ebook img

The Invention of Autonomy: A History of Modern Moral Philosophy PDF

618 Pages·1997·87.856 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The Invention of Autonomy: A History of Modern Moral Philosophy

PUBLISHED BY THE PRESS SYNDICATE OF THE UNIVERSITY OF CAMBRIDGE ThePittBuilding,TrumpingtonStreet,CambridgeCB21RP,UnitedKingdom CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS TheEdinburghBuilding,CambridgeCB22RU,UnitedKingdom 40West20thStreet,NewYork,NY10011-4211,USA 10StamfordRoad,Oakleigh,Melbourne3166,Australia ©CambridgeUniversityPress1998 Thisbookisincopyright.Subjecttostatutoryexception andtotheprovisionsofrelevantcollectivelicensingagreements, noreproductionofanypartmaytakeplacewithout thewrittenpermissionofCambridgeUniversityPress. Firstpublished1998 PrintedintheUnitedStatesofAmerica TypesetinPalatino LibraryofCongress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Schneewind,J. B. (JeromeB.),1930 Theinventionofautonomy: ahistoryofmodernmoralphilosophy / J. B.Schneewind. p. em. Includesbibliographicalreferencesandindexes. ISBN0-521-47399-3.- ISBN0-521-47938-X(pbk.) 1.Ethics,Modern- 17thcentury. 2. Autonomy(Philosophy) History- 17thcentury.3. Ethics,Modern- 18thcentury. 4· Autonomy(Philosophy)- History- 18thcentury.5. Kant,Immanuel, 1724-1804- Ethics.1.Title. BJ301.S35 1997 17°'.9'°32- DC21 97-7570 CIP A catalogrecordfor this bookisavailablefrom theBritishLibrary ISBN° 521 473993hardback ISBN° 52147938Xpaperback A note on references and abbreviations Thefirstbibliography,Sources,listsmaterialpublishedpriorto1800. It includes a number of early histories of moral philosophy as well as theworks ofthe authorswhoare mymainconcern. WhenIciteany of theseworks, Iuse the author's name ifthere is only one worklisted, a short title of the work, or one of the abbreviations listed here. Quota tionsfrom anthologies,whichare alsogathered underSources,follow ing the primary authors, are similarly identified byindicating the edi tor's name and the page number. Citationsfromlatercommentatorsandhistoriansareidentifiedinall cases by author and date. The works Irefer to are listed in the second bibliography, Commentary. Occasionally Irefer to a modernworkjust once and incidentally; in these cases bibliographical details are given only in the citation. DJBP Hugo Grotius, On the Law ofWar and Peace (De Jure Belli ac Pacis Libri Tres). Trans. Francis W. Kelsey. Oxford, 1925. DJN Samuel Pufendorf, On the Law ofNature and Nations (1672). Trans. C. H. Oldfather and W. A. Oldfather. Oxford, 1934. DJP Hugo Grotius, Commentary on the Law ofPrize and Booty (De Jure Praedae Commentarius) (1604). Trans. Gwladys L. Williams and Walter H. Zeydel. Oxford, 1950. ECHU John Locke, An Essay concerning Human Understanding (1689). Ed. Peter Nidditch. Oxford, 1979. LCCorr Samuel Clarke and G. W. F. Leibniz, The Leibniz-Clarke Correspondence. Ed. H. G. Alexander. Manchester, 1944. LE Immanuel Kant, Lectures on Ethics. Ed. Peter Heath and J. B. Schneewind. Trans. Peter Heath. Cambridge, 1997. MM Immanuel Kant, The Metaphysics ofMorals. Trans. Mary Gregor. Cambridge, 1991. xxi xxii Anote on references and abbreviations ST St. Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica. Trans. Fathers of the English Dominican Province. New York, 1947. T.P Immanuel Kant, Theoretical Philosophy, 1755-1770. Trans. and ed. David Walford and RalfMeerbote. Cam bridge, 1992. Introduction 1 Them.es in the history of m.odern m.oral philosophy Kant invented the conception of morality as autonomy. I use the notion of invention as Kant himself did in an early remark. "Leibniz thought up a simple substance," he said, "which had nothing but ob scure representations, and called ita slumberingmonad. This monad he had not explained, but merely invented; for the concept of it was not givento himbutwas rather createdbyhim."l Autonomy, as Kantsaw it, requires contracausal freedom; and he believed that in the unique experience of the moral ought we are "given" a "fact of reason" that unquestionablyshowsus thatwepossesssuchfreedom asmembers of anoumenalrealm.Readerswhohold,asIdo,thatourexperienceofthe moraloughtshows us no suchthingwillthinkofhis version ofauton omy as an invention rather than an explanation.2 Those with different views on freedom and morality may wish that I had called this book The Discovery ofAutonomy. We can probably agree that Kant's moral thoughtisashardtounderstandasitisoriginalandprofound.System atic studiesfrom Patonand Beckto the presenthave greatlyimproved our critical grasp of his position. In this book I try to broaden our historical comprehension of Kant's moral philosophy by relating it to the earlier work to which it was a response. 