ebook img

The Political Economy of Death Penalty Abolition PDF

24 Pages·2015·0.63 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The Political Economy of Death Penalty Abolition

Pulling Leviathan’s Teeth – The Political Economy of Death Penalty Abolition Jerg Gutmann* Abstract It is not obvious why a state should willingly give up its harshest legal punishment and thus abandon an effective instrument at the disposal of politicians to deter the opposition. Until now, the social science literature has explained the fact that some states abolish capital punishment while others retain it by drawing on differing values held by their respective citizens and politicians. In this article, I propose and empirically test a political economy model in which politicians are more likely to give up the death penalty if it is either not of political value to them or if the process of abolition serves as a costly signal during periods of transition. The hypotheses derived from this political economy model are tested against competing cultural and socio-economic explanations from the literature. The results of a stratified Cox model support the argument of signaling, but also the independence of the judiciary can promote abolition of the death penalty. Keywords: Capital punishment, death penalty abolition, political economy, positive constitutional economics, spatial policy diffusion. JEL Classification: K14, K42, P16, P26, P48, Z18. * Institute of Law & Economics, University of Hamburg, Johnsallee 35, 20148 Hamburg, Germany. Tel.: +49(0)-40-42838-3040, e-mail: [email protected]. The author thanks Mila Versteeg and Tom Ginsburg for sharing their respective data on the constitutional prohibition of the death penalty. Helpful comments and suggestions came from Agnes Strauß, Dalia Fadly, Dina El-Sayed, Jiwon S. Lee, Konstantinos Pilpilidis, Marwa El-Abhar, Rola El-Kabani, Stefan Voigt and Teresa Wittgenstein. I. INTRODUCTION Constitutional Political Economy, the study of the choice of rules within which actions of representatives of the nation-state are taken, has grown significantly in scope and importance over the last decades. Many of these studies are concerned with the allocation of competences among political actors, e.g., by installing federalism, judicial independence or a particular form of government (see Voigt 2011 for an overview). Less attention has, however, been paid to politicians’ self-commitment regarding the domestic use of force. Given that economists work under the premise that politicians are primarily motivated by self-interest, this neglect is surprising. Political agents are assumed to maximize the rents they can appropriate in office. Yet, in practice politicians seem to willingly constrain themselves to not use instruments that could limit entry into the political market. Their use could prolong incumbents’ expected tenure and increase their discretion to extract political rents. The death penalty is one such instrument with the potential to deter or eliminate political opponents. This article aims for explaining the abolition of the death penalty as a result of rational political decision-making. The conditions under which politicians are willing to constrain themselves are a core research interest of constitutional economics (Buchanan 1975:13). Liberal political philosophy assigns a legal monopoly on violence to the state in order to overcome the ‘natural state,’ where all fight against all and life is ‘solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short.’ Thomas Hobbes, like many others, has argued for the necessity to vest sufficient power in Leviathan (i.e., the state) to keep its citizens in check. At the same time Hobbes (1651, Ch VI, n 3) recognized that politicians may not be interested in having sufficient power to oppress all citizens. Hence, politicians might benefit from credibly committing themselves to abstain from a set of possible actions. This can be interpreted as the proposal of a state with a powerful chief executive whose actions are reviewed by an equally strong and independent judiciary. Although the beneficial consequences of judicial independence have been demonstrated empirically (Feld and Voigt 2003; Voigt et al. 2015), it is still under-researched why only some countries implement such constraints on the executive.1 Understanding politicians’ differing incentives to abolish the death penalty could, more generally, add to an economic theory of political self-commitment. 1 Hayo and Voigt (2007, 2012) offer insights regarding both de jure and de facto judicial independence. More recently, others have studied the decision to adopt judicial review (Ginsburg and Versteeg 2014). From an economic point of view it is difficult to rationalize that the state should not use the death penalty, e.g., to deter murder and other severe crimes. Capital punishment might even be ‘morally required’ when its practice is expected to save more lives than are taken (Sunstein and Vermeule 2005). This argument by Sunstein and Vermeule is based on strictly utilitarian assumptions and uses the reasoning that there is no convincing justification for differentiating between the casualties caused by action or inaction of the state. Consequently, even the death penalty for juveniles would be justified, if it had a sufficient deterrent effect on deadly violence. Economists commonly label the death penalty as a form of regulation, comparable, e.g., to gun control, where the state also has to take decisions over life and death. The principal difference is that the government can decide a specific person’s fate when it applies the death penalty. This suggests—at