ebook img

The legal process : basic problems in the making and application of law, Volume 2 PDF

445 Pages·1958·31.49 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The legal process : basic problems in the making and application of law, Volume 2

THE LEGAL PROCESS: BASIC PROBLEMS IN THE MAKING AND APPLICATION OF LAW By Henry M. Hart, Jr. P.n d Albprt M. Sacks Professors of Law, Harvard University Cambridge Tentntive Edition, 1958 Copyright, 1958 by Henry M. Hart, Jr. Pnd Albert M. Scks 366 Chapter III. THE COURTS AS PLACES OF INITIAL RESORT FOR SOLVING PROBLEMS WHICH FAIL OF PRIVATE SOLUTION PREFATORY NOTE The immediate concern of this chapter is with the role of the courts in the development of the American common law - the body of unwritten, self-applying, decisional law which historically has been the basic instrument of official regulation in the legal systems of all the American states except Louisiana, and which currently provides still the underlying framework of order. The chapter seeks to make clear the vital function which this kind of unenacted law has performed in the past, now performs, and can perform in the future. This poses the central question of the chapter: How should courts conceive of their responsibility to keep this body of law alive and growing? When can they properly say, "The decisional law is settled, and any new development or change must come from the legislature"? When are they obliged to say this? When, on the other hand, do they abdicate responsibility if they do so? This kind of issue, it will be observed, always involves two subordinate issues which are distinct and yet almost inextricably linked together. The question has to be asked: With respect to this particular matter, is the legislature as an institution a more appro- priate agency of settlement than a court? But since a legislature can ordinarily act only by the method of passing a statute, the question must also be asked: Is it desirable that the law in this area should take the form of an enactment rather than of unwritten grounds of decision? This second question may pose a problem simply of choice between enacted law and decisional law when both forms of law operate in the same self-applying fashion. But the statute is not merely an alternative form of self-applying law. It may introduce new techniques of control which are beyond the reach of innovation by the decisional process. The present chapter, as a result, is concerned in the end as much with the shortcomings of the common law as a form of law as with its merits. It tries to lay a foundation for an understanding of the frequent need for some one of the more sophisticated types of administered regulation or non-regulatory control which have been devel- oped in the effort to remedy these shortcomings. This foundation will become important when the uses of these forms of control are brought under direct examination in the fifth chapter on the legislature and the sixth chapter on the executive and administrative processes. In inquiring into the role of the courts in the development of the unwritten law, the chapter lays a foundation also for later consideration of their role in placing a decisional gloss upon enact- ments. 1hese aspects of the judicial function are dealt with in the seventh chapteravn the interpretation of statutes and in the parts of the 367 eighth chapter having to do with the interpretation and enforcement of constitutions. The emphasis of the chapter, which has been indicated, on the law making, or law declaring, function of the courts is in keeping with the subtitle of these materials. But this emphasis should not be allowed to obscure the fact that the development of a body of decisional law is only a by-produce of the judicial process. The basic function of courts is the function of adjudication - or, more accurately, the function of settling disputes by the method of adjudication. Attention accordingly has to be given to the significance of this method and this function in the operation of the legal system as a whole. The problems in the first three sections of this chapter all involve adjudication by a court, and they all involve entirely conven- tional types of adjudication. Lhe complaining party has become involved in a dispute with the defending party growing out of past events. He comes before a court which has been given a general jurisdiction to settle disputes of this kind. He asks the court to give him a remedy against the defendants of a familiar type which the court in an appro- priate case is empowered to give. In support of his claim for relief, he relies upon one or more propositions of primary law and one or more propositions of remedial law, and he proves or offers to prove the existence of facts which bring these propositions into play. 'he defendant answers, and submits his counter-proof or offers of counter- proof. The court then comes to a decision one way or another. Thought should be given to the various ways in which the existence of this procedure of settlement contributes, or may contribute, to the good ordering of society. It contributes, first, by the very fact of bringing to a peaceable conclusion the particular disputes which the courts actually settle. But this is a contribution made also by other procedures of settlement, and particularly the various procedures of private settle- ment which were examined in the second section of the last chapter. Is the courts' contribution any greater, case for case, because of the enhanced acceptability that flows from the prestige of a judicial determination? In the run of cases: In great cases? Secondly, the existence of the courts as a last-ditch place or resort contributes to the good ordering of society by encouraging the utilization of less formal or unofficial methods of settlement. In this connection, thought should again be given to the implications