Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind 17 Börje Bydén Filip Radovic E ditors The Parva naturalia in Greek, Arabic and Latin Aristotelianism Supplementing the Science of the Soul Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind Volume 17 Series editors Henrik Lagerlund, The University of Western Ontario, Canada Mikko Yrjönsuuri, Academy of Finland and University of Jyväskylä, Finland Board of Consulting Editors Lilli Alanen, Uppsala University, Sweden Joël Biard, University of Tours, France Michael Della Rocca, Yale University, U.S.A. Eyjólfur Emilsson, University of Oslo, Norway André Gombay, University of Toronto, Canada Patricia Kitcher, Columbia University, U.S.A. Simo Knuuttila, University of Helsinki, Finland Béatrice M. Longuenesse, New York University, U.S.A. Calvin Normore, University of California, Los Angeles, U.S.A. More information about this series at http://www.springer.com/series/6539 Börje Bydén • Filip Radovic Editors The Parva naturalia in Greek, Arabic and Latin Aristotelianism Supplementing the Science of the Soul Editors Börje Bydén Filip Radovic Department of Philosophy, Linguistics Department of Philosophy, Linguistics and Theory of Science and Theory of Science University of Gothenburg University of Gothenburg Gothenburg, Sweden Gothenburg, Sweden Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind ISBN 978-3-319-26903-0 ISBN 978-3-319-26904-7 (eBook) https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-26904-7 Library of Congress Control Number: 2017943325 © Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature 2018 Chapters 1 and 4 are licensed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/). For further details see license information in the chapters. This work is subject to copyright. All rights are reserved by the Publisher, whether the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any other physical way, and transmission or information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar or dissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed. The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publication does not imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use. The publisher, the authors and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in this book are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the publisher nor the authors or the editors give a warranty, express or implied, with respect to the material contained herein or for any errors or omissions that may have been made. The publisher remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. Printed on acid-free paper This Springer imprint is published by the registered company Springer International Publishing AG part of Springer Nature. The registered company address is: Gewerbestrasse 11, 6330 Cham, Switzerland Preface The 13 essays that make up the bulk of this volume all began as papers or comments on papers presented at the first conference in Gothenburg arranged by the research programme Representation and Reality: Historical and Contemporary Perspectives on the Aristotelian Tradition on 6–8 June 2014. Representation and Reality is funded by Riksbankens Jubileumsfond for the period 2013–2019 and hosted by the Department of Philosophy, Linguistics and Theory of Science, University of Gothenburg. For more information, visit http://representationandreality.gu.se. Our thanks are due to Anna Ntinti for invaluable help with preparing the Index of Passages. Gothenburg, Sweden Börje Bydén Filip Radovic v Contents 1 Introduction: The Study and Reception of Aristotle’s Parva naturalia . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1 Börje Bydén 2 The Unity of Sense-Power in the De anima and Parva naturalia . . . . 51 Giuseppe Feola 3 The Notion of κοινὴ αἴσθησις and Its Implications in Michael of Ephesus . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 65 Péter Lautner 4 Aristotle and Alexander of Aphrodisias on Colour . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 77 Katerina Ierodiakonou 5 Aristotle’s Transparency: Comments on Ierodiakonou, “Aristotle and Alexander of Aphrodisias on Colour” . . . . . . . . . . . . . 91 Pavel Gregoric 6 Representation of Which Reality? “Spiritual Forms” and “maʿānī ” in the Arabic Adaptation of Aristotle’s Parva naturalia . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 99 Rotraud Hansberger 7 Dreams, Providence and Reality: Comments on Hansberger, “Representation of Which Reality?” . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 123 Emma Gannagé 8 Representation and Reality: On the Definition of Imaginative Prophecy in Avicenna . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 133 Olga L. Lizzini 9 The Byzantine Reception of Aristotle’s Parva naturalia (and the Zoological Works) in Eleventh- and Twelfth-Century Byzantium: An Overview . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 155 Michele Trizio vii viii Contents 10 Albert the Great as a Commentator of Aristotle’s De somno et vigilia: The Influence of the Arabic Tradition. . . . . . . . . 169 Silvia Donati 11 Good Night and Good Luck: Some Late Thirteenth-Century Philosophers on Activities in and through Dreams . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 211 Martin Pickavé 12 George Scholarios’ Abridgment of the Parva naturalia: Its Place in His Œuvre and in the History of Byzantine Aristotelianism . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 233 John A. Demetracopoulos 13 George Gennadius II Scholarios and the West: Comments on Demetracopoulos, “George Scholarios’ Abridgment of the Parva naturalia” . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 317 John Monfasani 14 Localizing Memory and Recollection: The Sixteenth-Century Italian Commentaries on Aristotle’s De memoria et reminiscentia and the Question Concerning the Degrees of (dis)embodiment of the “Psychic” Processes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 325 Roberto Lo Presti Index of Names . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 343 Index of Passages . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 353 Chapter 1 Introduction: The Study and Reception of Aristotle’s Parva naturalia Börje Bydén 1 This Volume The thirteen essays that make up the bulk of this volume all began as papers or com- ments on papers presented at the first Representation and Reality conference in Gothenburg on 6–8 June 2014 (“Cross-Cultural Dialogues: The Parva naturalia in Greek, Arabic and Latin Aristotelianism”).1 They are perhaps most straightforwardly read as accounts of so many episodes in the history of the ancient and medieval reception of a classical philosophical work, Aristotle’s Parva naturalia. By and large, they can also be read as inquiries into different passages in the development of a specific theme (psycho-physiology, for want of a better term) in the history of ancient and medieval philosophy. For in ancient and medieval times, the reception of classical philosophical works, not least Aristotle’s, was part of the daily business of philosophers, not historians. Each of these accounts (or inquiries) presents o riginal research designed to widen and deepen our understanding of the episode in hand. The contributors to the volume, all recognized experts in their respective fields, were not assigned specific topics for treatment according to any systematic plan; instead, some of them were invited to submit original papers on topics selected at their own discretion and on the basis of their own expertise, whereas others were asked to comment on one or another of these papers. As a result, certain episodes in the history of the reception of the Parva naturalia—typically ones considered by 1 The research programme Representation and Reality: Historical and Contemporary Perspectives on the Aristotelian Tradition is funded by Riksbankens Jubileumsfond for the period 2013–2019 and hosted by the Department of Philosophy, Linguistics and Theory of Science, University of Gothenburg. For more information, visit http://representationandreality.gu.se B. Bydén (*) Department of Philosophy, Linguistics and Theory of Science, University of Gothenburg, Gothenburg, Sweden e-mail: [email protected] © The Author(s) 2018 1 B. Bydén, F. Radovic (eds.), The Parva naturalia in Greek, Arabic and Latin Aristotelianism, Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind 17, https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-26904-7_1 2 B. Bydén contemporary scholars to be of particular significance—will be found to have cap- tured the attention of more than one contributor; others, alas, are only touched upon in passing or not at all. For the benefit of those readers who legitimately wonder how one or another of these episodes connects with the rest (and what the missing episodes were all about), the following introduction attempts to provide a skeletal outline of the study and reception of the Parva naturalia through the ages, with the bibliographical references necessary for putting flesh on the bones also regarding those parts of the story which are not directly addressed in any of the thirteen essays. 2 Aristotle’s Parva naturalia2 Aristotle’s De sensu et sensibilibus is prefaced with a statement of the relation between the preceding discussion “of the soul as such and of each of its faculties” (evidently the De anima) and the following inquiry, the purpose of which is to estab- lish which functions (πράξεις)3 are peculiar to some and which are common to all animals and other living (and thus ensouled) creatures. In this inquiry, Aristotle says, the results of the preceding discussion must be assumed. This is how the new inquiry begins: It is clear that the main attributes of animals, both those that are common [to all] and those that are peculiar [to some], are common to the soul and the body, for instance, sense percep- tion, memory, spiritedness, appetite and desire in general, and besides these pleasure and pain. Indeed, these belong to practically all animals. But besides them certain attributes are common to all things that partake of life, while others [belong only to] some among the animals. It so happens that the principal among these attributes constitute four pairs of opposites, namely: wakefulness and sleep, youth and old age, inhalation and exhalation, life and death. We must examine what each of these attributes is and which are the causes of their occurrence. But it is also the task of a natural philosopher to discern the first principles of health and disease, since neither health nor disease can exist in things that are bereft of life. This is why pretty much the vast majority of natural philosophers end up in the study of medicine, whereas those among the physicians who pursue their art in a more philo- sophical way take the study of nature as their starting-point (Sens. 436a6–b1).4 By and large, the programme of study set out in this passage is implemented over the next nine (or eight, if 7a and 7b in the list below are taken together as one) trea- tises in our standard editions of the corpus aristotelicum. The English and Latin titles of these treatises used in the present volume are as follows: 2 For general overviews of the Parva naturalia, see Ross (1955, 1–68); Düring (1966, 560–571); Morel (2000, 9–60). For discussions of their unity, scope and character, see Kahn (1966); Lloyd (1992); van der Eijk (1994, 68–87, 1997); Morel (2006, 2007, 71–89); Johansen (2006); Sassi (2014). See also King (2001, 34–73), which is particularly focused on the theory of nutrition occu- pying centre stage in Parva nat. 7a–8. 3 For the concept, see De part. an. 1.5, 645b14–646a4, which lends little support to Alexander’s contention (In De sensu 4.5–6, echoed by Ross 1906, 123–124) that the term is used “properly” for rational activity. See also Morel (2000, 19–23). 4 Unless otherwise stated, all translations are my own.
Description: