ebook img

The Invention of Autonomy: A History of Modern Moral Philosophy PDF

627 Pages·1998·6.479 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The Invention of Autonomy: A History of Modern Moral Philosophy

PUBLISHED BY THE PRESS SYNDICATE o1= THE UNWERSITY o1= CAMBRIDGE ThePittBuilding, TrumpingtonStreet,Cambridge CB2 1RP,United Kingdom CAMSRIDGE UNWSRSITY PRESS TheEdinburghBuilding, Cambridge CB22RU, United Kingdom 4oWestzothStreet,NewYork, NY 1oo11-4211, USA 1oStamford Road,Oakleigh, Melbourne3166, Australia ©CambridgeUniversityPress 1998 Thisbookisincopyright. Subjectto statutory exception and to the provisionsofrelevantcollectivelicensingagreements I noreproductionofanypartmaytake placewithout thewrittenpermissionofCambridge UniversityPress. First published 1998 Printed in the United States ofAmerica Typeset inPalatino LibraryofCongress Catalogirig-in-Publication Data Schneewind,]. B. (]eromeB.), 193o- Theinventionofautonomy : a historyofmodernmoral philosophy / I. B. Schneewind, p. cm. Includesbibliographical referencesand indexes. ISBN 0-521-47399-3.-ISBNo-521-47938-X (pbk.) 1. Ethics,Modern- 17thcentury. 2. Autonomy(Philosophy)- History- 17thcentury. 3. Ethics,Modern- 18th century. 4. Autonomy (Philosophy)-History- 18thcentury. 5. Kant,Immanuel, 1724-1804-Ethics. I. Title. BI30ï-535 1997 17o'.9'o32- DC21 97-757o CIP A Catalogrecordforthis bookisavailablefrom the British Library ISBNo 521 47399 3 hardback ISBNo 521 47938Xpaperback A note on references and abbreviations Thefirstbibliography,Sources, listsmaterialpublishedpriorto1800. It includes a number of early histories of moral philosophy as Well as theWorks oftheauthors Who are my main concern. WhenI citeany of these Works, I use the author"s name if there is only one Work listed, a short title of the Work, or one of the abbreviations listed here. Quota- tions from anthologies, Which arealso gathered under Sources, follow- ing the primary authors, are similarly identified by indicating the edi- tor"s name and the page number. Citationsfromlatercommentatorsand historiansareidentifiedinall cases by author and date. The Works I refer to are listed in the second bibliography, Commentary. Occasionally I refer to a modern workjust once and incidentally; in these cases bibliographical details are given only in the citation. DIBP Hugo Grotius, On the Law ofWar and Peace (DeIure Belli ac Pacis Libri Tres). Trans. Francis W. Kelsey. Oxford, 1925. DIN Samuel Pufendorf, On the Law ofNature and Nations (1672). Trans. C. H. Oldfather and W. A. Oldfather. Oxford, 1934. DIP Hugo Grotius, Commentary on the Law ofPrize and Booty (DeIure Praedae Commentarius) (1604). Trans. Gwladys L. Williams and Walter H. Zeydel. Oxford, 1950. ECHLI Iohn Locke, An Essay concerningHuman Understanding (1689). Ed. Peter Nidditch. Oxford, 1979. LCCorr Samuel Clarke and G. W. F. Leibniz, The Leibniz-Clarke Correspondence. Ed. H. G. Alexander. Manchester, 1944. LE Immanuel Kant, Lectures on Ethics. Ed. Peter Heath and I. B. Schneewind. Trans. Peter Heath. Cambridge, 1997. MM Immanuel Kant, The Metaphysics ofMorals. Trans. Mary Gregor. Cambridge, 1991. xxi xxii Anote on references and abbreviations ST St. Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica. Trans. Fathers of the English Dominican Province. New York, 1947. TP Immanuel Kant, Theoretical Philosophy, 1755-1770. Trans. and ed. David Walford and Ralf Meerbote. Cam- bridge, 1992. Introduction 1 Themes in the history of modern moral philosophy Kant invented the conception of morality as autonomy. I use the notion of invention as Kant himself did in an early remark. “Leibniz thought up a simple substance/" he said, “which had nothing but ob- scure representations, and called it a slumbering monad. This monad he had not explained, but merely invented; for the concept of it was not given to himbut was rather created by him.”1 Autonomy, as Kant saw it, requires contracausal freedom; and he believed that in the unique experience of the moral ought we are “given” a “fact of reason” that unquestionablyshowsus thatwepossess such freedomas members of anoumenalrealm. Readerswhohold,asIdo,thatourexperienceofthe moral ought shows us no such thing will thinkofhis version ofauton- omy as an invention rather than an explanation.2 Those with different views on freedom and morality may wish that I had called this book The Discovery ofAutonomy. We can probably agree that Kant's moral thoughtis ashard tounderstand as itisoriginalandprofound. System- atic studies from Paton and Beck to the present have greatlyimproved our critical grasp of his position. In this book I try to broaden our historical comprehension of Kant's moral philosophy by relating it to the earlier work to which it was a response. 1 ”Leibniz dachte sich eine einfache Substanz, die nichts als dunkle Vorstell- ungen hätte, and nannte sie eine schlummernde Monade. Hier hatte er night diese Monadeerklärt,sondernerdacht;dennderBegriffderselbewarihmnichtgegeben, sondernvonihmerschaffenworden.” GesammelteSchriften 2.277;TP, 249where the translationis somewhat different. See also Critique ofPureReason A729 = B757. 2 For a compactand learned review ofthe history of the term, see Pohlmann 1971. Initially standing for a political conception in Greek thought, the term came to be used in religious controversies during the Reformation; but its main use in earlymoderntimeswasinpoliticaldiscussions.Kantseems tohavebeenthefirstto assign broader significance to it, using it in his theoretical as Well as his practical philosophy. 