ebook img

The M\_{3}[D] construction and n-modularity PDF

0.28 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The M\_{3}[D] construction and n-modularity

THE M [D] CONSTRUCTION AND n-MODULARITY 3 5 0 0 G.GRA¨TZERANDF.WEHRUNG 2 n Abstract. In 1968, E. T. Schmidt introduced the M3[D] construction, an a extension of the five-element nondistributive lattice M3 by a bounded dis- J tributivelatticeD,definedasthelatticeofalltripleshx,y,zi∈D3 satisfying 5 x∧y=x∧z=y∧z. Thelattice M3[D]isamodularcongruence-preserving 2 extension ofD. In this paper, we investigate this construction for an arbitrary lattice L. ] For every n > 0, we exhibit an identity µn such that µ1 is modularity and M µn+1 isproperlyweaker thanµn. LetMn denotethevarietydefinedbyµn, thevarietyofn-modular lattices. IfLisn-modular,thenM3[L]isalattice,in G fact, acongruence-preserving extension of L;wealsoprove that, inthiscase, h. IdM3[L]∼=M3[IdL]. t WeprovideanexampleofalatticeLsuchthatM3[L]isnotalattice. This a examplealsoprovidesanegativesolutiontoaproblemofR.W.Quackenbush: m IsthetensorproductA⊗BoftwolatticesAandBwithzeroalwaysalattice. [ WecomplementthisresultbygeneralizingtheM3[L]constructiontoanM4[L] construction. Thisyields,inparticular,aboundedmodularlatticeLsuchthat 1 M4⊗Lis not a lattice, thus providinga negative solution to Quackenbush’s v probleminthevarietyMofmodularlattices. 0 Finally, we sharpen a result of R. P. Dilworth: Every finite distributive 3 latticecanberepresentedasthecongruencelatticeofafinite3-modular lattice. 4 WedothisbyverifyingthataconstructionofG.Gra¨tzer,H.Lakser,andE.T. 1 Schmidtyieldsa3-modularlattice. 0 5 0 / h 1. Introduction t a m E.T.Schmidt[11]and[12]introducedthefollowingconstruction. LetM3 bethe five-element, modular, nondistributive lattice and let D be a bounded distributive : v lattice. ThelatticeM extendedby D,denotedbyM [D],isthelatticeofalltriples 3 3 Xi hx,y,zi∈D3 satisfying x∧y = x∧z = y∧z; we call such triples balanced. Then M [D]isa(modular)latticeandM [D]andDhaveisomorphiccongruencelattices. r 3 3 a MeetinM [D]isperformedcomponentwise,whilethejoinisthesmallestbalanced 3 triple in M [D] containing the triple formed by componentwise joins. 3 Note that the elements hx,0,0i, x ∈ D, form a sublattice of M [D] isomorphic 3 to D. We identify hx,0,0i∈M [D] with x∈D, making M [D] an extension of D. 3 3 Let L be a lattice. A lattice K is a congruence-preserving extension of L, if K is an extension of L and every congruence of L has exactly one extension to K. Of course, then the congruence lattice of L is isomorphic to the congruence lattice ofK. E.T.SchmidtprovedthatM [D] is a congruence-preserving extension of D. 3 Date:Sept. 17,1998. 1991 Mathematics Subject Classification. Primary: 06B05,Secondary: 06C05. Key words and phrases. Lattice,modular,congruence-preserving extension. TheresearchofthefirstauthorwassupportedbytheNSERCofCanada. 