ebook img

The Parametrization of Universal Grammar PDF

250 Pages·1993·21.551 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The Parametrization of Universal Grammar

THE PARAMETRIZATION OF UNIVERSAL GRAMMAR LINGUISTIK AKTUELL This series provides a platform for studies in the syntax, semantics, and pragmatics of the Germanic languages and their historical developments. The focus of the series is represented by its German title Linguistik Aktuell (Linguistics Today). Texts in the series are in English. Series Editor Werner Abraham Germanistisch Instituut Rijksuniversiteit Groningen Oude Kijk in 't Jatstraat 26 9712 EK Groningen The Netherlands Advisory Editorial Board Hans den Besten, University of Amsterdam Guglielmo Cinque, University of Venice Günther Grewendorf, J. W. Goethe-University, Frankfurt Hubert Haider, University of Stuttgart Lars Hellan, University of Trondheim Christer Platzack, University of Lund Ken Safir, State University of New Jersey Lisa deMena Travis, McGill University Volume 8 Gisbert Fanselow (ed.) The Parametrization of Universal Grammar THE PARAMETRIZATION OF UNIVERSAL GRAMMAR Edited by GISBERT FANSELOW JOHN BENJAMINS PUBLISHING COMPANY AMSTERDAM/PHILADELPHIA 1993 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data The Parametrization of universal grammar / edited by Gisbert Fanselow. p. cm. -- (Linguistik aktuell, ISSN 0166-0829 ; v. 8) Includes bibliographical references and index. 1. Grammar, Comparative and general. 2. Principles and parameters (Linguistics) I. Fanselow, Gisbert. II. Series: Linguistik aktuell ; Bd. 8. P151.P32 1993 415-dc20 92-39961 ISBN 90 272 2728 4 (Eur.)/l-55619-226-6 (US) (alk. paper) CIP © Copyright 1993 - John Benjamins B.V. No part of this book may be reproduced in any form, by print, photoprint, microfilm, or any other means, without written permission from the publisher. John Benjamins Publishing Co. • P.O. Box 75577 • 1070 AN Amsterdam • The Netherlands John Benjamins North America • 821 Bethlehem Pike • Philadelphia, PA 19118 • USA Table of Contents Instead of Preface: Some Reflections on Parameters Gisbert Fanselow VII Principled Variability: Parametrization without Parameter Fixing 1 Hubert Haider Parameter Setting and the Binding Theory: No Subset Problem 17 Priya Bondre Projecting Inflecting Verbs 37 Eric Reuland & Wim Kosmeijer The Projection of Categories and the Nature of Agreement 73 Ellen Brandner The Structure of German Verb Projections - A Problem of Syntactic Parametrization 123 Peter Suchsland The Definition of Morphological and Syntactic Words 145 Marco Haverkort On the Linear Order of the Modifier-Head-Position in NPs 161 Manfred Ewert & Fred Hansen On the Parametrization of Lexical Properties 183 Elisabeth Löbel The Syntax of "Possessor" Phrases 201 Ilse Zimmermann INSTEAD OF A PREFACE: SOME REFLECTIONS ON PARAMETERS* Gisbert Fanselow 0. In its popular interpretation, the theory of evolution by natural selection tries to explain the perfect adaption of living species to the demands of the environment they live in. One of the recurrent themes in the writings of Stephen Jay Gould is, however, the attempt to convince us, the laymen, that this is not quite so. A perfect and optimal adaption to the environment could also be the result of an act of a benevolent creator, while imperfect, but still functional designs, solutions that would never come to the mind of a fairly rational engineer, are what you would expect to be the outcome of natural selection. Gould's description of the panda's thumb (Gould 1980) is a nice illustration of this point. Natural languages constitute, of course, a further example of this insight. The argument against a divine origin of language is just the same: who dares to make Him responsible for, say, the German language? Imperfections seem to disappear, though, when we move up one level in the hierarchy of linguistic analysis, when we turn our attention to the structure of Universal Grammar. I think it is wise to not attribute the complications in e.g. current formulations of the ECP, the notion of a barrier, etc., to the structure of UG, but to consider them rather as reflecting the fact that we have not yet attained a full understanding of the principles underlying natural language grammars. Chomsky (1992:1) makes us aware of the curious situation that the study of natural languages within the generative enterprise, guided by the quest for elegance, simplicity and the greatest possible degree of generalization, has been extremely successful in the last 35 years, in spite of the fact that the object of our studies, UG, is a biological entity, and thus prone