ebook img

The Physical Basis of The Direction of Time PDF

240 Pages·2001·8.651 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The Physical Basis of The Direction of Time

The Physical Basis of The Direction of Time Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg GmbH ONLINE LIBRARY Physics and Astronomy http://www.springer.de/phys/ H. Dieter Zeh The Physical Basis of The Direction of Time Fourth Edition With 34 Figures i Springer Professor Dr. H. Dieter Zeh Institut rur Theoretische Physik Universitat Heidelberg Philosophenweg 19 69120 Heidelberg, Germany Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data applied for. Die Deutsche Bibliothek -CIP-Einheitsaufnahme: Zeh, Heinz-Dieter: The physical basis of the direction of time I H. Dieter Zeh. - 4. ed. ISBN 978-3-540-42081-1 ISBN 978-3-540-38861-6 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-3-540-38861-6 This work is subject to copyright. All rights are reserved, whether the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broad- casting, reproduction on microfilm or in any other way, and storage in data banks. Duplication of this publication or parts thereof is permitted only under the provisions of the German Copyright Law of September 9, 1965, in its current version, and permission for use must always be obtained from Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg GmbH. Violations are liable for prosecution under the German Copyright Law. http://www.springer.de © Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 1989, 1992, 1999, 2001 Originally published by Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg New York in 2001 The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, etc. in this publication does not imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant pro tective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use. Typesetting: Data conversion by K. Mattes, Heidelberg Cover design: Erich Kirchner, Heidelberg Printed on acid-free paper SPIN 10837695 55/3141lba 5 4 3 2 1 0 Preface to the Fourth Edition The fourth edition contains again various revisions and updates throughout the whole book. There are many new comments, formulations and arguments, several new references, and three minor error corrections (regarding page 22, 112 and 146 of the third edition). This time I am grateful to David Atkinson (for a very useful discussion of radiation damping - Sect. 2.3), to Larry Schulman (for comments on the problem of simultaneous arrows of time - Sect. 3.1.2), and to Paul Sheldon (for a discussion of the compatibility of closed time-like curves with quantum theory - Chap. 1). The most efficient help came from John Free, who carefully edited the whole fourth edition (not only for matters of English language). Heidelberg, April 2001 H. D. Zeh Preface to the Third Edition The third (1999) edition of the Direction of Time offered far more revisions and additions than the second one in 1992. During the seven years in between, several fields of research related to the arrow of time had shown remarkable progress. For example, decoherence proved to be the most ubiquitous man ifestation of the quantum arrow, while articles on various interpretations of quantum theory (many of them with inbuilt time-asymmetric dynamical aspects) can and do now regularly appear in reputed physics journals. There fore, most parts of Chap. 4 were completely rewritten and some new sections added, while the second part of Chap. 3 was affected by these changes in or der to prepare for the discussion of measurements and dynamical maps within the framework of classical ensemble theory. However, all parts of the book have been revised, and some of them com pletely rewritten, whilst essentially maintaining the book's overall structure. Some of the new aspects of the third edition may be listed here: The Introduction now attempts to distinguish rigorously between those time asymmetries which still preserve dynamical determinism, and the various 'irreversiblities' (arrows of time proper) which are the subject of this book. In Chap. 2, the concept of forks of causality is contrasted to that of forks of indeterminism (to be used in Chaps. 3 and 4), while the treatment of the radiation reaction of a moving charge (Sect. 2.3) had to be updated. Sects. 3.2-3.4 have been given a new structure, while a discussion of semi groups and their physical meaning has been added to Sect. 3.4. In Chap. 4, only Sects. 4.1 and 4.5 (the former Sect. 4.3 on exponential decay) are not entirely new. In particular, there is now an extended separate Sect. 4.3 on decoherence. Sects. 4.4 (on quantum dynamical maps) and 4.6 (on the time arrow in various interpretations of quantum theory) have been added. In Chap. 5, the thermodynamics of acceleration is now presented separately (Sect. 5.2), while Sect. 5.3 on the expansion of the universe contains a discus sion of the consistency of cosmic two-time boundary conditions. The dynam ical interpretation of general relativity with its concept of intrinsic time is discussed in Sect. 5.4. Chap. 6 now covers various aspects of quantum cosmology and thus includes, as Sect. 6.1, the material of the former Sect. 5.2.2 on phase transitions of the vacuum with their consequences on entropy capacity. In Sect. 6.2 on quan tum gravity, emphasis is on timelessness, which is enforced by quantization of a reparametrization invariant theory. There is a new Sect.6.2.2 on the VIII Preface to the Third Edition emergence of classical time along the lines of the Tomonaga-Schwinger equa tion, while Sect. 6.2.3 describes some speculations on the impact of quantum cosmology on the concept of black holes and their thermodynamical proper ties. A numerical toy model has been appended after the Epilog in order to illustrate some typical arguments of statistical mechanics. I also hope that most disadvantages which had resulted from the fact that I previously had (very unfortunately) translated many parts of the first edition from the German lecture notes that preceded it (Zeh 1984), have now been overcome. Two new books on the arrow of time (Price 1996 and Schulman 1997) have recently appeared. They are both well written, and they discuss many important aspects of 'irreversible' physics in a consistent and illuminating manner - often nicely complementing each other as well as this book. However, I differ from their views in two respects: I regard gravity (not least its quantized form) as basic for the arrow of time, as I try to explain in Chaps. 