1 2 G.GRA¨TZERANDF.WEHRUNG This construction plays a central role in a number of papers dealing with con- gruences of modular lattices, see G. Gr¨atzer and E. T. Schmidt [4] and [5], as two recent references. ThispaperstartedwithaproblemproposedinG.Gr¨atzerandE.T.Schmidt[4]: Does everylattice have a propercongruence-preservingextension? (We solvedthis problem in G. Gr¨atzer and F. Wehrung [6].) Of course, if the lattice is a bounded distributive lattice D, then M [D] is such an extension. So two problems were 3 raised: 1. For what classes of lattices C, is M [L] a lattice for L∈C? 3 2. When is M [L] a congruence-preservingextension of L? 3 Surprisingly, in addition to Schmidt’s result (M [D] is a (modular) lattice pro- 3 videdthatDisaboundeddistributivelattice),wecouldonlyfindoneotherrelevant result in the literature, see R. W. Quackenbush [10]: if L is modular, then M [L] 3 is a lattice. In Section 2, we define a lattice identity µ , for every n > 0, such that µ is n 1 equivalenttothemodularidentityandµ isweakerthanµ . LetM denotethe n+1 n n varietydefinedbyµ ; wecallM the varietyofn-modular lattices. We provethat n n ifLisan-modularlattice,thenM [L]isalattice anditisacongruence-preserving 3 extension of L. In Section 3, we verify that M ⊂ M and M gets very large n n+1 n as n gets large: (M |n<ω) generates the variety L. n We show, in Section 4, that M [L] is, in general, not a lattice. In Section 5, 3 S we show how we can remove the condition that L be bounded in the results of the previous sections. In Section 6, we explain how the two different definitions of M [D] in the literature canbe reconciledusing tensor products, andwe obtainthe 3 isomorphismM [L]∼=M ⊗L,foranylatticeLwithzerowhichsatisfiesµ forsome 3 3 n n. Itfollows,then,thattheresultofSection4canbereinterpreted: thereisalattice LwithzerosuchthatM ⊗Lisnotalattice. Thissolves,inthenegative,aproblem 3 proposedinR.W.Quackenbush[10]: Isthetensorproductoftwolatticeswithzero always a lattice? In fact, our counterexample consists of two planar lattices. In Section7,weshowthethereisacounterexampleconsistingoftwomodularlattices, M and the subspace lattice of any infinite dimensional vector space. There is 4 another result on n-modular lattices in Section 6: IdM [L]∼=M [IdL]. 3 3 In Section 8, we prove that every finite distributive lattice can be represented as the congruence lattice of a finite 3-modular lattice L. Without 3-modularity, this is a result of R. P. Dilworth. We prove this by verifying that the lattice L constructed by G. Gr¨atzer, H. Lakser, and E. T. Schmidt [3] to represent D is, in fact, 3-modular. The paper concludes with a discussion of some additional results and a list of open problems in Section 9. 2. The identities Let L be a lattice. The triple hx,y,zi∈L3 is balanced, if x∧y =x∧z =y∧z. We denote byM [L]the setofallbalancedtriples. We regardM [L]asa subposet 3 3 of L3, in fact, a meet-subsemilattice of L3. Lemma 2.1. Let L be a lattice. Then M [L] is a lattice iff M [L] is a closure 3 3 system in L3. THE M3[D] CONSTRUCTION AND n-MODULARITY 3 Proof. If M [L] is a closure system and hx ,y ,z i, hx ,y ,z i ∈ M [L], then the 3 0 0 0 1 1 1 3 closureofhx ∨x ,y ∨y ,z ∨z iinM [L]isthejoinofhx ,y ,z iandhx ,y ,z i. 0 1 0 1 0 1 3 0 0 0 1 1 1 Conversely, if M [L] has joins, then the closure of hx,y,zi∈M [L] is 3 3 hx,o,oi∨ho,y,oi∨ho,o,zi, where o is any element of L contained in x, y, and z. (cid:3) Let us define the lattice polynomials p , q , and r , for n< ω, in the variables n n n x, y, and z: p =x, q =y, r =z, 0 0 0 p =x∨(y∧z), q =y∨(x∧z), r =z∨(x∧y), 1 1 1 ... p =p ∨(q ∧r ), q =q ∨(p ∧r ), r =r ∨(p ∧q ). n+1 n n n n+1 n n n n+1 n n n Let hx,y,zi∈L3. Define, for n>0, hx,y,zi(n) =hp (x,y,z),q (x,y,z),r (x,y,z)i n n n Note that (1) hx,y,zi≤hx,y,zi(1) ≤···≤hx,y,zi(n) ≤··· Definition 2.2. For n > 0, define the identity µ as p = p . Let M be the n n n+1 n lattice variety defined by µ . The lattices in M are called n-modular; lattices n n in Mn −Mn−1 are called exactly n-modular or of modularity rank n. A lattice L∈/ M , for all n<ω, is of of modularity rank ∞. n Lemma 2.3. L is an n-modular lattice iff, for all a, b, c ∈ L, ha,b,ci(n) is the closure of ha,b,ci. Proof. This statement immediately follows from the definitions. (cid:3) Corollary 2.4. The following inclusions hold: M ⊆M ⊆···⊆M ⊆··· 1 2 n Corollary 2.5. For every finite lattice L, there is an integer n>0 such that L is n-modular. Proof. Indeed,ifLisfinite,thentheincreasingsequenceha,b,ci(n) mustterminate in L3, so Lemma 2.3 yields this result. (cid:3) Corollary 2.6. (M |i<ω) generates L, the variety of all lattices. i Proof. Indeed, bySCorollary2.5, (Mi |i<ω) contains all finite lattices and it is well-known that all finite lattices generate the variety L. (cid:3) S Lemma 2.7. M is the variety of modular lattices. 1 Proof. If L is a modular lattice, then computing in FM(3): p =(x∨(y∧z))∨(y∨(x∧z))∧(z∨(x∧y))=x∨(y∧z)=p . 2 1 Conversely, if L is nonmodular, then it contains a pentagon N = {o,a,b,c,i} 5 (with zero o, unit i, and with b<a) as a sublattice and p (b,a,c)=b∨(a∧c)=b, 1 p (b,a,c)=(b∨(a∧c))∨((a∨(b∧c))∧(c∨(a∧b))=a, 2 4 G.GRA¨TZERANDF.WEHRUNG so µ : p =p fails with x=b, y =a, and z =c. (cid:3) 1 1 2 On the other hand, p =p holds in N , so we obtain 2 3 5 Lemma 2.8. The variety N generated by N is 2-modular. 5 5 E. T. Schmidt [11] and [12] proved that M [L] is a modular lattice, if L is 3 distributive. We now prove the converse. Lemma 2.9. L be a lattice. Then M [L] is a modular lattice iff L is distributive. 3 Proof. So let M [L] be modular. Since M [L] is an extension of L, it follows that 3 3 L is modular. If L is not distributive, then L contains M = {o,a,b,c,i}, the five 3 element modular nondistributive lattice, as a sublattice. Then ho,o,oi, ha,a,ai, ha,a,ii, hb,c,oi, hi,i,ii ∈ M [L], ha,a,ii∧hb,c,oi = ho,o,oi, ha,a,ai∨hb,c,oi = 3 hi,i,ii, which easily imply that N ={ho,o,oi,ha,a,ai,ha,a,ii,hb,c,oi,hi,i,ii} 5 is the five-element nonmodular lattice, a sublattice of M [L], a contradiction. (cid:3) 3 The following lemma is due to E. T. Schmidt [11], for n = 1, and to R. W. Quackenbush[10], for n=2: Lemma 2.10. Let n > 0 and let L ∈ M be a lattice. Then M [L] is a lattice. n 3 Furthermore, if L is bounded, then M [L] has a spanning M . 