of the note on The Great Pyramid of Legal Order, at pp. 312-13, above. Far more disputes are settled because the courts are there to settle them if the parties don't than the courts are actually called upon to settle themselves. Thirdly, and most importantly, the courts serve a function which is indispensable to the effectual operation of general directive arrangements at the primary no less than at the remedial stage. Intrinsic in these arrangements are uncertainties. Intrinsic in them also, therefore, 368 is the need for some agency of authoritative resolution of the uncer- tainties, if the arrangements are to be made to work at all. The student should consider whether the courts, in their conventional operation, may not also make a fourth and distinct con- tribution to the good ordering of society by holding themselves out as agencies of correction of law which is unclear or unjust. Here is a litigant who believes that the law as it affects him is needlessly uncertain or that a previously announced rule or standard is irrational or otherwise inconsistent with some more basio principle or policy. He comes before the court, in Oillard Hurst's illuminating phrase, as a "one-man lobby," with a formal opportunity to urge a development or change in the law at the moment and point where it most concerns him. To what extent does the availability of such a forum of decision pro- mote the health of a society by helping to convince its members of its concern for their just treatment? To what extent can this function be served by a legislature? Beyond these questions concerning the role of the courts in the exercise of the conventional function of adjudication lie a host of closely related questions. To what extent can courts be effectively utilized as agencies for the enaotment of law, as in the promulgation of rules of procedure, or for the clarification of law otherwise than as an incident of the adjudication of a particular dispute, as in giving advisory opinions? Does the strength of judge-made law depend upon its association with - and its emergence out of - the procedure of formal adjudication? If so, is it essential that the proceeding leading to the decision have all of the attributes of a conventional law suit at common law or in equity? Or are some of these, such as the presence of an adversary party, dispensable? These questions are suggested and some aspects of them are explored in the fourth section of this chapter. To what extent does the method of adjudication as employed by the courts provide a useful model for the settlement of disputes by other agencies? For the settlement of similar kinds of disputes? For the settlement of disputes of other kinds, such as a dispute about wages or working conditions between a labor union and an association of employers, or a dispute between governments which, if unsettled, may lead to war. These questions also are touched upon in the fourth section of this chapter. Kindred questions again are raised in the sixth chapter on the executive and administrative processes and in the final chapter on the making and amending of constitutions. 369 Section 1. The Relation Between Law and Fact NOTE ON THE IDENTIFICATION OF FACT In a more spacious view of the legal process than these materials have taken, it would be appropriate at this point to present a problem dealing with the modes by which courts ascertain the historical facts of a litigation which pose the legal problems for decision. Such an examination of judicial methods of fact finding would afford a basis of comparison with the methods of fact finding used in the various procedures of private settlement considered in the last section of Chapter II as well as with the methods used by administrative agencies which are touched on in Chapter VI. A practical reason for omitting any such problem is the difficulty of presenting in any short compass materials which are ade- quate for an informed and critical appraisal of the judicial process of fact finding. A further reason is that an inquiry of this kind has not seemed to the editors to be strictly relevant to the main theme of the materials, which concerns basic problems in the development of law. Are the editors wrong about this? It might be urged that the law actually applied by courts depends on the actual facts of the cases they decide and not on the facts as the courts erroneously suppose them to be. In this view, it might be thought that study of the ways in which the courts make or declare law should include study of the ways in which purported law is distorted by mistakes in findings of fact, and of the ways in which these distortions can be minimized. Compare the voluminous writings of the late Judge Jerome Frank on the importance of judicial fact finding. E.g., Fran]; A Plea for Lawyer-Schools, 56 YALE L.J. 1303 (1947); FRANK, COURTS ON TIXrTl194T). Is it an adequate answer to this position to say that the two problems of accurately finding what happened in a case and of justly determining what should be the legal consequences of the happenings are separable - so that, vitally important as accurate fact finding is, it is not an integral part of the process of deciding what judgment ought to be entered upon a given state of facts? PROBLEM NO. 10. LAW, FACT, AND DISCRETION IN THE APPLICATION OF LAW In Commonwealth v. Wright, reproduced immediately hereafter, the defendant was charged with setting up and promoting a certain lottery for money in violation of a statute of the Commonwealth. When the prosecution and the defense had finished presenting their evidence, it appeared that there was no material dispute about what the defendant had done. There remained, however, a lively diagreement about whether the defendant had set up and promoted a lottery for money, 370 The problems for consideration all relate to the situation which was presented to the judje in the Wright case at this point in the trial. 