3 4 Introduction i. Moral philosophy and social change There are reasons beyond the particular importance of Kant's own views for studying the history of the moral thought out of which they emerged. During the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries established con- ceptions ofmoralityas obediencecameincreasingly tobecontestedby emergingconceptionsofmoralityasself-governance. Ontheoldercon- ception, morality is to be understood most deeply as one aspect ofthe obedience we owe to God. In addition, most ofus are in a moral posi- tion in whichwemust obeyother human beings. God's authorityover allofusismadeknowntousbyreasonaswellasbyrevelationand the clergy. Butwearenotallequallyabletoseeforourselveswhatmorality requires. Even if everyone has the most fundamental laws of morality writtenintheirheartsorconsciences,mostpeopleneed tobeinstructed bysomeappropriateauthorityaboutwhatismorallyrequiredinpartic- ular cases. And because most people usually do not understand the reasons for doing what morality directs, threats ofpunishment as well as offers of reward are necessary in order to assure sufficient com- pliance to bring about moral order. The new outlook that emerged by the end ofthe eighteenth century centeredonthebeliefthatallnormalindividualsareequallyabletolive together in a morality of self-governance. All of us, on this view, have an equal ability to see for ourselves what morality calls for and are in principle equally able to move ourselves to act accordingly, regardless of threats or rewards from others.3 These two points have come to be widelyaccepted -sowidely thatmostmoralphilosophynow startsby assuming them. In daily life they give us the working assumption that thepeoplewelivewitharecapableofunderstandingand acknowledg- ing in practice the reasons for the moral constraìnts we all mutually expectourselvesandotherstorespect. Weassume,inshort, thatpeople are equally competent as moral agents unless shown to be otherwise. Therearemanysubstantivepointsonwhichmodernmoralviewsdiffer from what was widely accepted at the beginning of the seventeenth century, but our assumption ofprima facie equal moral competence is the deepest and most pervasive difference. Theconceptionofmoralityasself-governanceprovidesaconceptual framework for a social space in which we may each rightly claim to direct our own actions without interference from the state, the church, theneighbors,orthoseclaimingtobebetterorwiserthanwe.Theolder conception of morality as obedience did not have these implications. 3 Darwall1995,p.8andn. 18,usesanarrowernotionofself-governancethanI do. Modern moral philosophy 5 Theearly modernmoral philosophyin which the conception ofmoral- ity as self-governance emerged thus made a vital contribution to the rise of the Western liberal vision of the proper relations between indi- vidualand society. That form oflifecould not have developed without the work of moral philosophers. My attribution to moral philosophy of this essential role in aiding basicsocialchangemayseemsurprising,butitshouldnotbe.Humanly meaningful differences among individuals and Societies are in large part not biological. They are cultural and therefore impossible without shared vocabularies and concepts. This is certainly true of the moral, political, and religious aspects of life. In these matters we can only be what we can think and say we are. Philosophical debate in the seven- teenth and eighteenth centuries was a major source of new ways of conceptualizing our humanity and of discussing it with one another. Our own moral philosophy carries on from the point to which those earlier discussions took us. Seeing how we got to that point is not just seeinghow wecame to asksomeofthephilosophical questionsweare stillasking. Itisalsoseeinghowwecametoadistinctivelymodernway of understanding ourselves as moral agents. ii. Morality and self-governance Mymainthemeinwhatfollowsisthe emergenceofvarious concep- tions ofmorality as self-governance. As early as Machiavelliand Mon- taigne there were thinkers who set aside the conception of morality as obediencein order to workout analternative. Butmost ofthe philoso- phers who rethought morality in the seventeenth and early eighteenth centuries did notintend to replace theolder conception with a concep- tion ofmorality as self-governance. Theywere for the most part trying to solve problems arising within the older view. Most of them were hoping to show how Christian moralitycould continue to offer helpful guidancein the faceofdifficulties that no one had previouslyfaced. To solve the problems that new social and political circumstances posed for their moral and religious commitments, some of them developed newways of thinking aboutmoralityand politics. Theycould nothave foreseen the uses to which later thinkers eventually put their ideas. It was only from abouttheearlyeighteenthcenturythat theeffort to create a theory of morality as self-governance became self-conscious. Moraland politicalconcerns led increasingnumbersofphilosophers to think that the inherited conceptions of morality did not allow for a proper appreciation of human dignity, and therefore did not properly allow even for the moral teachings of the Christianity that many of them still accepted. Such concerns had already been strongly voiced duringtheseventeenthcentury. Eighteenth-centuryphilosopherscould 6 Introduction therefore draw on the work of