3 3 Proof. By Lemma 2.1, we have to prove that M [L] is a closure system. For 3 hx,y,zi∈M [L], define 3 (2) hx,y,zi=hp (x,y,z),q (x,y,z),r (x,y,z)i. n n n ′ ′ ′ By (1), hx,y,zi≤hx,y,zi. Since a polynomial is isotone, hx,y,zi≤hx,y ,z i im- pliesthathx,y,zi≤hx′,y′,z′i. Finally,lethx,y,zi=hx∗,y∗,z∗i;thenp (x,y,z)= n p (x,y,z)=p (x∗,y∗,z∗), so hx,y,zi is closed. n+1 1 The spanning M is {h0,0,0i,h1,0,0i,h0,1,0i,h0,0,1i,h1,1,1i}. (cid:3) 3 Theorem 1. Let n > 0 and let L be a bounded n-modular lattice. Then M [L] is 3 a lattice with a spanning M . The map 3 ε: x7→hx,0,0i embeds L into M [L]. If we identify x ∈ L with xε = hx,0,0i ∈ M [L], then the 3 3 lattice M [L] is a congruence-preserving extension of L. 3 Proof. By Lemma 2.10, M [L]is a lattice. Furthermore,ε is, obviously,anembed- 3 ding; we identify x∈L with xε=hx,0,0i. Now let Θ be a congruence of L. Form Θ3, a congruenceofL3, andlet M [Θ]be the restrictionofΘ3 to M [L]. We claim 3 3 that M [Θ] is the unique extension of the congruence Θ to M [L]. Since M [Θ] 3 3 3 restricted to L equals Θ, it is sufficient to prove the following two statements: (i) M [Θ] is a congruence of M [L]. 3 3 (ii) Every congruence Φ of M [L] is of the form M [Θ], for some congruence 3 3 Θ of L. Re: (i). M [Θ] is obviously a meet-congruence on M [L]. It remains to prove 3 3 the join substitution property. So let hx ,y ,z i ≡ hx ,y ,z i (M [Θ]) and let 0 0 0 1 1 1 3 hu,v,wi ∈ M [L]. Then x ≡ x (Θ) and so x ∨ u ≡ x ∨u (Θ). Similarly, 3 0 1 0 1 THE M3[D] CONSTRUCTION AND n-MODULARITY 5 y ∨v ≡y ∨v (Θ)andz ∨w ≡z ∨w (Θ). Sinceapolynomialhasthesubstitution 0 1 0 1 property, we conclude that p (x ∨u,y ∨v,z ∨w)≡p (x ∨u,y ∨v,z ∨w) (Θ), n 0 0 0 n 1 1 1 and similarly for q and r . Thus n n hp (x ∨u,y ∨v,z ∨w),q (x ∨u,y ∨v,z ∨w), n 0 0 0 n 0 0 0 r (x ∨u,y ∨v,z ∨w)i n 0 0 0 ≡hp (x ∨u,y ∨v,z ∨w),q (x ∨u,y ∨v,z ∨w), n 1 1 1 n 1 1 1 r (x ∨u,y ∨v,z ∨w)i n 0 0 0 modulo Θ3, andtherefore, modulo M [Θ]. By (2), this lastcongruence is the same 3 as hx ,y ,z i∨hu,v,wi≡hx ,y ,z i∨hu,v,wi (M [Θ]), 0 0 0 1 1 1 3 which was to be proved. Re: (ii). Let Φ be a congruence of M [L] and let Θ be the restrictionof Φ to L. 3 We want to show that M [Θ]=Φ. Let hx ,y ,z i, hx ,y ,z i∈M [L]. 3 0 0 0 1 1 1 3 If hx ,y ,z i ≡ hx ,y ,z i (M [Θ]), then x ≡ x (Θ) in L and so hx ,0,0i ≡ 0 0 0 1 1 1 3 0 1 0 hx ,0,0i (M [Θ]). Since M [Θ] and Φ agree on L, we conclude that 1 3 3 (3) hx ,0,0i≡hx ,0,0i (Φ). 0 1 Similarly, hy ,0,0i≡hy ,0,0i (Φ); therefore, 0 1 h0,y ,0i=(hy ,0,0i∨h0,0,1i)∧h0,1,0i 0 0 ≡(hy ,0,0i∨h0,0,1i)∧h0,1,0i=h0,y ,0i (Φ) 1 1 that is, (4) h0,y ,0i≡h0,y ,0i (Φ). 0 1 Similarly, (5) h0,0,z i≡h0,0,z i (Φ). 0 1 Joiningthethreecongruences(3)–(5),weobtainthathx ,y ,z i≡hx ,y ,z i (Φ). 