ebook img

The intrinsic value of nature PDF

160 Pages·1997·34.027 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The intrinsic value of nature

EDITORIAL FOREWORD Leena Vilkka takes us on a critical journey through the forest of distinctions and theories that treat life and nature in terms of values. Such values have been variously proposed as intrinsic, inherent, instrumental, immediate, inherited, absolute, derivative, self-generated, objective, subjective, experiental, personal, biological, social, natural, or global. To this proliferation of ideas, Vilkka brings systematic order and sensitive appraisal. She defines the positions, charts their structures, contrasts their programs, weighs their insights, and corrects their shortcomings. Throughout the philosophical expedition, Vilkka keeps her eye on the living matter that may evade the nets and snares of value-theory. What matters is life. Life has many biological forms, in addition to that form which has been our central concem as theorists and as animals, namely, humanity. Even the Earth might be thought of as a living organism. Often the theories of vailues elaborated by human beings that are applied to life and to nature as a whole give priority to the human species. How could we do otherwise? Even theories that take the extra step of arguing for the rights of other living things may operate by extending a set of human values, as if by generosity, to those who are not human beitigs. The movement is from human rights to the rights of nature. Vilkka calls for a change of persjjective so that we can appreciate the rights of our species, along with the rights of others, as coming under the broader canopy of the value of life. Thus, the rights of nature may give justification to our human rights. Vilkka is not asking us to forget our humanity. She helps us to discover a fuller sense of what is truly valuable in life on this threatened planet. Robert Ginsberg Executive Editor Value Inquiry Book Series One WHAT IS INTRINSIC VALUE? 1. Introduction This book is a theoretical inquiry aimed at forming a theory of the intrinsic value of nature. It provides philosophical arguments for animal preservation and nature preservation. The third task of the book is to persuade its readers to realize the importance of its subject-matter. Most philosophers and scientists do not accept the language of intrinsic value in relation to the non-human world. This book questions two common assumptions: (1) only human beings have intrinsic value; (2) human beings are the origin of all values. I am critical of anthropocentrism, although I propose a form of ecohumanism, which recommends an attitude of respect for animals and nature. The ethical goal, which I have espoused, is the well-being of thé people on Earth and the well-being of the Earth and its diverse life forms, plants and animals. Intrinsic value is a notoriously difficult concept. The debate surrounding this key concept has been confused. Among the authorities in the field of intrinsic value, no agreement has been reached about basic terms, concepts, and ideas. Some good books on intrinsic value exist, although the experts have different views and few attempts have been made to reconcile their individual terminologies (like inherent value, inherent worth). The term "intrinsic value" has become broad and imprecise. Virtually anybody or anything can be the location of intrinsic value or the object of intrinsic valuation: individuals, universals, and wholes, or people, animals, plants, and ecosystems. We need to clarify and classify different forms and meanings of intrinsic value. The search for intrinsic or natural value is the ultimate ground of nature- conservation philosophy. 1 Anthony Weston claims that "it becomes easy to justify respect for other life forms and concern for the natural environment, and indeed many of the standard arguments only become stronger, once the demand to establish intrinsic values is removed."^ I defend the contrary view: we have a substantial need to prove the assumption that the natural world is of worth in itself.3 Intrinsic value in nature is the most fascinating problem of nature-conservation philosophy from the theoretical point of view. The position that we should not attempt to establish the intrinsic value of nature cannot be successful from a practical point of view. We do need a notion of intrinsic value to justify environmental policy for treating the non-human world. Several instrumental human interests occur in the environment: economic, ecological, scientific, religious, cultural, aesthetic, and leisure interests. Non-instrumental human interests in nature are also strong. The willingness of nature activists to preserve nature for its own sake should not be ignored in 4 What Is Intrinsic Value? environmental practice and theory. We need the intrinsic-value view of nature to form a complete frame of nature's values. The basic interests of this book concern animals (other than human beings), living beings, and ecosystems. I offer a naturistic (nature-istic) argument. A humanistic (human-istic) approach would be at stake, if the topics of human beings were made central. My argument is based on the classification between naturocentrism and naturogenic value. Anthropogenic value in nature is a form of value generated by human beings and centered on nature. Naturogenic value is generated by nature. The argument has three components: (1) the