ebook img

The Marginal Revolution in Economics: Interpretation and Evaluation PDF

372 Pages·1973·31.397 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The Marginal Revolution in Economics: Interpretation and Evaluation

ThMea rgiRneavlo liuntEi coonn omics TheM argiRneavlo lution inE conomics InterpraenEtdva atliuoant ion Papeprrse seantta e dc onference heldt haVeti lSlear belBleolnlia,g io, ItaAluyg,u 2s2t- 2189,7 1 Editbeyd R.D.C ollBilsaocnk A.W .C oats CraufDu.Vlr .dG oodwin 1973 DukUen iverPsrietsys DurhaNmo,r tCha rolina © 1972, 1973, Duke University Press L.C.C. card no. 72-91850 I.S.B.N. 0-8223-0278-0 PRINTEDB Y-INTE TEE SEEEU.MNAITNE DP RSITNATETERSY- , OTFN OA,MERIO.A Contents Preface vii Was There a Marsginal Revolution 1 Mark Blaug 3 The Origins of l\farginalism Richard S. Howey 15 The Economic and .Social Context of the Marginal Revolution of the 1870's A. W. Coats 37 Marginalism and the Boundaries of Economic Science Donald 1Vinch 59 Mill and Cairnes and the Emergence of Marginalism in England N. B.de Marchi 78 W. S. J evons and the Foundation of Modern Economics R.D.Collison Black 98 Leon W alras' s Role in the "Marginal Revolution" of the 1870s 1Villiam Jaffe 113 Vilfredo Pareto and Marginalism Vincent J. Tarascio 140 To What Extent Was the Austrian School Marginalist 1 Erich Streissler 160 The ''M arginal Revolution'' and the Decline and Fall of English Classical Political Economy T. W. Hutchison 176 The Marginal Revolution and Concern with Economic Growth Joseph J. Spengler 203 Marginalism and Marxism Ronald L. Meek 233 The Spread of Marginalism in Italy, 1871-1890 Piero Barucci 246 Marginalism in Japan Tamotsu, Matsuura 267 Marginalism Moves to the New World Craufurd D. W. Goodwin 285 The Adoption of the Marginal Utility Theory George J. Stigler 305 Marginalism: The Harvest G. L. S. Shackle 321 Retrospect and Prospect A. W. Coats 337 Index 359 Preface THE remarkable continuity of the main "orthodox" tradition of economic analysis, from Adam Smith to John Maynard Keynes and beyond, has often been cited as evidence for the view that economics is a science-indeed, that it is the most scientific of all the social sciences. During the past decade, however, it has been widely held that the history of science is marked by periodic discontinuities, ''crises,'' or ''revolutions,'' and it is therefore appropriate to re­ consider the question whether the '' marginal revolution'' in economics can be fitted into this category. As is well known, during the early years of the 1870 's a handful of brilliant innovators in several different countries published a series of pathbreaking ideas which, taken col­ lectively, exerted a significant influence on the course of economic science in the ensuing century. But was this episode really an exception to the apparent continuity in the development of economics? Were the pioneer marginalists sufficiently united in purpose and comparable in performance to justify us in grouping them together? When their works are compared with the writings of their predecessors and suc­ cessors, do their contributions seem sufficiently novel and significant to warrant the dramatic designation usually accorded them? In short, was there in fact a marginal revolution? And if so, is it worth commemorating? This symposium was organized in the hope of casting light on these and related questions. The essays published herein examine the marginal revolution in a variety of perspectives: in terms of rthe predecessors, the revolutionaries themselves, the diffusion of ideas by their disciples and descendants, and their aggregate impact. The selection of topics and the range of coverage are necessarily in­ complete, partly owing to unfores�eable circumstances and unavoidable logistical obstacles, but partly because there is already a substantial literature in the field, e.g., that dealing with the second generation of marginalists. The articles in this volume are based on papers that were prepared for and discussed at a series of meetings held at the Villa Serbelloni, viii THE MARGINAL REVOLUTION IN ECONOMICS Bell io, Italy, from August 22 to 28, 1971, and the participants wish ag to record their warm appreciation of the direct support and generous hospitality provided by the Rockefeller Foundation and its staff. Dur­ ing the five days of vigorous, continuous, and stimulating discussion, many si ificant differences of opinion and interpretation emerged, gn with respect to both the specific topics under review and a number of wider questions of method and purpose in the history of economics. Some of these matters are examined in the opening and closing essays by Messrs. Blaug and Coats. Others recur repeatedly throughout the volume. While some papers were modified in response to the pro­ ceedings at Bellagio, neither the authors nor the editors have de­ liberately sought agreement on controversial matters. Indeed, in some instances disagreements have been emphasized for the reader's benefit. In conclusion, it should be noted that the symposiasts left Bellagio with the heady feeling-no doubt influenced by the beauty and ex­ hilarating qualities of the environment-that the history 0£ economics is a field of rich intellectual promise. There are so many unanswered questions, untried methods of approach, and untapped research op­ portunities. Hence this collection should be regarded as a provisional agenda for future work, not as a final word on the marginal rev­ olution. R.D.C.B. A.W.C. C.D.W.G. ThMea rgiRneavlo liuntE icoonn omics Was There a Marginal Revolution� Mark Blaug I THE TERM '' marginal revolution'' is usually taken to refer to the nearly simultaneous but completely independent discovery in the early 1870' s by J evons, Menger, and \Valras of the principal of diminishing marginal utility as the fundamental building block of a new kind of static microeconomics. It constitutes, so the argument goes, one of the best examples of multiple discoveries in the history of economic thought, which simply cries out for some sort of historical explanation: it is too much to believe tliat three men working at nearly the same time in such vastly different intellectual climates as those of Man­ chester, Vienna, and Lausanne could have hit by accident on the same idea; it must be due to some common cause, which it is the job of the intellectual historian to identify. The only trouble is that none of the standard explanations are