1 "Leibniz dachte sich eine einfache Substanz, die nichts als dunkle Vorstell ungen hatte, and nannte sie eine schlummernde Monade. Hier hatte er night diese Monadeerklart,sondernerdacht;dennderBegriffderselbewarihmnichtgegeben, sondernvonihmerschaffenworden." GesammelteSchriften2.277;TP, 249wherethe translationissomewhatdifferent.Seealso CritiqueofPureReason A729=B757. 2 Fora compactand learned review ofthe history ofthe term, seePohlmann 1971. Initially standingfor a politicalconception inGreek thought, the term came to be used in religious controversies during the Reformation; but its main use in earlymoderntimeswasinpoliticaldiscussions.Kantseemstohavebeenthefirstto assign broader significance to it, using it in his theoretical as well as his practical philosophy. 3 Introduction 4 i. Moral philosophy and social change There are reasons beyond the particular importance of Kant's own views for studying the history of the moral thought out ofwhich they emerged. During the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries established con ceptionsofmoralityas obediencecameincreasinglytobecontestedby emergingconceptionsofmoralityasself-governance.Ontheoldercon ception, moralityis to be understood nlost deeply as one aspect ofthe obediencewe owe to God. In addition, most ofus are ina moralposi tioninwhichwe must obeyotherhumanbeings. God's authorityover ..allofusismadeknowntousbyreasonaswellasbyrevelationandthe clergy.Butwearenotallequallyabletoseeforourselveswhatn10rality requires. Even ifeveryone has the most fundamental laws ofmorality writtenintheirheartsorconsciences,mostpeopleneedtobeinstructed bysomeappropriateauthorityaboutwhatismorallyrequiredinpartic ular cases. And because most people usually do not understand the reasons for doingwhat moralitydirects, threats ofpunishment as well as offers of reward are necessary in order to assure sufficient com pliance to bring about moral order. The new outlookthatemergedbythe end ofthe eighteenthcentury centeredonthebeliefthatallnormalindividualsareequallyabletolive together in a morality ofself-governance. All ofus, on this view, have an equal ability to see for ourselves what morality calls for and are in principle equallyable to move ourselves to act accordingly, regardless of threats or rewards from others.3 These two points have come to be widelyaccepted- sowidelythatmostmoralphilosophynowstartsby assumingthem. Indailylife they giveus the working assumption that thepeoplewelivewitharecapableofunderstandingandacknowledg ing in practice the reasons for the moral constraints we all mutually expectourselvesandotherstorespect.Weassume,inshort,thatpeople are equally competent as moral agents unless shown to be otherwise. Therearemanysubstantivepointsonwhichmodernmoralviewsdiffer from what was widely accepted at the beginning of the seventeenth century, but our assumption ofprima facie equal moral competenceis the deepest and most pervasive difference. Theconceptionofmoralityasself-governanceprovidesaconceptual framework for a social space in which we may each rightly claim to directour own actions withoutinterferencefrom the state, the church, theneighbors,orthoseclaimingtobebetterorwiserthanwe.Theolder conception of morality as obedience did not have these implications. 3 Darwall1995,p.8andn.18,·usesanarrowernotionofself-governancethanI do. Modemmoral philosophy 5 Theearlymodernmoralphilosophyinwhich the conceptionofmoral ity as self-governance emerged thus made a vital contribution to the rise ofthe Western liberal vision of the proper relations between indi vidualand society. Thatform oflifecouldnothavedevelopedwithout the work of moral philosophers. My attribution to moral philosophy of this essential role in aiding basicsocialchangemayseemsurprising,butitshouldnotbe.Humanly meaningful differences among individuals and societies are in large partnotbiological. Theyare culturaland therefore impossiblewithout shared vocabularies and concepts. This is certainly true of the moral, political, and religious aspects of life. In these matters we can only be what we can think and say we are. Philosophical debate in the seven teenth and eighteenth centuries was a major source of new ways of conceptualizing our humanity and of discussing it with one another. Our own moral philosophy carries on from the point to which those earlier discussions took us. Seeinghow we got to that point is not just seeinghowwecametoasksomeofthephilosophicalquestionsweare stillasking.Itisalsoseeinghowwecametoadistinctivelymodernway of understanding ourselves as moral agents. ii. Morality and self-governance Mymainthemeinwhatfollows istheemergenceofvariousconcep tions ofmoralityas self-governance. As earlyasMachiavelliandMon taigne