ethical and ontological types of intrinsic value in nature (zoocentric and zoogenic value, biocentric and biogenic value, ecocentric and ecogenic value), (2) the specific ideals of intrinsic values (well-being, biodiversity, and beauty), and (3) the generic levels of value in nature (consciousness, livingness, and wholeness). I argue that animals and nature have sufficient intrinsic value that in decision contexts animals and nature should win, since their values have priority over human values. This book is divided into three parts. Part I develops basic concepts and distinctions of intrinsic value. In Part 11, basic nature-centered concems are discussed in detail. Part III is focused to three themes: the origin of value, the problem of priorities between human and natural value, and rights for animals and nature. The purpose of Chapter One is introductory. It defines the basic distinctions and issues posed by the problems of the intrinsic value of nature. In Chapter Two, I distinguish between intrinsic, instrumental, and systemic goodness in nature. Chapter Three continues the classification of intrinsic value in terms of good. Four basic groups are: 1. intrinsic value in terms of experienced-value, 2. intrinsic value in terms of ends-value and of self-value, 3. the group of subjective intrinsic value (subject- centered intrinsic value), and 4. the group of objective intrinsic value (object-centered intrinsic value). Finally, intrinsic value is understood in terms of respect and love for animals and nature. Activists on behalf of animals and of nature express their willingness to preserve nature for its own sake by using the language of intrinsic value. Part II concentrates on three basic topics of nature: animals, life, and nature as a whole. Chapter Four offers the animal-centered philosophy called zoocentrism. I focus on animal well-being, animal subjectivity, and animals as sentient beings. Tom Regan's concept of inherent value of sentient animals is analyzed in detail. Chapter Five proposes the model of biocentrism, life-centered philosophy. Basic questions are "What is life?", and "What is the intrinsic value of life?" Some old philosophical issues of life are fruitful in the modern discussion of biodiversity. I introduce the old principle of plenitude, and the concepts of will to live (Arthur Schopenhauer, 1788-1860) and e'/an v;to/ (Henri Bergson, 1859-1941). The present concept of inherent worth is a part of Paul W. Taylor's biocentrism and is examined in detail. Taylor compares biocentrism to anthropocentrism. Biocentrism regards respect for living nature in the same way as anthropocentrism regards respect for Introduction 5 people. Taylor builds his theory of nature's inherent worth on the concept of the good of each living being. His argument is roughly as follows: if an entity has a good of its own, and if it is better that this good be realized than not be realized, then the entity has inherent worth. For a living entity it will be better that its good be realized than not. Thus, all living organisms have inherent worth. This includes the moral argument that animals and plants should be treated in such a way that their good be realized rather than not. Taylor's individualistic approach is principally challenged by holistic nature thinkers, such as Aldo Leopold (1887-1948) and J. Baird Callicott. Chapter Six considers ecocentrism, the philosophy of ecosystems. Its three sub-forms are divided into anthropogenic holism (J. Baird Callicott), biocentric holism (Lawrence Johnson), and physiocentrism (Klaus Meyer- Abich). In Chapter Seven, I develop my naturistic theory, in the sense of ethical and ontological extensionism and value pluralism. I argue for the existence of intrinsic value in nature, including the intrinsic value of consciousness, life forms, the land, ecosystems, and the earth. This approach develops naturogenic value subdivided into zoogenic, biogenic, and ecogenic value inhering in non-human nature independent of human valuation. The issue of natural beauty is discussed in this chapter. Chapter Eight discusses anthropocentric intrinsic value in nature. Weak anthropocentrists can argue that things other than human beings have intrinsic value, albeit human worth takes priority over the intrinsic value of nature. Ecohumanism is the promising model of weak anthropocentrism in defending both human and natural value. Finally, I offer three types of argument for nature's intrinsic value in relation to rights: the conceptual points of values and rights, the ontology of intrinsic value and moral rights, and the practical preservation utilities arising from the relationship. In Chapter Nine, I argue that our view of the rights of animals and nature depends on our general view of the world, whether it is anthropocentric or naturocentric. We should extend the idea of natural rights to the rights of animals and nature. In recent discussions, no comprehensive book has been written against the intrinsic-value view of nature. The present book defends the pluralism of value and classifies basic forms of value in nature. The notion of intrinsic value related to environmental protection is strikingly new in philosophical discussion. We even cannot argue against the view that such values exist in nature, unless we have suitable theories in the field. My hope is that this book inspires the discussion of intrinsic value.

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.