ebook img

The Perceptual Structure of Three-Dimensional Art PDF

111 Pages·2017·1.551 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The Perceptual Structure of Three-Dimensional Art

SPRINGER BRIEFS IN PHILOSOPHY Paul M.W. Hackett The Perceptual Structure of Three- Dimensional Art 123 SpringerBriefs in Philosophy SpringerBriefs present concise summaries of cutting-edge research and practical applications across a wide spectrum offields. Featuring compact volumes of 50 to 125 pages, the series covers a range of content from professional to academic. Typical topics might include: (cid:129) A timely report of state-of-the art analytical techniques (cid:129) A bridge between new research results, as published in journal articles, and a contextual literature review (cid:129) A snapshot of a hot or emerging topic (cid:129) An in-depth case study or clinical example (cid:129) Apresentation ofcore conceptsthatstudents mustunderstand inordertomake independent contributions. SpringerBriefsinPhilosophycoverabroadrangeofphilosophicalfieldsincluding: Philosophy of Science, Logic, Non-Western Thinking and Western Philosophy. Wealsoconsiderbiographies,fullorpartial,ofkeythinkersandpioneers. SpringerBriefs are characterized by fast, global electronic dissemination, standard publishing contracts, standardized manuscript preparation and formatting guidelines, and expedited production schedules. Both solicited and unsolicited manuscripts are considered for publication in the SpringerBriefs in Philosophy series. Potential authors are warmly invited to complete and submit the Briefs AuthorProposalform.Allprojectswillbesubmittedtoeditorialreviewbyexternal advisors. SpringerBriefsarecharacterizedbyexpeditedproductionscheduleswiththeaim for publication 8 to 12 weeks after acceptance and fast, global electronic dissemination through our online platform SpringerLink. The standard concise author contracts guarantee that (cid:129) an individual ISBN is assigned to each manuscript (cid:129) each manuscript is copyrighted in the name of the author (cid:129) theauthorretainstherighttopostthepre-publicationversiononhis/herwebsite or that of his/her institution. More information about this series at http://www.springer.com/series/10082 Paul M.W. Hackett The Perceptual Structure of Three-Dimensional Art 123 PaulM.W.Hackett Schoolof Communication EmersonCollege Boston, MA USA ISSN 2211-4548 ISSN 2211-4556 (electronic) SpringerBriefs inPhilosophy ISBN978-3-319-48450-1 ISBN978-3-319-48452-5 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-48452-5 LibraryofCongressControlNumber:2016955304 ©TheAuthor(s)2017 Thisworkissubjecttocopyright.AllrightsarereservedbythePublisher,whetherthewholeorpart of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any other physical way, and transmission orinformationstorageandretrieval,electronicadaptation,computersoftware,orbysimilarordissimilar methodologynowknownorhereafterdeveloped. The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publicationdoesnotimply,evenintheabsenceofaspecificstatement,thatsuchnamesareexemptfrom therelevantprotectivelawsandregulationsandthereforefreeforgeneraluse. The publisher, the authors and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in this book are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the publisher nor the authorsortheeditorsgiveawarranty,expressorimplied,withrespecttothematerialcontainedhereinor foranyerrorsoromissionsthatmayhavebeenmade. Printedonacid-freepaper ThisSpringerimprintispublishedbySpringerNature TheregisteredcompanyisSpringerInternationalPublishingAG Theregisteredcompanyaddressis:Gewerbestrasse11,6330Cham,Switzerland The Tea Garden in Grantchester is a place where friends and colleagues have met and found inspiration for the last century. Walking along the banks of the River Cam through Grantchester Meadows and reading and writing in the Tea Rooms has been my privilege and is worthy of dedication. To father: a creative, artistic and gentle man. To mother: a delicate and creative craftsperson. To Jessica: with her sharp insight; the finest cubist. Also by Paul M.W. Hackett: Psychology and Philosophy of Abstract Art: Neuro-aesthetics, Perception and Comprehension Basingstoke: Palgrave McMillan. Facet Theory and the Mapping Sentence: Evolving Philosophy, Use and Application Basingstoke: Palgrave McMillan. Perceptual Neuroscience and Fine Art: Field of Vision and the Painted Grid New York: Psychology