0 0 0 1 1 1 Conversely, let hx ,y ,z i ≡ hx ,y ,z i (Φ). Meeting with hx ∨ x ,0,0i ∈ 0 0 0 1 1 1 0 1 M [L], we derive that hx ,0,0i ≡ hx ,0,0i (Φ) and so x ≡ x (Θ). Similarly, 3 0 1 0 1 h0,y ,0i≡h0,y ,0i (Φ). Therefore, 0 1 hy ,y ,1i=h0,y ,0i∨h0,0,1i≡h0,y ,0i∨h0,0,1i=hy ,y ,1i (Φ) 0 0 0 1 1 1 andmeetingwithh1,0,0i∈M [L],weconcludethathy ,0,0i≡hy ,0,0i (Φ),that 3 0 1 is, y ≡y (Θ). Similarly, z ≡z (Θ) and so hx ,y ,z i≡hx ,y ,z i (Θ3), from 0 1 0 1 0 0 0 1 1 1 which it follows that hx ,y ,z i≡hx ,y ,z i (M [Θ]). (cid:3) 0 0 0 1 1 1 3 3. The variety M n In this section, we prove that M is properly contained in M , for every n n+1 n > 0. It is obvious that M ⊆ M . To show that the equality fails, we have n n+1 to construct, for each n>0, an exactly (n+1)-modular lattice L . The lattice L n 3 is shown in Figure 1. The definition of L follows the pattern of L , except that n 3 therearen+1x-s: x , x ,...,x ; therearen+1y-s: y , y ,...,y ; andsothere 0 1 n 0 1 n are n+1 sublattices of the form C2 in the middle. 2 Since L is planar and bounded, it is a lattice. n 6 G.GRA¨TZERANDF.WEHRUNG 1 x ∨(y ∧z )=x y z =z ∨(x ∧y ) 2 0 2 3 0 3 2 2 0 x ∨(y ∧z )=x z =z ∨(x ∧y ) 1 0 1 2 2 1 1 0 x ∨(y ∧z )=x z =z ∨(x ∧y ) 0 0 0 1 1 0 0 0 L x z 3 0 0 0 Figure 1 Theorem 2. L is an exactly (n+1)-modular lattice. n Proof. It is easy to check that the free lattice on C +C (see Figure VI.1.1 in [2]) 2 1 is 2-modular. This shows that µ holds in any lattice at any triple hx,y,zi such 2 that two of the variables x, y and z are comparable. So to check that µ holds 2 in L at hx,y,zi, we can assume that x, y, and z form an antichain; since there 1 are very few antichains of three elements in L , it is very easy to compute that µ 1 2 holds. So L is (exactly) 2-modular. 1 Now we induct on n. The interval [x1∧z1,1] of Ln is isomorphic to Ln−1. So if x, y, z ∈ [x ∧z ,1], then µ holds at hx,y,zi, therefore, µ holds at hx,y,zi. 1 1 n n+1 If two of x, y, z are in [x ∧z ,1], say, y, z ∈ [x ∧z ,1], then replacing x by 1 1 1 1 x=x∨(y∧z),and, similarly,for y andz,we have allthree elements in[x ∧z ,1] 1 1 and µ holds for x, y, z, so µ holds for x, y, z. Since there is no three element n n+1 antichainoutside of [x ∧z ,1], we areleft with the casethat twoof x, y,z arenot 1 1 in [x ∧z ,1], say, x and z. We cannot then have x≤x ∧z , because there is no 1 1 1 1 such antichain. Similarly, z (cid:2) x ∧z . Theorefore, by symmetry, we can assume 1 1 that x = x and z = z . It follows that y ∈ [x ∧z ,y ]. So we have p = x and 0 0 1 1 0 1 1 q =y, r =z , all in [x ∧z ,1]. By induction, µ holds for x , y, and z and so 1 1 1 1 1 n 1 1 µ holds for x, y, z. n+1 It is clear that µ fails in L with the substitution x = x , y = y , and z = z n n 0 0 0 because p (x ,y ,z )=x <1=p (x ,y ,z ). (cid:3) n 0 0 0 n n+1 0 0 0 Corollary 3.1. The following proper inclusions hold: M ⊂M ⊂···⊂M ⊂··· 1 2 n 4. M [L] is not always a lattice 3 Inthissection,weconstructaboundedlatticeLsuchthatM [L]isnotalattice. 3 Theorem 3. For the lattice L of Figure 2, M [L] is not a lattice. Moreover, L has 3 modularity rank ∞. Proof. The reader can easily verify that L is a lattice by exhibiting the join- and meet-tables;forinstance,x ∧z =c ,x ∨z =1,andsoon. ByLemma2.1,to i j min(i,j) i j showthatM [L]isnotalattice,wehavetoverifythatM [L]isnotaclosuresystem. 