to consist of inelegancies, redundancies, and other unwelcome properties. Given what we know about the origin of species in general and of our own species in particular, we should not, however, take this as evidence that UG is godsend. Theories of UG do not immediately characterize properties of a biological system, rather, they reflect the structure of an abstract, formal system that comes into being when the linguistic co-processor of our brains, which we call UG, is confronted with linguistic data. At least this is the position advocated by Haider1, Koster (1987, 1988) and Fanselow (1991) (among others), and if it is true, it is no wonder that we can so VIII GISBERT FANSELOW successfully try to formulate elegant and general theories of grammar, since their relation to the biological object we study is only an indirect one. Nevertheless, the role the principles of UG play under such a conception of linguistic theory is sufficiently clear. They inform us about the limitations of the processing capacity of the neural structures underlying the human language faculty, i.e. they correspond, even if only indirectly, to something which is in our brains, and in the ideal situation, they will take a form that sheds some albeit vague light on deeper properties of the processing system. Koster's (1987) principle of Global Harmony, Rizzi's (1991) Relativized Minimality, Pesetsky's (1987) nestedness condition, and Chomsky's (1989, 1992) proposals concerning the economy of derivations and the ordering of rule application are cases in point. What parameters of UG inform us about, to turn at last to the topic unifying the contributions to this volume, is much less clear. At first glance, the answer seems to be quite simple: principles of UG represent language-invariant properties of grammar, and parameters tell us about the range of potential variation between grammars. Thus, Principles A and B of the Binding Theory require that anaphors be bound and pronouns be free in a certain local domain Σ, while parameters constrain the range of variation for Σ: the choice of Σ in a given language depends on the presence of a subject and/or properties of functional categories in the Infl- domain, other conceivable factors simply do not play a role in the grammar of anaphors (see, e.g., Manzini & Wexler 1987). 1. Closer inspection reveals, however, that this is not necessarily so. At the one extreme, what we express in terms of a parameter might not reflect a property X of the language faculty, but rather the absence of such a property. This comes close to the position in Haider. To give a simple example first, recall that in certain languages V assigns Case to the right (English, French), while in others, it assigns Case to the left (Dutch, German); similar variation may be observed for Infl, N and the other Case-assigning categories (but cf. e.g. Zimmermann). So one might postulate, as e.g. Fanselow & Felix (1987: 70) have done (to put the blame on myself), that there is a parameter of UG such as "X governs to the right/to the left". But it is obvious that this does not reflect any constraints on the processing capacity of UG: there are no other possibilities left; Case cannot be assigned above or below V or Infl. To postulate a parameter here is, in a sense, a strange way of expressing that UG does not regulate the direction of government at all (but see below). The importance of this example lies in the fact that the directionality of government has quite a number of far-reaching consequences in other domains of grammar. As Reuland & Kosmeijer demonstrate, a proper formulation of the principles governing the relation between various levels of representation, in particular the one between morphological structure and S-structure, guarantees that many correlates of the SVO-SOV contrast can be made to follow from statements SOME REFLECTIONS IX concerning the direction of government: the existence of V-to-I-movement, the placement of adverbials, the position of subjects, options for scrambling, pecularities in the grammar of gerunds/nominal infinitives, etc. Thus, to speak of a parameter of directionality of Case (or 0-role) assignment is nothing but a convenient façon de parler, but it is certainly misleading, at least in this case, since it would suggest that "parameters" themselves might be of any interest, whereas in reality, the crucial factors are principles such as those proposed by Reuland & Kosmeijer which guarantee that a number of properties of grammar will always co-vary. The only thing that would be lost if we eliminate the directionality parameter is the implication that government