there were thinkers who set aside the conception ofmoralityas obedienceinordertoworkoutanalternative. Butmostofthe philoso phers who rethoughtmoralityinthe seventeenthand early eighteenth centuriesdid notintendtoreplacethe olderconceptionwitha concep tion ofmoralityas self-governance. Theywerefor themostparttrying to solve problems arising within the older view. Most of them were hopingtoshowhowChristial1moralitycould continuetoofferhelpful guidanceintheface ofdifficulties thatno onehadpreviouslyfaced. To solve the problems that new social and political circumstances posed for their moral and religious commitments, some of them developed newwaysofthinkingaboutmoralityandpolitics. Theycouldnothave foreseen the uses to which later thinkers eventually put their ideas. Itwasonlyfromabouttheearlyeighteenthcenturythattheeffortto create a theory of morality as self-governance became self-conscious. Moralandpoliticalconcernsledincreasingnumbersofphilosophersto thin.k that the inherited conceptions of morality did not allow for a proper appreciation of1111man dignity, and therefore did not properly allow even for the moral teachings of the Christianity that many of them still accepted. Such concerns had already been strongly voiced duringtheseventeenthcentury.Eighteenth-centuryphilosopherscould 6 Introduction therefore draw on the work of predecessors as they sought ways to develop new understandings of morality. The moral philosophies of Reid, Bentham, and Kant are the final eighteenth-century efforts to articulatethenormativebeliefaboutthedignity andworthoftheindi vidual that led to conceptions of morality as self-governance.4 Kant'sexplanationofthisbeliefwasfullerandmoreradicalthanany other. He alonewas proposing a truly revoh.ltionary rethinking ofmo rality. Heheldthatweare self-governingbecauseweare autonomous. By this he meant that we ourselves legislate the moral law. It is only becauseofthelegislativeactionofOllrownwillthatweareundermoral law; and the same action is what always enables everyone to be law abiding. Kant was the first to argue for autonomy in this strong sense. His theoryis, ofcourse, ofmorethan historicalinterest. Itismorefully involved in current philosophical ethics than is the work of any other early modern thinker, with the possible exception of Hobbes. In the narrative that follows, therefore, I have kept Kant in mind. Naturally enough this skews myselectionofphilosophers and topics for presen tation.ButIhavetriedtogiveafairpresentationofthecomplexdebates out ofwhich there emerged the questions Kant tried to answer. Bentham, Reid, and Kant came to questions in moral philosophy withdifferentconcernsaboutpoliticsandreligion. Iftheyallreadsome of the same earlier philosophers, continental as well as British, Kant knew the work of others who were not on the British horizon at all. MuchofwhathemadeofmoralphilosophywasshapedbyhisGerman predecessors. Unless we know somethingabout themas wellas about themorefamiliar thinkersfrom whomhelearned,wewillnotseehow profoundlydifferentthesourceswerethatcontributedtohisinvention of autonomy. iii. Morality and religion Conceptions of morality as self-governance reject the inequality of moralcapacityamonghumansthatwasa standard partofconceptions ofmoralityasobedience.WhatistheroleofGodinthesetwofamiliesof conceptions?WhatisthemoralbearingofinequalitybetweenGodand human beings? IfGod's superiority is not acceptable, must all ties be tweenmoralityandreligionbesevered?Thedebatesabouttheseissues form another major theme in what follows. Eventsoutsideofphilosophyitselfwerelargelyresponsibleforstim ulatingtherethinking ofmoralitythatoccurredintheseventeenthand eighteenth centuries. The Reformation and the Counter-Reformation 4 Reid'stheoryallowsforself-governancebut,asIpointoutinChapter20.V,it isnotclearthatBentham'spositiondoes. Modernmoral philosophy 7 madeanythingtiedtoreligionamatterofcontroversy- andeverything s was tied to religion. The warfare that racked Europe almost contin uously from the sixteenth century until the middle of the seventeenth century, and the civil conflicts in Britain that lasted almost until the century's end, were understood in terms of issues about religion. If God's rule oftheworldastransmittedbytheclergywas theonlyhope fororder,itcouldwellseemthatpeacewasnottobeobtained.Morality as interpreted by churches that were themselves rent by sectarian dis agreements could not provide either an inner sense of community or external constraints sufficient to make civilized life possible. Could politics by itself provide those constraints? Repressive force could indeed keep the peace for a while. But who was to control such force,andtowhatends?Thequestionswerepressing.Thosewhoasked