3 3 We claim that hx ,y ,z i has no closure. So let us assume to the contrary that 0 0 0 THE M3[D] CONSTRUCTION AND n-MODULARITY 7 hx,y,zi is the closure of hx ,y ,z i. Since p (x ,y ,z ) = x , q (x ,y ,z ) = y , 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 1 1 0 0 0 0 r (x ,y ,z ) = z , so by induction, hx,y,zi must contain all hx ,y ,z i, that is, 1 0 0 0 1 n 0 n hx ,y ,z i ≤ hx,y,zi, for all n ≥ 0. On the other hand, hu ,y ,v i is balanced, n 0 n n 0 n so hx,y,zi ≤ hu ,y ,v i, for all n > 0. But there is no hx,y,zi ∈ L satisfying n 0 n hx ,y ,z i≤hx,y,zi≤hu ,y ,v i, for all n>0, so hx,y,zi does not exist. n 0 n n 0 n u y v 0 0 0 u v 1 1 L x c z 1 2 1 x c z 0 1 0 c =0 0 Figure 2 If L was n-modular, for some n<ω, then hx ,y ,z i(n) =hx ,y ,z i would be 0 0 0 n 0 n closed, but it is not. (cid:3) We shall see in Section 6 that L provides a negative solution to Quackenbush’s problem, namely, M ⊗L is not a lattice. 3 5. Removing the bounds Most results of Sections 2–4 remain valid without assuming that the lattice L has a unit. The only exception is, of course, the statement that M [L] has 3 a spanning M . If we do not assume that L has a unit, then the appropriate 3 statement is that in M [L], for every a∈M [L], there is a i∈M [L] such that (i] 3 3 3 has a spanning M . 3 If we do not assume that L has a zero, the definition of the embedding ε: x 7→ hx,0,0iinTheorem1doesnotmakesense,affectingthe crucialpartaboutcongru- ence-preserving extensions. So we need to reformulate Theorem 1: Theorem 4. Let n>0 and let L be an n-modular lattice. Then M [L] is a lattice. 3 The map ψ: x7→hx,x,xi embeds L into M [L]. If we identify x ∈ L with xψ = hx,x,xi ∈ M [L], then the 3 3 lattice M [L] is a congruence-preserving extension of L. 3 8 G.GRA¨TZERANDF.WEHRUNG Proof. The first part of the proof requires little change. Let Φ be a congruence of M [L] and let Θ be the restriction of Φ to L. We 3 want to show that M [Θ] = Φ. Let hx ,y ,z i, hx ,y ,z i ∈ M [L], and put 3 0 0 0 1 1 1 3 o= (x ∧y |i<3). i i Ifhx ,y ,z i≡hx ,y ,z i (M [Θ]),thenx ≡x (Θ)inLandsohx ,x ,x i≡ 0 0 0 1 1 1 3 0 1 0 0 0 V hx ,x ,x i (Φ). Therefore, 1 1 1 hx ,o,oi=hx ,x ,x i∧hx ∨y ,o,oi 0 0 0 0 0 0 ≡hy ,y ,y i∧hx ∨y ,o,oi=hy ,o,oi (Θ), 0 0 0 0 0 0 that is, hx ,o,oi≡hy ,o,oi (Θ). 0 0 Similarly, ho,y ,oi ≡ ho,y ,oi (Φ) and ho,o,z i ≡ ho,o,z i (Φ). Joining the 0 1 0 1 three congruences, we obtain hx ,y ,z i≡hx ,y ,z i (Φ). 0 0 0 1 1 1 The proof of the converse is similar to the original proof with o playing the role of 0 and i= (x ∨y |i<3) playing the role of 1. (cid:3) i i W 6. Two views of M [D] 3 For a finite distributive lattice D, in the literature, M [D] is presented either 3 as the lattice of balanced triples hx,y,zi ∈ D3 (as we presented it in Section 1) or as the lattice MP, the lattice of isotone maps from P = J(D) (the poset of 3 join-irreducible elements of D) to M . Either approachis convenient; both present 3 a modular lattice with a spanning M with D embedded as the ideal generated by 3 anatomofM andthelatticeisgeneratedbyM andD. Thesecondapproachhas 3 3 the advantage that it yields with no computation that M [D] is a modular lattice. 