The Intentional Fallacy Author(s): W. K. Wimsatt Jr. and M. C. Beardsley Source: The Sewanee Review, Vol. 54, No. 3 (Jul. - Sep., 1946), pp. 468-488 Published by: The Johns Hopkins University Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/27537676 Accessed: 15/07/2010 09:38 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=jhup. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. The Johns Hopkins University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Sewanee Review. http://www.jstor.org THE INTENTIONAL FALLACY By W. K. WIMSATT, JR. and M. C. BEARDSLEY He owns with toil he wrote the following scenes; But, if they're naught, ne'er spare him for his pains: Damn him the more; have no commiseration For dullness on mature deliberation. William Congreve, Prologue to The Way of the World THE claim of the author's "intention" upon the critic's judgment has been challenged in a number of recent dis cussions, notably in the debate entitled The Personal Heresy, between Professors Lewis and Tillyard, and at least im plicitly in periodical essays like those in the "Symposiums" of 1940 in the Southern and Kenyon Reviews.1 But it seems doubt ful if this claim and most of its romantic corollaries are as yet subject to any widespread questioning. The present writers, in a short article entitled "Intention" for a Dictionary2 of literary criticism, raised the issue but were unable to pursue its implica tions at any length. We argued that the design or intention of the author is neither available nor desirable as a standard for judging the success of a work of literary art, and it seems to us that this is a principle which goes deep into some differences in the history of critical attitudes. It is a principle which accepted or rejected points to the polar opposites of classical "imitation" and romantic expression. It entails many specific truths about inspiration, authenticity, biography, literary history and scholar ship, and about some trends of contemporary poetry, especially its allusiveness. There is hardly a problem of literary criticism in which the critic's approach will not be qualified by his view of "intention." "Intention," as we shall use the term, corresponds to what he intended in a formula which more or less explicitly has had wide acceptance. "In order to judge the poet's performance, we must WIMSATT AND BEARDSLEY 469 know what he intended." Intention is design or plan in the au thor's mind. Intention has obvious affinities for the author's at titude toward his work, the way he felt, what made him write. We begin our discussion with a series of propositions sum marized and abstracted to a degree where they seem to us axio matic, if not truistic. 1. A poem does not come into existence by accident. The words of a poem, as Professor Stoll has remarked, come out of a head, not out of a hat. Yet to insist on the designing intellect as a cause of a poem is not to grant the design or intention as a standard. 2. One must ask how a critic expects to get an answer to the question about intention. How is he to find out what the poet tried to do? If the poet succeeded in doing it, then the poem itself shows what he was trying to do. And if the poet did not succeed, then the poem is not adequate evidence, and the critic must go outside the poem?for evidence of an intention that did not be come effective in the poem. "Only one caveat must be borne in mind," says an eminent intentionalist3 in a moment when his the ory repudiates itself; "the poet's aim must be judged at the mo ment of the creative act, that is to say, by the art of the poem itself." 3. Judging a poem is like judging a pudding or a machine. One demands that it work. It is only because an artifact works that we infer the intention of an artificer. "A poem should not mean but be." A poem can be only through its meaning?since its medium is words?yet it isy simply is, in the sense that we have no excuse for inquiring what part is intended or meant.4 Poetry is a feat of style by which a complex of meaning is handled all at once. Poetry succeeds because all or most of what is said or implied is relevant; what is irrelevant has been excluded, like lumps from pudding and "bugs" from machinery. In this re spect poetry differs from practical messages, which are success 470 THE INTENTIONAL FALLACY ful if and only if we correctly infer the intention. They are more abstract than poetry. 4. The meaning of a poem may certainly be a personal one, in the sense that a poem expresses a personality or state of soul rather than, a physical object like an apple. But even a short lyric poem is dramatic, the response of a speaker (no matter how abstractly conceived) to a situation (no matter how universal ized). We ought to impute the thoughts and attitudes of the poem immediately to the dramatic speaker, and if to the author at all, only by a biographical act of inference. 5. If there is any sense in which an author, by revision, has better achieved his original intention, it is only the very abstract, tautological, sense that he intended to write a better work and now has done it. (In this sense every author's intention is the same.) His former specific intention was not his intention. "He's the man we were in search of, that's true"; says Hardy's rustic constable, "and yet he's not the man we were in search of. For the man we were in search of was not the man we wanted."5 "Is not a critic," asks Professor Stoll, "... a judge, who does not explore his own consciousness, but determines the author's meaning or intention, as if the poem were a will, a contract, or the constitution? The poem is not the critic's own."8 He has diagnosed very accurately two forms of irresponsibility, one which he prefers. Our view is yet different. The poem is not the critic's own and not the author's (it is detached from the author at birth and goes about the world beyond his power to intend about it or control it). The poem belongs to the public. It is embodied in language, the peculiar possession of the public, and it is about the human being, an object of public knowledge. What is said about the poem is subject to the same scrutiny as any