by a category X is always unidirectional (we do not find languages in which verbs assign Case both to the right and to the left, or in which some verbs govern leftwards and others rightwards), but this may be promoted to the status of a principle of UG.2 Note that the directionality parameter is by no means exceptional in this respect. Given that UG does not contain a statement excluding that D assigns Case, the fact that interesting properties of languages can be related to the presence or absence of such a Case assignment potentional (see, e.g., Zimmermann) does not at all force a reificationist interpretation of a parameter in this context. Similar considerations apply to those parameters that govern the level of representation at which certain processes must have applied: if we stick to the original T-model of the theory of Government and Binding, and if there are principles guaranteeing that, e.g., wh-phrases must be in [Spec, CP] at LF, or that V must be adjoined to Infl at this level of representation, then we need not add an additional statement to the theory of UG expressing that the movement processes in question may apply between D-structure and S-structure in some languages, and between S-structure and LF in others: there are, simply, no other options left. As a final illustration of the point I am trying to make, consider the parametrization of the Binding Theory as discussed e.g. in Bondre. Early accounts of the variation we find with respect to the local domain Σ of anaphoric binding such as Manzini & Wexler (1987) assumed that Σ is not constant across languages: any IP counts as a barrier for anaphoric binding in e.g. English, while in other languages, certain types of IPs are transparent: infinitives in Norwegian, infinitives and subjunctives in Icelandic, and any non-root clause in Japanese or Chinese. Nowadays, however, there seems to be a growing consensus that anaphors are always bound locally: the appearance that long distance binding is licensed in certain languages is either reduced to LF-movement of the anaphor (cf., e.g., Cole, Hermon & Sung 1990), or to the fact that, one way or the other, indices of subjects of superordinate clauses are copied into embedded clauses {Bondre). In the latter kind of approach, which seems to be superior to the former one (cf., e.g., the discussion in Fanselow 1991), long distance binding of X GISBERT FANSELOW anaphors is thus made possible by pecularities of the feature composition of Infl/Agr-nodes, and if UG neither excludes nor prescribes the pertinent feature transfer, no parameter in the literal sense of the term can be defined in the realm of anaphoric binding either. 2. The claim that parameters do not have the same ontological status as the principles of UG, in that they simply reflect the fact that UG is silent about certain formal properties that natural languages might have, can be established only if one demonstrates that all proposed types of parametric variation fit into this picture, but before we go into this issue a bit more deeply, we should turn to the other extreme in the spectrum of potential problems with parameters: they seem to introduce too much expressive power into the theory of grammar, cf., e.g., Webelhuth (1989) for this point. Suppose we encounter a language, Hubertese, with one of the properties discussed in Haider, which is just like English with the exception of the grammaticality judgements of the following types of sentences (1= grammatical in English, out in Hubertese; 2 = ungrammatical in English, perfect in Hubertese). (la) 1 what do you believe that he bought (lb) 1 who do you think won the race (lc) 1 how do you think that he solved the problem (ld) 2 who think you that won the race (le) 2 who wonder you what has bought (1f) 1 how wonder you why who behaves (2a) 1 1 did not come (2b) 2 7 came not Even if you have not yet read Haider's paper, it is easy to see that Hubertese differs from English in that traces must not be properly governed in the former language, while the ECP is, of course, obeyed in the latter. Nothing in the »traditional« version of the GB-approach really excludes such a language, since, if we were to discover that there are indeed native speakers of Hubertese in, say, some part of the Waldviertel in Lower Austria, all we would have to do is to transform the ECP to the parameter (3): (3) Empty categories must/must not be properly governed. Arguments of this type are sometimes brought forward to call the empirical nature of the whole GB-approach in question (cf., e.g., the introductory remarks

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.