least within a utilitarian framework—that the need to abolish capital punishment can be primarily explained by fear of its abuse. Although extralegal instruments like intimidation, torture and murder always constitute an alternative, politicians in many countries recurrently rely on the justice system―including capital punishment―to dispose of defiant political activists, journalists and political opponents. Modern-day examples of this practice are abundant and range from Belarus over Tunisia to the Sudan. Two of the more extreme cases are Egypt where after a military coup in 2013 hundreds of members of the Muslim Brotherhood were sentenced to death and North Korea with its excessive use of capital punishment even for minor forms of political dissidence. Both have been criticized by human rights organizations for disregarding international law and not facilitating fair trials. Even when capital punishment is mostly applied to non-political crimes, it can be of value to politicians, as argued by Schabas (2013:219) in the case of Iran: “Regardless of the crimes for which it is imposed, [it] is a message of terror targeted at those tempted to resist the regime.” Furthermore, the death penalty may be of value to the government of a country where it is not regularly applied, as long as its imposition can be credibly threatened. The general legality of the death penalty consequently also plays a role in regimes that are sometimes labeled de facto abolitionist, in the sense that they have not carried out executions for at least ten years.2 Although the primary purpose of the death penalty is the deterrence of severe crimes, mere differences in the evaluation of its effectiveness or different preferences for the severity of 2 The difference between de facto and de jure abolition can be though of as that between policies and institutions. Only the latter are durable and shape the future distribution of de facto political power (Acemoglu and Robinson 2006:177). Hence, this study focuses on the legal status of capital punishment. criminal punishment are questionable and unsatisfactory explanations for the varying legal status of the death penalty in countries around the world.3 Preferable to such idiosyncratic explanations would be a political economy model that systematically explains why politicians have a differing willingness to or interest in abolishing capital punishment. It is argued here that the abolition of the death penalty is largely motivated by the incentives set by specific political institutions. In some political systems leaders are more able to or dependent on threatening the use of lethal force than in others. While it would be without significant policy relevance if one could identify the country characteristics that are correlated with values that encourage or discourage the use of capital punishment, it is highly relevant to determine the political institutions that incentivize governments to commit themselves to relinquishing the domestic use of targeted violence―at least that which is exercised via the judicial system. The empirical literature on the determinants of death penalty abolition is to this point dominated by contributions from political scientists (McGann and Sandholtz 2012; Neumayer 2008), sociologists (Kent 2010; Mathias 2013) and legal scholars (Greenberg and West 2008). Among these, Neumayer (2008) is the most encompassing analysis of the relevance of political factors for death penalty abolition. Neumayer estimates a number of Cox regression models for a sample of up to 151 countries. His results show the importance of political and legal factors for abolition, whereas economic and cultural country characteristics appear to play no considerable role. Nevertheless, from an economic point of view, Neumayer’s theoretical model is not very useful, as it draws heavily on differences in values as explanatory factors, but almost completely ignores the incentives of rational politicians. Yet, virtually the entire empirical literature could be criticized on these grounds. The only contributions to this body of literature from an explicitly economic perspective are two articles by Mulligan et al. (2004) and Mulligan and Shleifer (2005), which deal with the legal status of the death penalty as just one aspect of the broader questions they are addressing. The research question of Mulligan et al. (2004) is whether more democratic countries systematically use different public policies than less democratic ones. Mulligan et al. find little to no effect of democracy on many economic and social policy variables. In contrast, a set of policies identified by Tullock (1987) as regulating the winning and maintaining of public office―including the legality of capital punishment―is significantly 3 Particularly in light of the fact that in most countries a strong majority of the population are in favor of the death penalty (Hobson 2013:36). On a more general level, already Stigler and Becker (1977) have argued that drawing on preferences or values to explain differences in behavior ultimately does not contribute to understanding or predicting human action. more likely to be employed by less democratic regimes. While this study provides at least a crude political economy model of abolition, the results of such a cross-sectional analysis with only some generic control variables can provide at most a preliminary evaluation of the issue at hand. Mulligan and Shleifer (2005) conduct a similar analysis to test whether larger countries are more likely to introduce regulation, as they face increasing economies of scale in regulatory policies. Although Mulligan and Shleifer cannot provide any evidence of these suspected increasing economies of scale, they argue that death penalty administration is a regulatory attempt to solve social problems using methods involving significant fixed costs. Again, a simple cross-sectional regression analysis backs up their theoretical conjectures that democracies and smaller countries are more likely to do away with capital punishment. To sum up: the empirical economic literature on the abolition of the death penalty suffers from clear methodological shortcomings and provides only ad hoc-models of potential determinants. In contrast, the recent contributions from other social sciences tend to use more advanced estimation techniques, but they essentially explain abolition patterns by different preferences for the death penalty. Here I combine the advantages of both strands of literature and extend upon their contributions. A political economy model of the determinants of capital punishment is formulated and stratified Cox regression models are estimated for up to 151 countries over the period from 1950 to 2012 in order to test the generated hypotheses. This study is also the first to take into account the organization of the judiciary and the political role of the military as determinants of abolition. Aside from testing an improved political economy model with a more appropriate estimation technique, this paper also uses more and higher quality data on the legal status of the death penalty, relative to all previous studies. The results indicate that abolition is used as a costly political signal in periods of transition, but also the independence of the judiciary is relevant for the decision to abolish. In the following Section, theoretical arguments regarding the systematic determinants of the abolition of the death penalty are introduced and critically discussed. Underlying this theoretical model is the assumption of rational, self-interested and utility-maximizing political actors. Section III introduces the data on the death penalty and discusses issues in the operationalization of its legal status. Some stylized facts are presented. Section IV presents the independent variables employed to test our hypotheses and their data sources. Bivariate relationships are discussed to give an indication of what countries have abolished capital punishment to this day. Section V presents the estimation technique for the survival model and critically discusses the regression results. Finally, Section VI concludes. II. A POLITICAL ECONOMY MODEL OF ABOLITION If politicians were social welfare-maximizers, it could be expected that, ceteris paribus, the death penalty is abolished first wherever states have the least resources, e.g., in terms of an effective and impartial judiciary, to apply capital punishment responsibly. High-income countries with a high-quality justice system should then be the last countries to abolish the death penalty. However, if politicians are assumed to be opportunistic and motivated by rent extraction, their interest in the legal status of capital punishment is primarily linked to its relevance for the duration of their stay in office. Moreover, the appeal and effectiveness of this instrument depends on a set of―mostly political―country characteristics. The following theoretical arguments fall into two main groups: (1) country characteristics that determine the relative attractiveness of the death penalty as a political instrument and (2) situations in which countries can use the abolition of the death penalty as a costly signal to the political opposition or the general population. A country’s political regime type may be crucial for the abolition of capital punishment. In democracies political power is allocated via contested elections. Dictators, in contrast, face only a revolution constraint, which forces them to make concessions or use tools of repression against their citizens. Dictators have to repress opposition and buy loyalty as long as they are unwilling to democratize, i.e., to commit to costly pro-citizen policies (Acemoglu and Robinson 2006). The threat of capital punishment is one of the more moderate (and thus less costly) tools at the command of an autocrat to deter opposition to their rule—at least when compared to extrajudicial killings and other severe violations of basic human rights. Lawful measures against opponents are perceived as more legitimate4 and may allow for economizing on the use of force that is necessary to maintain political power (Moustafa and Ginsburg 2008). Thus, it can be hypothesized that democratic regimes, because they are less reliant on the suppression of citizens to avert revolutions, are more likely than autocrats willing to give up the death penalty. Yet, also autocrats will not always resort to repression. The abolition of the death penalty is an institutional change that reallocates de jure and in consequence future de facto political power to citizens, although less so than democratization. Once the political regime credibly commits to refrain from the use of drastic measures against opponents, citizens will be able to organize future collective action against the government at a lower cost. Analogous to what 4 Berggren et al. (2015), e.g., provide evidence that legitimacy may allow large governments to spend resources with more discretion. has been argued in Acemoglu et al. (2010), where the elite forms an over-sized military in order to prevent a military coup, the autocrat may avoid a revolution in the present by making future revolutions less costly. Consequently it can even be in the interest of an autocrat to self-commit to not using capital punishment, given