3 The first approach, however, better lends itself to generalization, as we did it in this paper. It follows fromA. Mitchke and R. Wille [9] that the two constructions yield iso- morphiclattices;indeed,bothconstructionsyieldamodularlatticewithaspanning M with D embedded as the ideal generated by an atom of M and the lattice is 3 3 generated by M and D and, up to isomorphism, there is only one such lattice. 3 Inthissectionweshallgiveamoredirectexplanationwhythetwoconstructions yieldisomorphic lattices. To this end, we introduce the concept ofa cappedtensor product from G. Gr¨atzer and F. Wehrung [7]. Definition6.1. LetAandB be{∨,0}-semilattices. Abi-ideal ofA×B isasubset I of A×B satisfying the following conditions: (i) I is hereditary; (ii) I contains ∇ =(A×{0})∪({0}×B); A,B (iii) if ha ,bi, ha ,bi∈I, then ha ∨a ,bi∈I; 0 1 0 1 (iv) if ha,b i, ha,b i∈I, then ha,b ∨b i∈I. 0 1 0 1 For a∈A and b∈B, we define the bi-ideal a⊗b=∇ ∪{hx,yi∈A×B |hx,yi≤ha,bi}. A,B The bi-ideal lattice of A×B is an algebraic lattice. The tensor product A⊗B is the {∨,0}-subsemilattice of compact elements of the bi-ideal lattice of A×B. A bi-ideal I is capped, if there is a finite subset C of A×B such that I is the hereditary subset of A×B generated by C along with ∇ . A tensor product A,B THE M3[D] CONSTRUCTION AND n-MODULARITY 9 A⊗B is capped, if all bi-ideals of A×B are capped. A capped tensor product is a lattice. For a lattice L with zero, let L− denote the join-subsemilattice L−{0}. Let A⊗B be a capped tensor product and let I ∈ A⊗B. We define a map − ϕ : A →B: I For x∈A, x>0, let ϕ (x) be the largest element y in B such that hx,yi∈I. I Lemma 6.2. ϕ maps A− into B and I ϕ (x )∧ϕ (x )=ϕ (x ∨x ), I 0 I 1 I 0 1 for x , x ∈A−. 0 1 Proof. First we show that ϕ (x) is defined, for all x ∈ A−. Since I is capped, we I canwriteI intheformI = (a ⊗b |i<n)∪∇ ,wherenisanaturalnumber, i i A,B a ∈A, b ∈B, for i<n. Now define i i S b , if x≤a ; i i y = i (0, otherwise, for i < n and let y = (y | i < n). By definition, hx,y i ∈ I, so by 6.1(iv), i i hx,yi∈I. Nowlethx,zi∈I,forsomez ∈B. Thenhx,zi∈a ⊗b ,forsomei<n, i i W and so z ≤ b ≤ y. This proves that y satisfies the requirements in the definition i of ϕ (x). I Now ϕ (x ∨x ) ≤ ϕ (x ) is obvious, hence, ϕ (x ∨x ) ≤ ϕ (x )∧ϕ (x ). I 0 1 I 0 I 0 1 I 0 I 1 Conversely, ϕ (x ) ∧ ϕ (x ) ≤ ϕ (x ), so hx ,ϕ (x ) ∧ ϕ (x )i ∈ I; similarly, I 0 I 1 I 0 0 I 0 I 1 hx ,ϕ (x )∧ϕ (x )i ∈ I, therefore, by 6.1(iii), hx ∨ x ,ϕ (x )∧ϕ (x )i ∈ I, 1 I 0 I 1 0 1 I 0 I 1 implying that ϕ (x )∧ϕ (x )≤ϕ (x ∨x ). (cid:3) I 0 I 1 I 0 1 Let Bd denote the duallattice of B andlet Hom∨(A−,Bd) denote the lattice of join-homomorphisms from A− to Bd, ordered componentwise, as a subset of BA− (not (Bd)A−). Theorem 5. Let A and B be lattices with zero and let A⊗B be capped. Then ε: I 7→ϕI defines an isomorphism between A⊗B and Hom∨(A−,Bd). Proof. Lemma6.2statesthatthemapiswell-defined. Sincehx,yi∈I iffy ≤ϕ (x), I it follows that ϕ determines I and so ε is one-to-one. To show that ε is onto, let I ϕ ∈ Hom∨(A−,Bd) and define I = {hx,yi ∈ A×B | y ≤ ϕ(x)}. Since ϕ is a join-homomorphism, it follows that I is a bi-ideal and ϕ=ϕ . (cid:3) I Corollary 6.3. Let L be a lattice with zero. Then the following conditions are equivalent: (i) M ⊗L is a lattice. 