predecessors as they sought ways to develop new understandings of morality. The moral philosophies of Reid, Bentham, and Kant are the final eighteenth-century efforts to articulate thenormativebeliefaboutthedignity and worth oftheindi- vidual that led to conceptions of morality as self-governance.4 Kant'sexplanationofthisbeliefwasfullerandmoreradicalthanany other. He alone was proposing a truly revolutionary rethinking of mo- rality. He held that we are self-governingbecauseweare autonomous. By this he meant that we ourselves legislate the moral law. It is only becauseofthelegislativeactionofourownwillthatweareundermoral law; and the same action is what always enables everyone to be law- abiding. Kant was the first to argue for autonomy in this strong sense. His theoryis, ofcourse, ofmore than historical interest. It is morefully involved in current philosophical ethics than is the work of any other early modern thinker, with the possible exception of Hobbes. In the narrative that follows, therefore, I have kept Kant in mind. l\laturally enough this skews my selection ofphilosophers and topics for presen- tation.ButIhavetriedtogiveafairpresentationofthecomplexdebates out ofwhich there emerged the questions Kant tried to answer. Bentham, Reid, and Kant came to questions in moral philosophy withdifferentconcerns aboutpoliticsand religion. Iftheyallreadsome of the same earlier philosophers, continental as well as British, Kant knew the work of others who were not on the British horizon at all. MuchofwhathemadeofmoralphilosophywasshapedbyhisGerman predecessors. Unless we know something about them as well as about themorefamiliar thinkers fromwhomhelearned, wewillnot see how profoundlydifferentthesources werethatcontributed to his invention of autonomy. iii. Morality and religion Conceptions of morality as self-governance reject the inequality of moralcapacityamonghumans thatwasa standard partofconceptions ofmoralityasobedience.WhatistheroleofGodinthesetwofamiliesof conceptions?WhatisthemoralbearingofinequalitybetweenGod and human beings? If God's superiority is not acceptable, must all ties be- tweenmoralityandreligionbesevered?Thedebatesabout theseissues form another major theme in what follows. Eventsoutsideofphilosophyitselfwerelargelyresponsibleforstim- ulatingtherethinking ofmorality that occurred in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. The Reformation and the Counter-Reformation 4 Reid'stheory allowsforself-governancebut,asIpointoutinChapter2o.v,it is notclear that Benthanfsposition does. Modern moral philosophy 7 madeanythingtied toreligionamatterofcontroversy-andeverything was tied to religion.5 The Warfare that racked Europe almost contin- uously from the sixteenth century until the middle of the seventeenth century, and the civil conflicts in Britain that lasted almost until the century's end, were understood in terms of issues about religion. If God's rule oftheworld as transmitted by theclergywas the only hope fororder,itcouldwellseem thatpeacewasnottobeobtained. Morality as interpreted by churches that were themselves rent by sectarian dis- agreements could not provide either an inner sense of community or external constraìnts sufficient to make civilized life possible. Could politics by itself provide those constraìnts? Repressive force could indeed keep the peace for a while. But who was to control such force,and towhatends?Thequestionswerepressing.Thosewhoasked them increasingly wanted to be given reasons for submitting to au- thorities whose traditional standing was no longer enough. Religious controversy affected internal state authority as much as it did interna- tionalaffairs.Newgroupswithineachpolitybegantodemandaccessto power, justifying their claims with theories about how government should be handled and limited, and who should be involved in it. Religious strife undermined the claims of clergy to be the sole au- thorities in morals; political strife led ever more people to demand recognitionasfullycompetenttotakeanactivepartinaffairs. Amoral- ity of self-governance was a better view with which to defend such claims than previously available theories. The need for new generally acceptable justifications of authority and the distribution of power made a rethinking of morality inescapable. Philosophy, appealing to reasonand not to anyauthority, seemed anappropriatesource ofhelp. It is often supposed that the amazing sixteenth- and seventeenth- century developments in science provided the impetus for new efforts in philosophy generally, and as part of that, in philosophical ethics. There is no reason to doubt that the development of science from Copernicus and Galileo through Newton and on into the eighteenth centurywasprofoundlyimportantinshapingthecourseofphilosophy. Butmoralitywould haverequiredreexaminationandreshapingevenif there had been no new science. Without the science, the course that moral philosophy took would no doubt have been quite different. But theproblemsarisingfromreligiousdissensionand fromcallsforwider participation in politics were not themselves due to advances in scien- tific knowledge. And it was the former, not the latter, that primarily gave rise to modern moral philosophy. 5 SeeFebvre1982,chs.9and 1o,forabrilliantdiscussionofhowreligiousbelief so saturated sixteenth-century French vocabulary that it was nearly impossible to think beyond religion, oreven to notice thatone could notdo so.

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.