that this is cheaper than additional concessions, stronger repression or full-scale democratization (see Acemoglu et al. 2000 for the relative attractiveness of these three types of strategies). Expecting all nondemocratic countries to be equally prone to repressing their citizens might be too simplistic. Military dictatorships are the regime type under which the use of the death penalty to safeguard political power may be most tempting. It has been noted that military regimes have a comparative advantage at repression when compared to civilian autocratic regimes (Wintrobe 1998:56). South America provides for a number of examples, including Argentina in 1971 and 1976 as well as Brazil in 1969, where military governments systematically used the death penalty for political crimes as an instrument of suppression. A country’s regime type is, of course, not the only political institution of relevance. Previous studies on the determinants of abolition have ignored that it is not politicians themselves, but judges who have the power to hand out a death sentence. It is thus important for politicians to be able to exercise control over critical judicial decisions. With a largely independent judiciary the threat to use the death penalty against political opponents is considerably less credible. Judicial independence may consequently increase the probability of abolition, given that it decreases the relative attractiveness of capital punishment as a political instrument. If autocrats grant comprehensive independence to judges in order to enhance their legitimacy, they have no political use for capital punishment anymore. Again, Argentina and Brazil provide insightful examples. While political cases in Brazil were routed through the judiciary, which was loyal to the regime, dictators in Argentina had to make more use of extrajudicial violence (Pereira 2008). Nevertheless, both military regimes maintained the use of capital punishment, but its abolition may have been more realistic in Argentina. Irrespective of the independence of a country’s regular courts, politicians often face the opportunity to bring civilians before a military court or some other specialized court. This is a popular practice among dictators and allows them to create a largely independent judiciary for regular cases without completely giving up the judicial system as an instrument to deter opponents. That practice is described in detail by Moustafa (2008) for the case of Egypt. In line with the above argument on judicial independence in regular courts, politicians are expected to be more willing to abolish the death penalty when specialized courts do not exist. Aside from political regime types and institutional design features that make the death penalty a differently valuable political instrument, there are also more transient motives for its abolition. During episodes of turmoil, instability and political change the legal abolition of capital punishment can be employed as a costly signal that the political regime will not make use of force to preserve its interests. It has been argued here that abolition can reduce the risk of a revolution in the short-run and thereby delay full-scale democratization. However, a swift prohibition of capital punishment and other repressive instruments can as well signal the seriousness of reform efforts to transfer political power to the majority of citizens after a dictatorship has ended. At the same time, abolition can reduce the risk of backsliding into autocratic forms of governance by making the use of suppressive political instruments more costly to future rulers. The abolition of capital punishment can thus not only be expected in place of, but also during and following democratic reforms. Futamura and Bernaz (2014:5) go so far as to argue that it is democratization and not necessarily democracy that drives abolition. Furthermore, they emphasize the role of post-conflict peacebuilding as a different form of transition process driving the decision to abolish. Finally, independent of domestic politics, different mechanisms of spatial policy diffusion described in Elkins and Simmons (2005) may apply to death penalty abolition. The dispersion of abolition alters reputational payoffs from (not) abolishing the death penalty and the refusal of abolitionist countries to extradite criminals wanted for trial on a capital charge may directly incentivizes countries to abolish. Both politicians and civil societies in ‘nearby’ abolitionist countries may exert pressure on leaders of retentionist countries to abolish the death penalty or at least limit its use and improve the procedural standards in its application (Schabas 2002). As with other efforts to promote the rule of law and substantive legal standards worldwide, most of the pressure to abolish appears to come from democracies. Furthermore, countries may learn from the practices and experiences of other countries, particularly when the information is readily available and easily transferable, or they simply emulate the policies of other countries. All theoretical arguments about spatial dependence suggest a positive effect of abolition on the propensity of other countries to abolish. The data do, however, not allow testing the alternative theories against each other. III. THE LEGAL STATUS OF THE DEATH PENALTY International law distinguishes two types of death penalties: (1) those for ordinary crimes and (2) those for exceptional crimes, such as high treason, or crimes committed under exceptional circumstances, e.g., in wartime. The International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR) restricts the application of capital