ebook img

The Logic of William of Ockham PDF

335 Pages·1935·33.333 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The Logic of William of Ockham

THE LOGIC OF WILLIAM OF OCKHAM by ERNEST ADDISON MOODY Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, in the Faculty of Philosophy, Columbia University. NEW YORK SHEED & WARD, INC. MCMXXXV PREFACE AT a time when medireval philosophy is rece1vmg more serious attention than for some hundreds of years, no apologies need be offered for undertaking a detailed first hand study of Ockham's logic. His reputation, as the foremost of the nominalists and as the medireval philosopher whose thought was in many respects responsible for fundamental and characteristic attitudes and methods in modern science, exhibits him as the most significant philosopher of the later Middle Ages. Despite Ockham's fame, and the admitted importance of his nominalistic restatement of the Organon, no modern exposition of his logic, with any pretence at thoroughness or close analysis, exists. Furthermore, texts of Ockham's philo sophical writings are extremely scarce, so that it is not easy for those who wish to acquire a clear and adequate under standing of Ockham's thought, to do so. The present study is designed to reveal, through a careful analysis carried out with adequate source material, the philosophical content, and the essentially aristotelian inspiration, of Ockham's theory of science. In addition to this purely historical interest, a twentieth century re-reading of Ockham's logical discussions has direct interest from the philosophical point of view. One cannot for long study his discussions of quantity, quality, time, place, V PREFACE and relation, without being struck by the relevance of his analyses of logical and physical problems to the speculative interests of contemporary science. Though Ockham's language, and the aristotelian background of his thought, are largely absent from current statements of scientific problems, his interests are surprisingly "modern," and remarkably free from the theological preoccupations which, in the case of most medireval philosophical writings, obscure their scientific content to modern secular readers. The direct philosophical interest, for our own times, of Ockham's discussions, is heightened by the fact that he not only deals with problems that seem pertinent to us, but offers analyses of these problems, and modes of solution, which possess great philosophic power -though they are for the most part unfamiliar to contemporary philosophers of science. The reader's indulgence is asked for the unavoidable difficulties attendant on the attempt to render Ockham's thought accurately, in a language which to him would have seemed almost hopelessly diffuse and equivocal. The niceties of rhetoric have been sacrificed to what seemed a more important end-namely, to get to the bottom of Ockham's discussions, as far as possible, and to reveal, even at the cost of unusual terminology and seemingly needless restatement, what Ockham's much heralded "nominalism" is. My indebtedness to Dr. Richard McKeon, for his aid in the task of elucidating Ockham's thought within the context of Greek and medireval tradition, and for his kindness in lending me his much prized photostatic copies of Ockham's writings, is hereby acknowledged wft h the utmost gratitude. J. I am also much indebted to Professor F. E. Wood bridge, of Columbia University, for many illuminating ideas PREFACE vii communicated with rare felicity in the course of his discussions of philosophical empiricism. And for her immense patience, sympathy, and encouragement, without which this book could not have been :finished, I thank my wife. E.A.M. Greenwich, Conn. Sept., 1935. TABLE OF CONTENTS PAGE PREFACE . v CHAPTER ONE OCKHAM AND THE SCHOLASTIC TRADITION r I. The "place" assigned to Ockham in historical studies of medireval philosophy-as innovator, sceptic, "subjectiVISt," and destructive critic of scholastic aristotelianism. Doubts concerning this estimate -Ockham's opposition to the moderni, his constant appeal to Aristotle against them. An alternative hypotheslS of historical orientation-Ockham as critic of neo-platomst, arab, and augus tinian corruptions of Aristotle. II. Mediaeval interest in logic not merely pedagogic, but philosophical. Scholast1cism as a single organic philosophy vs. scholasticism as a conflict of philosophies. St. Thomas' critique of averroism and augustinism; Duns Scotus' critique of Aquinas. Ockham's "nomin al1Sm" originates in his statement of logic, and in his analysis of the term "universal." Porphyry's questions and his fifth predicable the "problem of individuation" and the "sixth predicable." Ockham, like Aquinas, a critic of the logical realism of the augus tinian and arab traditions, revived after Aquinas by the scotists. III. Ockham's life and writings. Authors cited and positions criticized by him. The terminist logic-Petrus Hispanus vs. Michael Psellos as author of the Summulae logicales. IV. Problems of aim ~nd method involved in the study of Ockham's logic and of hlS "nominalism." Historical vs. philosophical approach; synthetic vs. analytic methods of study. Judgments of comparison, and historical estimates, of little value unless preceded by detailed analysis from the philosophical point of view. Aim of present study: to make clear, in Ockham's own terms and in contrast to alternative "aristotelianisms" which he opposed and criticized, what Ockham's interpretation of aristotelian logic was. We cannot judge Ockham's aristotelianism by the "real Aristotle," but only by our own, or by some other, interpretation of Aristotle. ix CONTENTS X CHAPTER TWO PAGE THE LOGIC OF TERMS 31 I. The nature of logic-scientia rationalis and scientia realis. Logic not a speculative science, but an art. It treats of human "fabrications" -not of creations, either divine or hum.an. The "real distinction" pre-supposed by logic is that which is involved in all science of nature-namely, between substances and the qualitative contraries. II. The term-its definition. Natural and conventional signs. Sigmfica tive and non-significative supposition of terms. Terms of first and of second intention-the transcendental terms of metaphysics. Theories as to the ontological status of the concept or intention primacy, for Ockham, of intelligence and the intelligible. Ockham's logical nominalism a consequence of his metaphysical realism. III. Principles of incomplex signification. Absolute vs. connotative terms. Concrete vs. abstract terms; does the term "humanity" signify anything other than the individuals signified by the term "man?" Ockham's