5 and 6, and I do not think that the problem of quantum measurements can be solved by means of an appropriate final condition in a satisfactory way (see Footnote 4 of Chap. 4). I wish to thank Julian Barbour, Erich Joos, Claus Kiefer, Joachim Kupsch, York Ramachers, Huw Price, Fritz Rohrlich, Paul Sheldon and Max Tegmark for their comments on early versions of various parts of the manu script. Heidelberg, April 1999 H. D. Zeh Contents Introduction. . . . . . . . . 1 1. The Physical Concept of Time 9 2. The Time Arrow of Radiation 15 2.1 Retarded and Advanced Forms of the Boundary Value Problem . . . . . . 18 2.2 Thermodynamical and Cosmological Properties of Absorbers. . . . . . . . . 22 2.3 Radiation Damping . . . . . . 26 2.4 The Absorber Theory of Radiation 32 3. The Thermodynamical Arrow of Time 37 3.1 The Derivation of Classical Master Equations 40 3.1.1 j.l-Space Dynamics and Boltzmann's H-Theorem 41 3.1.2 r-Space Dynamics and Gibbs' Entropy 45 3.2 Zwanzig's General Formalism of Master Equations 55 3.3 Thermodynamics and Information. . . . . 66 3.3.1 Thermodynamics Based on Information 66 3.3.2 Information Based on Thermodynamics 71 3.4 Semigroups and the Emergence of Order 75 4. The Quantum Mechanical Arrow of Time . . 83 4.1 The Formal Analogy . . . . . . . . 84 4.1.1 Application of Quantization Rules 84 4.1.2 Master Equations and Quantum Indeterminism 87 4.2 Ensembles versus Entanglement 92 4.3 Decoherence . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 99 4.3.1 Trajectories . . . . . . . . . . . . 101 4.3.2 Molecular Configurations as Robust States 103 4.3.3 Charge Superselection . . . 105 4.3.4 Classical Fields and Gravity 107 4.3.5 Quantum Jumps . . . . . 109 x Contents 4.4 Quantum Dynamical Maps . . . . . . . . 111 4.5 Exponential Decay and 'Causality' in Scattering 116 4.6 The Time Arrow of Various Interpretations of Quantum Theory . . . . . . 121 5. The Time Arrow of Spacetime Geometry 133 5.1 Thermodynamics of Black Holes 137 5.2 Thermodynamics of Acceleration 146 5.3 Expansion of the Universe . . . 151 5.4 Geometrodynamics and Intrinsic Time 159 6. The Time Arrow in Quantum Cosmology 169 6.1 Phase Transitions of the Vacuum . . . . . . 171 6.2 Quantum Gravity and the Quantization of Time 174 6.2.1 Quantization of the Friedmann Universe 177 6.2.2 The Emergence of Classical Time 185 6.2.3 Black Holes in Quantum Cosmology 193 Epilog 197 Appendix: A Simple Numerical Toy Model. 201 References 207 Subject Index 227 Introduction The asymmetry of nature under a 'reversal of time' (that is, a reversal of mo tion and change) appears only too obvious, as it deeply affects our own form of existence. If physics is to justify the hypothesis that its laws control ev erything that happens in nature, it should be able to explain (or consistently describe) this fundamental asymmetry which defines what may be called a direction in time or even - as will have to be discussed - a direction of time. Surprisingly, the very laws of nature are in pronounced contrast to this funda mental asymmetry: they are essentially symmetric under time reversal. It is this discrepancy that defines the enigma of the direction of time, while there is no lack of asymmetric formalisms or pictures that go beyond the empirical dynamical laws. It has indeed proven appropriate to divide the formal dynamical descrip tion of nature into laws and initial conditions. Wigner (1972), in his Nobel Prize lecture, called it Newton's greatest discovery, since it demonstrates that the laws by themselves are far from determining nature. The formulation of these two pieces of the dynamical description requires that appropriate kine matical concepts (formal states or configurations z, say), which allow the unique mapping (or 'representation') of all possible states of physical sys tems, have already been defined on empirical grounds. For example, consider the mechanics of N mass points. Each state z is then equivalent to N points in three-dimensional space, which may be rep resented in turn by their 3N coordinates with respect to a certain frame of reference. States of physical fields are instead described by certain func tions on three-dimensional space. If the laws of nature, in particular in their relativistic form, contain kinematical elements (that is, constraints for kine matical concepts that would otherwise be too general, such as divE = 0 in electrodynamics), one should distinguish them from the dynamical laws proper. This is only in formal contrast to relativistic spacetime symmetry (see Sect. 5.4). The laws of nature, thus refined to their purely dynamical sense, describe the time dependence of physical states, z(t), in a general form - usually by means of differential equations. They are called deterministic if they uniquely determine the state at time t from that (and possibly its time derivative) at any earlier or later time, that is, from an appropriate initial or final condition. This symmetric causal structure of dynamical determinism is stronger than the traditional concept of causality, which requires that every event in nature H. D. Zeh, The Physical Basis of The Direction of Time © Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2001

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.