3 (ii) Forallhx,y,zi∈L3,thereexistsn>0suchthathx,y,zi(n) =hx,y,zi(n+1). Furthermore, if (i) is satisfied, then M ⊗L∼=M [L]. 3 3 In particular, if L is n-modular, for some n, then M ⊗ L is a lattice, and 3 M ⊗L∼=M [L]. 3 3 Proof. Since M is finite, M ⊗Lis alattice iff M ⊗Lis a cappedtensorproduct, 3 3 3 see Theorem 3 of [8]. Furthermore, in the same theorem, it is stated that this is equivalent to saying that, for every antitone map ξ: J(M ) → L, the adjustment 3 sequence of ξ terminates after a finite number of steps. Here, J(M ) = {a,b,c}, 3 and the ordering on J(M ) is trivial, thus every map from J(M ) to L is antitone. 3 3 10 G.GRA¨TZERANDF.WEHRUNG Identifyξ: J(M )→Lwiththetriplehξ(a),ξ(b),ξ(c)i. Withthisidentification,the 3 adjustmentsequenceofξ iseasilyseentobe thesequenceofallhξ(a),ξ(b),ξ(c)i(n), n>0. The equivalence between (i) and (ii) follows. NowassumethatM ⊗Lisalattice. Again,M ⊗Lisacappedtensorproduct, 3 3 thus, by Theorem 5, M3 ⊗L ∼= Hom∨(M3−,Ld). For all ξ ∈ Hom∨(M3−,Ld), we can identify ξ with the triple hξ(a),ξ(b),ξ(c)i, which, by Lemma 6.2, is a balanced triple. The isomorphism M ⊗L∼=M [L] follows. (cid:3) 3 3 NowthesolutionofQuackenbush’sproblem(discussedintheIntroduction)easily follows: Corollary 6.4. Let L be the lattice of Theorem 3. Then M ⊗L is not a lattice. 3 Proof. This is obvious by Theorem 3 and Corollary 6.3. (cid:3) Corollary 6.5. Let L be a lattice with zero. If L is n-modular, for some n, then (i) M ⊗L∼=M [L]. 3 3 If L is a finite distributive lattice and P = J(L), the poset of join-irreducible ele- ments of D, then (ii) M ⊗L∼=MP. 3 3 Proof. Part (i) follows immediately from Corollary 6.3. If L is a finite distributive lattice, then, by Theorem 5, M ⊗L is isomorphic 3 to Hom∨(L−,M3), and any ϕ ∈ Hom∨(L−,M3) can be identified with an isotone map from P into M . (cid:3) 3 Combining (i) and (ii) of Corollary 6.5, we obtain the desired isomorphism: Corollary 6.6. Let D be a finite distributive lattice. Then MP ∼=M [D], 3 3 where P =J(D), the poset of join-irreducible elements of D. For a given lattice, n-modularity has the following algebraic meaning: Proposition 6.7. Let L be a lattice with zero. Then the following conditions are equivalent: (i) M ⊗Lω is a lattice. 3 (ii) L is n-modular, for some n>0. Proof. (ii) implies (i). If L is n-modular,then Lω is n-modular,thus, by Corollary6.3, M ⊗Lω is a lattice. 3 (i)implies (ii). LetusassumethatthemodularityrankofLis∞. Foralln>0, there exists, by definition, a triple hx ,y ,z i∈L3 such that n n n hx ,y ,z i(n) <hx ,y ,z i(n+1). n n n n n n Define the following elements of Lω: x=hx |n>0i, n y =hy |n>0i, n z =hz |n>0i. n

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.