convincing.1 The levels of economic de­ velopment of England, Austria, and France were so different in the 1860's that all crypto-Marxist explanations in terms of changes in the structure of production, or in the relationship between social classes, tend to strain our credulity. Likewise, the utilitarian-empiricist tra­ dition of British philosophy, the neo-Kantian philosophical climate of Austria, and the Cartesian philosophical climate of France simply had no elements in common that could have provoked a utility revolution in economics. In matters of economic policy, there was in fact conti­ nuity with classical thinking, and when Jevons and Walras wrote on policy questions, as they did, there was little or no connection between practical recommendations and their views on value theory. As for an alleged "need" to defend the capitalist system, there was hardly MARK BLAUG is Professor of Economics of Ediwation at the Institilte of Ed­ ucation of the University of London. 1. I canvassed the various explanations in my Economic Theory in Retro­ spect, 2d ed. (Homewood, Ill., 1968), pp. 303-8. The present note is an attempt to rethink the issue raised in those pages. 4 THE MARGINAL REVOLUTION IN ECONOMICS anything more suitable than the old wages-population mechanism of classical economics or the writings of Bastiat, which owed nothing to marginal utility. Lastly, there was no ;eal sense of intellectual crisis in the 1860' s either in England or on the Continent which might have encouraged a search for alternative economic models ; besides, his­ toricism was such an alternative model which continued to gain new adherents after 1860, not only in Germany but also in England. In short, the simultaneous discovery of marginal utility may call for an explanation, but none of the available explanations is satisfactory. Perhaps the difficulty is that the idea of a ''m arginal revolution'' is the sort of '' rational reconstruction'' of the history of economic thought, like the concept of '' mercantilism'' or that of '' classical eco­ nomics'' as defined by Keynes, that is bound to generate spurious historical puzzles. This is a large part of the problem, I think, but it is not the whole of it. The debate over the marginal revolution so-called has in fact confused two quite different things: the explana­ tion of the origins of the revolution (if revolution it was) and the explanation of its eventual triumph. Some carelessness in the use of rthe concept of ''explanation'' in intellectual history has further clouded the debate. II A useful way to begin is to ask ourselves whether the discovery of marginal utility by Je vons, Menger, and W alras was in fact a "multiple," in Robert Merton's sense of the term. 2 After an intensive investigation of hundreds of multiple discoveries in the history of science, Merton concluded that ''a ll scientific discoveries are in prin­ ciple multiples, including those that on the surface appear to be singletons" (p. 477). Lest this should appear to be "a self-sealing hypothesis, immune to investigation,'' Merton conceded that it was only true of certain kinds of science at certain stages of their develop­ ment: ''A great variety of evidence ... testifies then to the hypothesis that, once science has become institutionalized, and significant num­ bers of men are at work on scientific investigation, the same dis­ coveries will be made independently more than once and that singletons 2. R. K. Merton, '' Singletons and Multiples in Scientific Discovery: A Chap­ ter in the Sociology of Science," Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society 105, no. 5 (1961). BLAUG • WAS THERE A MARGINAL REVOLUTION 7 5 can be conceived of as forestalled multiples" (p. 482). Although two­ thirds of his 264 intensively investigated multiples involved an in­ terval of ten years or less, Merton refused to confine the concept of multiples to nearly simultaneous discoveries: '' Even discoveries far removed from one another in calendrical time may be instructively construed as 'simultaneous' or nearly so in social and cultural !time, depending upon the accumulated state of knowledge in the several cultures and the structures of the several societies in which they appear" ( p. 486). Enough has now been said to indicate that the concept of "multiples" is difficult to interpret, particularly in fields less professionalized than the natural sciences. The gist of the argument, however, seems rto be that "mature science" is char­ aeterized by cumulative, continuous progress such as to make the next leap forward, if not absolutely inevitable, at least highly predictable.3 We may now ask: Was the state of economic science in the 1860 's such as to make the eventual emergence of the marginal utility prin­ ciple a perfectly predictable phenomenon, in which case it is hardly surprising that J evons, Menger, and Walras discovered it at just about the same time 1 The answer to that question must surely be No. First of all, it is highly doubtful that we can speak of one economic science in the 1860 's as if it were a heritage shared between economists all over the world, studying the same treatises, reading the same journals and employing a common set of tools in the analysis of a similar range of problems. A glance at Hutchison's terse accounts of the state of economic thought around 1870 in England, Germany, Austria, France, and the United States will show that there were at least two, if not three or four, "models" of economic science extant at that time.4 Although Jevons struggled against the tyranny of Mill's influence, German economists had long since rejected '' Smith- 3. Merton guards himself against misinterpretation by denying that his thesis implies that '' all discoveries are inevitable in the sense that, come what may, they will be made, at the time and the place, if not by the individual(s) who in fact made them" (p. 485). For a similar qualification, see his "Re­ sistance to the Systematic Study of Multiple Discoveries in Science,'' European Journal of Sociology 4, no. 2 (1963): 246. 4. T. W. Hutchison, A Review of Economic Doctrines, 1870-1929 (Oxford, 1953), chaps. 1, 8, 12, and 16; see also the writers cited by Jevons, Menger, and Walras in their treatises, with hardly a name in common. R. S. Howey, The Rise of the Marginal Utility School, 1870-1889 (Lawrence, Kans., 1960), chaps. 1-5.

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.