them increasingly wanted to be given reasons for submitting to au thorities whose traditional standing was no longer enough. Religious controversy affected internalstate authority as much as it did interna tionalaffairs.Newgroupswithineachpolitybegantodemandaccessto power, justifying their claims with theories about how governn1ent should be handled and limited, and who should be involved in it. Religious strife undermined the claims of clergy to be the sole au thorities in morals; political strife led ever more people to demand recognitionasfullycompetenttotakeanactivepartinaffairs. Amoral ity of self-governance was a better view with which to defend such claims than previously available theories. The need for new generally acceptable justifications of authority and the distribution of power made a rethinking of morality inescapable. Philosophy, appealing to reasonand nottoanyauthority,seemedanappropriatesourceofhelp. It is often supposed that the amazing sixteenth- and seventeel1th century developments in scienceprovided the impetus for new efforts in philosophy generally, and as part of that, in philosophical ethics. There is no reason to doubt that the development of science from Copernicus and Galileo through Newton and on into the eighteenth centurywasprofoundlyimportantinshapingthecourseofphilosophy. Butmoralitywouldhaverequiredreexaminationandreshapingevenif there had been no l1ew science. Without the science, the course that moral philosophy tookwould no doubt have been quite different. But theproblemsarisingfromreligiousdissensionandfromcallsforwider participationinpoliticswere not themselves due to advances in scien tific kl10wledge. And it was the former, not the latter, that primarily gave rise to modern moral philosophy. 5 SeeFebvre1982,chs.9andla,forabrilliantdiscussionofhowreligiousbelief so saturated sixteenth-century Frenchvocabulary that itwas nearly impossible to thinkbeyond religion, oreventonotice thatonecould notdo so. 8 Introduction What I have called conceptions of morality as self-governance are oftenthoughttoresultfromamajoreffortbyEnlightenmentthinkersto bring about a secularized society. It is assumed that there was an "En lightenment project" to show that morality had no need of religion because it had its own, wholly rational, foundations. Modern views of morality are then assumed to have been thought out as part of this effort. Ifind the assumptions questionable in several respects. Therewere,ofcourse,someatheistswhopublishedtheirviewsdur ing the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. Bentham, after all, was notthefirsttocrusadeforafullysecularmorality. Butthereweremany rnorepeoplewho,withoutbeingatheists oreven doubters,weretaken tobeantireligiousonlybecausetheyheldthatinstitLltionalreligionwas doing great harm. They certainly hoped to see the churches or the clergyreformed,buttheysoughtnosecularethic.Anticlericalismisnot atheism. A wide variety of writers in the latter part of the period I shall be considering called themselves "enlightened" and wanted others to think them so. If some were atheists, the majority were not; and they differed in many other respects as well. Like many other scholars I consequently do notfind it helpful to think in terms ofa single move ment ofEnlightenment orAufkliirungor Lumieres, still less ofanything thatmightbecalled asingleprojectinvolvingallthosewho claimed to be enlightened.6 The error about moral philosophy and secularizing enlightenment is particularly egregious. Briefly, the claimthatthemaineffortofthemoralphilosophyofthe eighteenthcenturywastosecularizemoralitysimplydoesnotstandup toeventhemostcursoryinspection. Indeed,ifIwereforced toidentify something or other as "the Enlightenment project" for morality, I should saythat itwas the effort to lin1itGod's control over earthlylife while keeping him essential to morality. Naturally this effort took different forms, depending on how the relations between God and morality were conceived. As I shall be reiterating, there are two basic approaches to keeping God essential to morality. One is now usually called "voluntarism."7 VoluntaristsholdthatGodcreatedmoralityandimposedituponusby anarbitraryfiatofhiswill.Heisessentialtomorality,therefore,because -hecreateditandcanalways,inprinciple,alterit- asheseemstodoon those rare occasions, such as his commanding Abraham to sacrifice Isaac, when he intervenes in it. On the other approach, often called "intellectualism," Goddidnotcreatemorality. Whenhegivesusmoral 6 SeePorterand Teich 1981,and for anoverview,Outram1995,ch. 1. 7 According to the Oxford English Dictionary the term is a nineteenth-century coinage.

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.