punishment to the ‘most serious crimes’. Its Second Optional Protocol commits signatories to abolish the death penalty, but allows for a reservation regarding war crimes. The information on the legal status of the death penalty by Amnesty International (2014) is compiled in accordance with these categories. A country is coded as “retentionist”, “abolitionist for ordinary crimes” or “abolitionist for all crimes”. In line with most of the previous empirical literature, abolition in practice is not considered as a separate category here, as it does not constitute a credible commitment to not applying the death penalty. Numerous countries have restarted executions after being de facto abolitionist for many years. Recent examples include Gambia (after over 25 years) and India (after 8 years), both of which restarted executions in 2012. If a country does not carry out the death penalty, but explicitly leaves this door open―while its courts possibly even hand out new death sentences―the legality of capital punishment can still limit political competition. One limitation of the data by Amnesty International has been ignored in previous empirical studies: its neglect of the fact that a number of countries have reinstated capital punishment by law. Together with the invention of a category ‘abolitionist in practice’, this omission could be interpreted as a window-dressing of the abolitionist movement’s success story. For lack of a systematic collection of cases in which the death penalty was reintroduced by law, this data was manually coded for the period following 1950, primarily based on Hood and Hoyle (2015), and cross-referenced with other sources.5 Gathering such information is of vital importance: First, it adds cases of abolition that have to be considered as events in the empirical analysis. Second, it determines when we should recognize countries to be at risk of abolition. Obviously, a country cannot abolish the death penalty during periods when it is already prohibited. Furthermore, a country’s baseline hazard of abolition may be different, after it has already abolished and reinstated the death penalty, relative to a country that has no previous experience with abolition. All of these aspects have been neglected in previous empirical studies. A final value added is the more precise measurement of the influence that abolitionist countries may have on the decisions made by other countries. 5 The codings are provided in Appendix A together with the data by Amnesty International (2014). Amnesty International (2014) reports the legal status of the death penalty in 198 countries, not all of which are members of the United Nations. By the end of 2012, 93 (47%) of those countries were retentionist and another seven (4%) had abolished the death penalty only for ordinary crimes. Although this situation is far from indicating the end of capital punishment, the change relative to 1950 is remarkable. Back then, just nine countries had no death penalty and twelve more had it abolished for ordinary crimes only. Almost 30% of the countries that abolished capital punishment for all crimes between 1950 and 2012 were first abolitionist for ordinary crimes only. There are no reports of cases in which a country abolished the death penalty within the same year for ordinary crimes and then for all crimes. Additional variation in the legal status of capital punishment results from the nine countries that have reinstated capital punishment since 1950―Argentina reintroduced it even twice. Four of these nine countries remain retentionist to this day, suggesting that abolition is not a one-way street. Another measure for the legality of the death penalty is based on its constitutional status. This data was collected in the Comparative Constitutions Project by Elkins et al. (2009). Law and Versteeg (2013) independently produced a similar indicator and cross-validated their codings with the data from Elkins et al. (2009). These conciliated codings are used in the following, with minor corrections, to determine the constitutional status of death penalty abolition. Law and Versteeg (2013) distinguish only between the constitutionally entrenched prohibition of capital punishment for all crimes and the absence of such a clause. Their data supports a claim by Hood and Hoyle (2009) that countries can make use of constitutional entrenchment to establish abolition permanently. None of the cases of death penalty reinstatement were in violation of the constitution and no country has ever removed a ban on capital punishment from its constitution. By 2012, 48 out of the 185 countries covered by the data had constitutionally prohibited capital punishment. This amounts to 26% of all countries or 55% of all fully abolitionist countries. IV. THE CAUSES OF ABOLITION: DATA AND BIVARIATE RELATIONSHIPS This section introduces an operationalization of the potential determinants of abolition and the estimation approach. Descriptive statistics provide a first impression of the association between presently abolitionist countries and our variables of interest. Data collected by Cheibub et al. (2010) and updated by Bormann and Golder (2013), is used to identify political regime types. Their categorization is collapsed into four categories represented by dummy variables: (1) parliamentary and mixed democracies, (2) presidential democracies, (3)

Description:
penalty. Keywords: Capital punishment, death penalty abolition, political economy, positive .. form of transition process driving the decision to abolish. Finally .. Laos. South Sudan. ―. Cameroon. Latvia. Spain. Canada. Lebanon.
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.