1. Should the judge have regarded the questions whether what the defendant had concededly done constituted the setting up and promoting of a lottery for money as - (a) a question of fact? (b) a question of law? (c) a question of mixed fact and law? or (d) some other kind of question? 2. What instructions should the judge have given the jury? Suppose he had before him the following three requests for instructions: (a) A request by defendant's counsel for an instruction that if the jury believed beyond a reasonable doubt that the defendant had set up and promoted a lottery for money, they should find him guilty; otherwise, not guilty; (b) A request by the prosecuting attorney for an instruction that if the jury believed beyond a reasonable doubt that the defendant had con- ducted a game having the following described characteristics (specifically enumberating all of the characteristics of the game which the defendant had admittedly conducted) then they should find him guilty; otherwise, not guilty; and (c) A request by the proseouting attorney that if instruction (b) were refused the jury should be instructed as follows: "Gentlemen, any game in which, first, a prize is or may be awarded to the players; second, the award of the prize is dependent upon chance; and, third, the players furnish a consideration in return for a chance at a prize, is a lottery within the meaning of the laws of this Commonwealth. If you believe beyond a reasonable doubt from the evidence that the defendant conducted a game having these three elements, then it is your duty to find him guilty; other.. wise, not guilty." Cf. State v. Jones. 44 N.M. 623 (1940) Which of the three requests, if any, should the judge have granted? 3. Are the questions in 1 and 2, above, simply two different ways of asking the same thing? COMMONWEALTH v. WRIGHT Supreme Judicial Court of Massachusetts, 1884. 137 Mass. 250 HOLMES, J. The defendant has been convicted of setting up and promoting a certain lottery for money; and the only question raised by his exceptions is whether the jury were warranted in finding that a game popularly known as the policy or envelope game is a lottery, within the Pub. Sta. c. 209, 01. 371 There was evidence that the defendant carried on the game, and that the public were invited to attend and take part in it. The substance of the game, as described in the bill of exceptions, seems to be that any one wishing to play chooses a number and pays a certain sun for it; and that then the conductor of the game draws an envelope from a box full of them, which envelope contains a slip with many numbers upon it. If the number chosen is found among those upon the slip, the person who chose it receives a multiple of the sum paid by him, greater or less according to the odds agreed upon. If not, he loses what he has paid. 1e assume that the numbers upon the slips are limited in some way, so that the chances or success may be exactly calculated. But the defendant's argument that therefore the game contained no element of chance may be dis- missed with a word. The event is none the less uncertain, that the chances of the event are certain. The chances only represent the average of a long series of events. The event does not appear to have been even mechanically certain, as the selecting the envelope seems to have been made arbitrarily, after payment. But if the choice of the number had also fixed the envelope, so long as the event could not be predicted by the party concerned, it would be uncertain, and depend on chance in the only sense which the law has to take into account. Commonwealth v. Thacher, 97 Mass. 583. State v. Clarke, 33 N.H. 329, 335. Perhaps it is a little more difficult to show how the game is more than a wager. A bet, however, is usually executory on both sides, isolated, and determined by events independent of any action of the parties, while in this game a price is paid for the chance of a prize, and it is determined by a mechanical device worked by the manager of the game according to a scheme held out to the public, whether he who pays the money is to have the prize or nothing. " It may be that the difference between this and a single wager on the cast of a die is only one of degree; but, if so, the difference is sufficiently marked to warrant the finding of the jury. We cannot say, as matter of law, that the facts that the prize was money and not specific, and that more than one could elect the same number with the same result, prevented the game from sing a lottery. It is a lottery according to the popular use of the word as shown by the dictionaries, according to history, to which lotteries with money prizes not specific have long been known and according to the course of the decisions. Kilkinson v. Gill 74 N.Y. 63. See State v. Lovell, 10, Vroom 458; and cases cited in Bish. Stat. Crimes, 5952.- Exceptions overruled. COMMONWEALTH v. SULLIVAN Supreme Judicial Court of Massachusetts, 1888. 146 Mass. 142. INDICTNEM alleging the defendant "did set up and promote a certain lottery, the name and a more particular description of which said lottery being to said jurors unknown, which said lottery was then and there for money, said lottery not being then and there authorized by law in said Commonwealth." Trial in the Superior Court, before Bacon J., who allowed a bill of exceptions, which, so far as material, was as follows: 372 Franklin H. Walker, the only witness called by the government, testi- fied that he knew the defendant: that on April 1, 1886, he went to a small room in building No. 1156 Washington Street, Boston, in which was a long counter, and behind it were some men writing; that thirty minutes after he got there the defendant came in, took off his coat and hat, and said to one Graham, who was one of the writers, "I am ready to go to work"; that he asked the defendant if he was a writer there, and the defendant said he was, and on being futther arked if he was the proprietor, replied that he was only hired there, and did it for money; that he asked the defendant to whom he should look for his money if he won any, and the defendant said he would settle all as soon as the drawings were made; that he gave the defendant four numbers from a column of 78; that if he had given the defendant three num- bers it would have been a "gig; that he paid ten cents to the defendant; that he saw several other persons give the defendant numbers and give and take money; that the defendant gave him a ticket or piece of paper with 479 on it; and on being asked, "What does 479 stand for?" replied, "The number for the drawing; each drawing is numbered a class number. 