough 1 0 1 .0 1 /gro 1 Forinstructivesuggestions,however,seeClewis(2009),Dobe(2018),andStoner(2019). .io d //:sp tth ThePoliticsOfBeauty 3 suchacritique(insofarasthiscanbeestablishedonthebasisofthetextitself). Moreover, unlike many who have touched on the latter topic,2 I try to take seriouslythemoralandpoliticalharms,aswellasbenefits,thatflowfromthe advanceofcivilizationandculture.Sounderstood,Kant’sCritiqueofTaste,as Iwillargue,isitselfapractical/politicalinterventionmeanttoredirecttastein amorepositivecivilandmoraldirection.Idonotclaimthistobetheprimary aimoftheCritiqueofTaste;noriswhatfollowsintendedasacomprehensive studyofKant’saccountofbeauty.Still,asIhopetoshow,viewingtheCritique of Taste through such a lens not only reveals a degree of comprehensive philosophic rigor and coherence not otherwise easily appreciated; it also suggests that Kant’s Critique of Taste may harbor untapped resources for understandingandimprovingourowncivicandaestheticculture.3 This study is also distinguished from many others4 in claiming that the normativestandardoftastemaybeeitherconstitutiveorregulative,depending onwhethernaturalorartisticbeautyismainlyatissue.Theconstitutivestandard applies to “pure judgments of taste” that presuppose a capacity shared by all humanbeingscapableofmakingobjectiveepistemicjudgments.Theregulative standard, by way of contrast, mainly applies, as I will argue, to a taste for exemplaryworksofart.Unlikethecapacityforandexerciseofpurejudgments of natural beauty, the latter sort of taste must be cultivated, a process that is partly dependent on the progress of civilization and that gives rise to an “antinomy” that must be critically resolved if taste is to realize, rather than frustrate,itsmorallypreparatorymission.Moreover,unlikepurejudgmentsof tasteforfreebeauties(ofnature),whichonlyconcernthefreeplayofimagin- sse ationandunderstanding,tasteintheregulativesensecruciallyinvolvesreason rP y aswell.5Italsopresupposesa“creative”expansionoftheimagination(beyond tisre thatinvolvedinpurejudgmentsoftaste)thatgivesrisetobothnewopportun- v in U ities for spiritual enlivening (e.g., through the art of poetry) and new dangers e g dirb (e.g.,throughthemisuseofrhetorictobeguileratherthanelevate). m a C yb 2 Forexample,Sweet(2013),Murray(2015);butcompareKalar(2017)andOtabi(2018). en 3 Considerinthis regardboth ClementGreenberg’schampioningofabstract expressionismon ilno putatively(andfalsely)“Kantian”grounds,andArthurDanto’scounter-championingof“con- deh ceptualism”ongroundsthatweremoreKantianthanhehimselfevidentlyrecognized.Onthese silb andothermisappropriationsofKant’saestheticswithinthecontemporaryartworld,seeCazeaux u P (2021),Guyer(2021),andCostello(2007). 0 48 4 “Regulative” readings include, for example, Crawford (1974), Longuenesse (2006), and 6 20 Matherne(2019).Forsomealternativecombined readingsseeSaville(1987),Kemal(1992), 9 00 and Dobe (2010). According to Guyer (1979:327) and Stoner (2019) Kant leaves the matter 1 87 unsettled. 9/7 5 Thesignificanceofthisaddition(and henceanessential difference between thetwo sortsof 1 01 aestheticjudgment)tendstobeoverlooked;anexceptionisCrowther(2010:142)whoneglects, .01 however,thecontinuingimportanceoftherelationbetweenimaginationandunderstanding(as /gro wellasreason)injudgmentsoffineart. .io d //:sp tth 4 ThePhilosophyofImmanuelKant The sections that follow take their initial bearings from the oft noted but insufficiently pondered coincidence of the Storming of the Bastille in July1789–alongwithitsimmediatepoliticalcontextandaftermath–andthe months in which Kant completed the Critique of Judgment, installments of which he sent off to the printer between January and March 1790. As John Zammito (1992) has convincingly argued, building on the earlier work of GiorgioTonelli(1966),muchofthelattersectionsofPartOne,aswellasthe bulk of Part Two, were written after May 1789 and some, including the final version of the “Dialectic of Aesthetic Judgment” and a greatly expanded concluding section of Part Two, were not completed until early 1790. By May 1789, much had already happened in France, including the publication of Abbé Sieyès’ influential pamphlet What Is the Third Estate? in January of that year, followedbythe king’s call forelections ofdelegates tothe Estates- General(whichhadnotmetforoveracentury)andtheParisriotsinApril;May and June witnessed the meeting of the Estates-General followed by its trans- formation,undertheself-declaredauthorityoftheThirdEstate,intoaNational AssemblywhichLouisXVIofficiallyrecognizedinlateJune.Formaladoption by the Assembly of the Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen would follow in August. By December 1789, the Assembly had appropriated thepropertyoftheChurchforthenation’suse,introducedtheassignat(aform ofcurrencybasedonthevalueofconfiscatedChurchproperty),andopenedup publicofficetoProtestants. Kant’s avid interest in revolutionary developments in France is common knowledge.Accordingtoonecontemporaryreport,hewassocaughtupthathe sse “wouldhavewalkedformilestogetthemail”(Kuehn,2001:343);andhewould rP y lateradmit,inanunpublisheddraft,toa“feverish”enthusiasmforthelatestnews tisre (Refl-E19:604).ThatKanthadeventsinFrancefirmlyinmindashecompleted v in U PartTwooftheCritiqueofJudgmentisstronglysuggestedbyhisreference,in e g dirb a striking footnote, to the recent transformation of a great people into a state ma “organized”alongrepublicanlines,andcopyingalmostverbatimthewordsofthe C y b e Abbé, who writes in What Is the Third Estate? of the constitutional laws that n iln can emanate from the will of a nation as of two kinds, some “determin[ing] o deh the organization and the functions of the legislative body; the others ... the silbu organization and functions of the various executive bodies” (Sieyès, 2002:53). P 0 4 Itseemslikely,then,asZammito(1992:334)argues,thattheFrenchRevolution 8 6 20 contributedtoageneralreorientationinKant’shistorical,political,andreligious 9 0 0 1 thinkingtowhichthethirdCritiquebearssignalwitness. 8 7 9 /7 In Part One of the Critique of Judgment, the evidence is admittedly less 1 0 1.0 conclusive and more subtle, as we shall see. But, in any case, the political 1 /gro dimensions of Kant’s Critique of Taste were not limited to, or bounded by, .io d //:sp tth

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.