Press. By Jessica B. Schwarzenbach and Paul M.W. Hackett Transatlantic Reflections on the Practice-based PhD in Fine Art New York: Routledge. Preface When we look at abstract paintings,drawings, sculptures, and other abstract forms of what is termed fine art,1 how do we understand these experiences? Perhaps we see a mess, a clutter or a confusion of lines, shapes and textures, and perhaps an array of vivid colour. Providingananswertothe question of just whatit iswe see when we look atabstract artworks has been a challenge accepted by many authors (see for example,Crowther 2007; Crowtherand Wunsche 2012), including myself (Hackett2013,2016).Inrelationtotwo-dimensionalartworks,theseauthorsandI, have attempted to shed light upon what I call figure–ground mereology2 where figure and ground are parts of the whole artwork, are related to this totality and where the parts have structural interrelationships. In this essay, I will offer my contributiontothedebateabouttheperceptionofabstractart:specifically,artthatis both abstract and three dimensional. In an attempt to establish such an understanding, I will consider how, in the generalcourseofourlives,weperceivethevisualfieldthatstretchesoutbeforeus, andmorespecifically,thewayinwhichweperceivethree-dimensionalworksofart thatareunderstoodtobeabstractratherthanfigurativeordirectlyrepresentational. A central concern within this essay is the relationships that exist between a three-dimensional artwork and its context in situations where context is central to the artworks’ perception (be these figurative, concrete representations of reality or non-representational forms of art) within our visual fields. Furthermore, the 1Fine art is sometimes called studio art in the US and is usually thought to consist of painting, drawing,sculpture,printmaking,andotherformsofpredominantlyvisualart.Withinthisgrouping of art products, fine art is primarily or exclusively associated with viewer appreciating such artworks in terms of their content which is intellectual (a person’s mental abilities applied to achieve understanding objectively through reasoning), imaginative (the construction of novel ideas,conceptsorimagesfromwhatwesensebutwhichisnotpresentforthesenses)oraesthetic (thatwhichisassociatedwithbeautyorthecreationofbeauty).Furthermore,itisoftenassumed thattocreatefineartrequiresgreatskillonthepartoftheartistandknowledgeanddiscernmenton thepartoftheviewer. 2Mereologicalisthatwhichpertainstomereology,wheremereologyisthestudyofparttowhole relationships. ix x Preface exploitation by the artist of the relationships in two-dimensional artwork between figure and ground elements forms the basis for the creation of the perceived art image. In three-dimensional works of art, this relationship delimits objects and forms: Within some definitions of art, figure–ground and object–context are the components of an artwork that facilitate the artist’s mereological account and convey meaning. Mereology is a term found in philosophical writing and thinking. Literally, mereology means the study of parts and wholes and their associations. In philos- ophy, mereology is usually composed of a series of part–whole relationships that aresomewhatformallyspecifiedthroughalgebraicequations.Whenthinkingabout abstract, two- and three-dimensional visual art, what constitutes the perception of this mereological amalgam of object, figure or form, positive and negative space, may become almost duplicitous: Perceptions of abstract forms of artwork are particularly and specifically multi-faced as they embody uncertainty. At the same time, and in contrast to figurative art, non-representative art more clearly exposes thewaysinwhichthethree-dimensionalartobjectmaybeincorporatedwithin,and differentiated from,itscontextbytheartist. Withoutseekingrecoursetotheuseof figurative elements three-dimensional abstract art attempts to exploit physiological/psychological associations and in doing this uncertainty itself becomespartoftheartwork.Duringthefollowingpages,Iwillbrieflyreview how we structure our observations of visual objects.3 Avastliteratureexiststhatexploresthenatureofhowweconceiveoftheworld around us. As vision, forms the major sense through which we assemble our worldview I will spend time looking at a selection of these visual worldviews. In onesense,theseworldviewsmaybeconsideredontologies.Ontologyisthestudyof beingandthepropertiesofbeing,asthesepropertiesaresharedacrossmaterialand