answer, and that of Avicenna and Duns Scotus. CHAPTER THREE PORPHYRY AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS 66 I. Porphyry's reversal of the aristotelian order of priority between signification and predication, meamng and truth, things and facts. Porphyry's neo-platonist metaphysics constantly present in his treatise on the predicables, though concealed by equivocal language. Ockham's commentary on Porphyry expressed as an "interpreta tion," though actually equivalent to a radical criticism of the porphyrian viewpoint. II. The problem of universals and of individuation. Ockham's analysis of the meanings of the terms "universal" and "individual." Analysis of the expression "universale in re," in terms of the distinc tion between natural and conventional signs. Aquinas vs. Averroes -are human beings intelligent by nature, or only by illumination from a superior Intelligence? Avicenna 's compromise, and its influence on Duns Scotus. Ockham's criticism of the scotist notions of natura indeterminataa nd of the distinctiofo rmalzs a parte rei. Ockham's answers to Porphyry's three questions. III. Treatment of the predicables, by Ockham, as terms of second inten tion; his fidelity to Aristotle's treatment of them in the Topics. Constant correction of Porphyry's equivocation. Genus and species; differentia; property; accident. IV. Other terms of second intention. Meanings of the terms "definition," "description," "subject," "predicate," "signify," "opposite," and "attribute." CONTENTS. Xl CHAPTER FOUR PAGE THE CATEGORIES OF ARISTOTLE II8 I. The Categoriesn ot a metaphysical treatise, but concerned with the terms of first intention used in the science of nature and in mathe matics. Relation of metaphysics to discursive sciences-metaphysics not a demonstrative nor discursive science. Equivocal predicatictn of ens of the terms in the categories-due to abstractive character of all incomplex signification. Distinction between substances and the contraries, or between thmgs and facts, primary for all discur sive science, though not for first philosophy. Distinction between ensp er se and ens per aliud, or between ms in actu and ens in potentia, not metaphysically primary, but involved only in the analysis ot motion and in the sciences of changeable things. Univocal, equivocal, and denominative terms. "Predicable of a subject" and "present in a subject." Ockham vs. Boethius. The dictum dB omni of the Categories.T he categorical order a logical, and not meta physical, order. Ockham's method and interests, in his analysis of modes of signification. II. The category of substance. First and second substances. Qpale gui,da nd hoe aliquid. Characteristics of substantive terms. III. The category of quantity. Quantity not a "thing" distinct in being from substances and qualities. Critique of the motkrni. What are mathematical propositions true of? Meanings of the word "part" -things numbered are only metaphorically "parts" of the number. Class names, and numbers as classes of classes. Quantitative terms signify nothing other than substances or qualities-but they signify them, or their parts, coniunctimo, r else through connoting the opera tions of numbering or of dividing. Ockham's analysis of quantity based on the aristotelian principle that the actually infinite is not a principle of human knowledge; the scotist view involves a departure from this aristotelian principle. IV. The category of relation. Relations not "things," but ways of signifying substances or qualities, either connotatively or "taken together" (coniunctim). Is the word "relative" a term of second intention? Difference in mode of signification between concrete and abstract forms of relative terms-e.g., "father" and "father hood." D1Stinctive logical characteristics of relative terms. V. The category of quality. Four kinds of qualitative terms. "Real" qualities-the contraries which are principles of change and of sense perception. Real quahties signified coniunctimb y qualitative terms of the second species. The third and fourth kinds of qualitative terms. Contrariety, variation in degree, "like" and "unlike." Time and place, and the remaining c.ategories, Sigruficance of Ockham's analysis. :xii CONTENTS CHAPTER FIVE PAGE FORMS OF COMPLEX SIGNIFICATION 176 I. Complex llS. incomplex signification; apprehension and judgment. The mode of signification of the terms "true" and "false." The formal character of Ockham's analysis of the proposition. II. Ockham's exposition of the De interpretationaen,d his analysis of the proposition in his Summat otiusl ogicae.T he aims and methods of the termioist logicians. Ockham's use of the distinction between signifaatioa nd suppositw-the kinds of suppositiop ersonali,sD. ivision of propositional forms. The categorical proposition-ingular, particular, and universal. Time reference of verb or copula. Future contingents-the scientific and the theological answer. Modal propositions-sensus dwisusa nd sensusc ompositusE. xponible proposi tions-are all categorical propositions, whose terms stand for individual existent things, equivalent to hypothetical or conditional propositions? The possibility of necessary categorical propositions, in the real sciences, shown to presuppose Ockham's "nominalistic" solution of the problem of universals. III. The categorical syllogism-its kinds. Difference between demonstra tive and probable premises. The syllogism as a form of complex signification. Its modes and figures-can their vahd1ty be proved? The dictum de omm of the Prior Anarytics. Expository syllogisms; Ockham's detailed analysis of modal syllogisms. CHAPTER SIX DEMONSTRATION AND DEFINITION 220 I. The demonstrative syllogism-its definition, and connotation of "evident knowledge." Epistemic conditions of demonstration extrinsic principles. Characteristics of propositions entering into demonstrations: necessity, universality. The two kinds of per se propositions; the attribute and its "first subject." II. Evident knowledge which is non-demonstrative. Experience, involving both sense perception and mtellectual recognition, is the .sineq uan ono f our grasp of scientific principles. Intellectual appre hension of the undivided and of the indivisible. Universal propositions-demonstrable and indemonstrable. Meanings of "prior," "posterior," "principle." Prionty of things or of indwiduan1a tureso, ver facts or euents. Knowledge of the fact vs. knowledge of the reasoned fact; a posterioprir oof, and its conditions. Subalternant and subalternate sciences-natural philosophy not subalternate to metaphysics or logic, nor llicev ersa.

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.