1he drawings are put in envelopes." Walker further testified, that he stayed there ten or fifteen minutes, and saw others receive from the defendant similar papers with numbers, and give money to himl that the defendant stood up and asked if there were any other parties that wanted to take part in the game; that the defendant took an envelope from the wall, and taking therefrom a slip of paper with twelve numbers on a black-board, and also the class number; that then a man made a claim of five dollars, and the defendant continued to write again, and he remained and saw another drawing made in the same way,: that the numbers that the persons wanted to give the defendant, or call out, the defendant would write on slips of paper in place of the money he took from them; and that then, when the audience oneed to take part, another drawing wa-made, that is, the defendant took another envelope and took out a drawing just as he did in the other case. Walker was then asked to "describe this game in full, -- in detail"; but this question was excluded by the judge, and he proceeded to testify that his four numbers were 4, 17, 11, 44, and were not in the claim; that he was not entitled to any claim because those numbers did not appear in the claim, and that he did not draw any money. 'he latter portion of this testimony was objected to. * * * The Jury returned a verdict of guilty; and the defendant alleged exceptions. HOLMESJ. 1. This is an indictment under the Pub..Sts. c. 209, 81, for setting up and promoting a lottery. The indictment follows the words of the statute, and is well enough. 2. The testimony desor*,ed a game substantially similar to that described in Commonwealth v. Wright, 137 Mass. 250, which the jury found to be a lottery. The defendant asked the court to rule that there was no suf- ficient evidence to warrant a conviction. The court refused so to rule, but ruled that, if the evidence was believed, "it was a lottery, and a set- ting up and promoting a lottery," and that the jury would be warranted in finding the defendant guilty. If the statement that "it was a lottery," &c.. was anything more than a preliminary explanation of why the court refused 373 the defendant's request, the substance of the ruling made being that there was evidence for the jury, we cannot say that it went too far. The testimony was not very clear, it is true, and further description seems to have been excluded on the defendanth objection. But if the evidence meant anything, it described a game in which a price was paid for a chance of a prize, and in which it purported to be determined by chance; that is, by means making the result independent of the will of the manager of the game, according to a scheme held out to the public, whether he who paid the money should have the prize or nothing. Lhis having been determined to be a lottery in Commonwealth v. Wright, it is not necessary to go on forever taking the opinion of the jury in each new case that comes up. Whether or not a definitely described game falls within the prohibition of the statute, is a question of law. The defendant was bound to know at his peril. What- ever practical uncertainty courts may have felt upon a subject with which they are less well acquainted that some others of the community, in theory of law there is no uncertainty, and the sooner the question is relieved from doubt the better. * * * Exceptions overruled BACKGROUND NOTES ON THE DISTINCTION BETEEN LAW AND FACT A. The Utili of Nfforts to Distinguish " "anFact" Suppose the judge, faced with the requests for instructions set forth in paragraph 2 of the problem, gives instruction (a) as requested by defendant's counsel. It is commonly said that "questions of law" are for the judge and "questions of fact" for the jury. Other important empowering arrangements are often formulated also in terms of the distinction between law and fact. Not only the division of functions as between judge and jury but the division as between trial court and reviewing court and as between administrative agency and reviewing court is said to turn, at least in part, on this distinction. If this usage is accepted, it would seem to follow that the judge in giving instruction (a) has decided that the question whether defendant's game constituted a lottery is a question of fact. However, the perceptive critic may well ask whether the judge assigned the question to the jury because, properly analyzed, it is one of fact, or whether it is called one of fact because he assigned it to the jury. Was the motivating consideration for the assignment a conclusion really derived by analysis of the nature of the question, or a judgment based on independent grounds about what the allocation of function ought to be? Some critics have concluded that "law" cannot be distinguished analy- tically from "fact" and that at best there terms are nothing more than labels to describe a conclusion about division of function. This being so, they have urged, the labels should be discarded and the essential issues for

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.