non-material entities. Ontology is concerned with the understanding the funda- mental categories of existence.4 Husserl(1859–1938)advancedacategorialsysteminhisLogicalInvestigations (1913–21) (Fisette 2003) of a ‘pure theory of objects’. In his ontology, Husserl proposed the categories of: object, state of affairs, property, genus, species, unity, plurality,number,relation,connection,series,part,whole,dependence,magnitude, open and closed, set, boundary, manifold, space, time, movement, causality, etc. Fromthis list,itcanbeseenthatHusserl’sontologyisanextremelycomprehensive account of the more basic elements of life. Husserl was stating an ontological framework, where these categories form an understanding of our being or exis- tence, where this ontology may also be employed to define a manner in which we comprehend the nature of being human. Inanyattempttoexplainhowhumanbeingsexperiencetheirexistence,asubset ofontologicalcategoriesmaybeselectedinordertoformboundariesaroundandto 3WhatImeanwhenIusethetermartobjectisaworkoffineartthatisnotapainting,drawing,or print,butisathree-dimensionalobjectoranarteventwithinspace. 4Anontologyisalsoamodelorrepresentationofthebasicelementsofourexperience. Preface xi delimit an existential domain. In this essay I will attempt to establish the bounds, and internal sub-divisions of, the experience of three-dimensional abstract fine art. I liken the application and/or functional processes of an ontology to those of a worldviewasbothdelimitourexperiences.Ontologiesandworldviewsdefinewhat weconsidervalidandthusdeterminethescopeofourtheorizingandthestatements that arise from our speculations. Formal ontology is the systematic understanding oftheformsofentities andstatesofbeingintheworld.Aswellasruminatingupon ontologies as totalities I will reflect upon the separate parts of the world, as we understand this, and the parts relate to each other and to the whole (ontology) itself.5 I have specific reasons for focussing upon the concepts of ontology and mere- ology. The first of these is that I have used mapping sentences and facet theory in my earlier research. These approaches incorporate an implicit ontological per- spectivethathashelpedmeto identifythebasicunitsthroughwhichwe experience of an artwork (an ontological account). Furthermore, the mapping sentence approach can also model the interrelationships between the basic ontological ele- ments of an artwork (a mereological account). In my earlier research I have used facet theory approaches to produce understanding of how we perceive two-dimensional artworks. In the current research, I attempt to extend this under- standing by developing a mereological/ontological account of three-dimensional artworks located within the visual field.6 Several writers and scholars have exerted an important influence upon the writinginthisbook.Oftheseauthors,Iwillespecially beconsideringthewritingof art historian and writer Rosalind Krauss,7 who has written a great deal about the visualfieldandhowbothtwo-dimensionalandthree-dimensionalartworks occupy this space. In particular, she has deliberated over how artists from the modernist milieuhaveuseddevicessuchasfigureandgroundintheirtwo-dimensionalworks and how land artists have explored notions of the extended visual field in their three-dimensionalcreations.8Inthecaseofthree-dimensionalworks,Kraussdwells upon concepts of the extended field of the work and offers accounts of three-dimensional works inclusive of the location within which a work is sited. In both two- and three-dimensional cases, Krauss emphasizes the context within which an artwork is situated and the general context that surrounds an art object. Intermsofthetwo-dimensionalimagesandthree-dimensionalartworks,Krauss’ seminal contribution to understanding the artwork has been the development of a structuralists’ account that uses a ‘Klein Group Model’. Krauss claims that the 5Scholars whose thoughts are important in this part of my essay include but are not limited to: Plato,Aristotle;Ockham;DunScotus;KantandHegel. 6WhenspeakingaboutthevisualfieldIamdefiningthistobetheareathatapersonisabletosee when looking through a single eye whilst keeping their body, and especially their head, motionless. 7Forexample:Krauss(1977,1981,2003). 8Insimpleterms,theextendedfieldisthespaceorareaaroundathree-dimensionalartworkorthe largerareathatconstitutesaworkoflandart,etc.

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.