statement in linguistics or in the general science of psychology or morals. Mr. Richards has aptly called the poem a class? "a class of experiences which do not differ in any character more WIMSATT AND BEARDSLEY 471 than a certain amount . . . from a standard experience." And he adds, "We may take as this standard experience the relevant experience of the poet when contemplating the completed com position." Professor Wellek in a fine essay on the problem has preferred to call the poem "a system of norms," "extracted from every individual experience," and he objects to Mr. Richards' deference to the poet as reader. We side with Professor Wellek in not wishing to make the poet (outside the poem) an authority. A critic of our Dictionary article, Mr. Ananda K. Coomara swamy, has argued7 that there are two kinds of enquiry about a wrork of art: (1) whether the artist achieved his intentions; (2) whether the work of art "ought ever to have been undertaken at all" and so "whether it is worth preserving." Number (2), Mr. Coomaraswamy maintains, is not "criticism of any work of art qua work of art," but is rather moral criticism; number (1) is artistic criticism. But we maintain that (2) need not be moral criticism: that there is another way of deciding whether works of art are worth preserving and whether, in a sense, they "ought" to have been undertaken, and this is the way of objective criticism of works of art as such, the way which enables us to distinguish between a skilful murder and a skilful poem. A skilful murder is an example which Mr. Coomaraswamy uses, and in his system the difference between the murder and the poem is simply a "moral" one, not an "artistic" one, since each if carried out ac cording to plan is "artistically" successful. We maintain that (2) is an enquiry of more worth than (1), and since (2), and not (1) is capable of distinguishing poetry from murder, the name "artistic criticism" is properly given to (2). II It is not so much an empirical as an analytic judgment, not a historical statement, but a definition, to say that the intentional fallacy is a romantic one. When a rhetorician, presumably of the first century A.D., writes: "Sublimity is the echo of a great soul," 472 THE INTENTIONAL FALLACY or tells us that "Homer enters into the sublime actions of his heroes" and "shares the full inspiration of the combat," we shall not be surprised to find this rhetorician considered as a distant harbinger of romanticism and greeted in the warmest terms by so romantic a critic as Saintsbury. One may wish to argue whether Longinus should be called romantic,8 but there can hardly be a doubt that in one important way he is. Goethe's three questions for "'constructive criticism" are "What did the author set out to do? Was his plan reasonable and sensi ble, and how far did he succeed in carrying it out?" If one leaves out the middle question, one has in effect the system of Croce? the culmination and crowning philosophic expression of roman ticism. The beautiful is the successful and intuition-expression, the ugly is the unsuccessful; the intuition or private part of art it the aesthetic fact, and the medium or public part in not the subject of aesthetic at all. Yet aesthetic reproduction takes place only "if all the other conditions remain equal." Oil-paintings grow dark, frescoes fade, statues lose noses . . . the text of a poem is corrupted by bad copyists or bad print ing. The Madonna of Cimabue is still in the Church of Santa Maria Novella; but does she speak to the visitor of to-day as to the Florentines of the thirteenth century? Historical interpretation labours ... to reintegrate in us the conditions which have in the course psychological changed of history. It . . . enables us to see a work of art (a physical as its author saw it in the moment of object) production.9 The first italics are Croce's, the second ours. The upshot of Croce's system is an ambiguous emphasis on history. With such passages as a point of departure a critic may write a close analysis of the meaning or "spirit" of a play of Shakespeare or Corneille ?a process that involves close historical study but remains aes WIMSATT AND BEARDSLEY 473 thetic criticism?or he may write sociology, biography, or other kinds of non-aesthetic history. The Crocean system seems to have given more of a boost to the latter way of writing. "What has the poet tried to do," asks Spingarn in his 1910 Columbia Lecture from which we have already quoted, "and how has he fulfilled his intention?" The place to look for "in superable" ugliness, says Bosanquet, in his third Lecture of 1914, is the "region of insincere and affected art." The seepage of the theory into a non-philosophic place may be seen in such a book as Marguerite Wilkinson's inspirational New Voices, about the poetry of 1919 to 1931?where symbols "as old as the ages . . . retain their strength and freshness" through "Realization." We close this section with two examples from quarters where one might least expect a taint of the Crocean. Mr. I. A. Richards' fourfold distinction of meaning into "sense," "feeling," "tone," "intention" has been probably the most influential statement of intentionalism in the past fifteen years, though it contains a hint of self-repudiation: "This function [intention]," says Mr. Rich ards, "is not on all fours with the others." In an essay on "Three Types of Poetry" Mr. Allen T?te writes as follows: We must understand that the lines Life like a dome of many-colored glass Stains the white radiance of eternity are not poetry; they express the frustrated will trying to compete with science. The will asserts a rhetorical proposition about the whole of life, but the imagination has not seized upon the mater ials of the poem and made them into a whole. Shel ley's simile is imposed upon the material from above; it does not grow out of the material. The last sentence contains a promise of objective analysis which is not fulfilled. The reason why the essay relies so heavily throughout on the terms "will" and "imagination" is that Mr. T?te is accusing the romantic poets of a kind of insincerity (ro 474 THE INTENTIONAL FALLACY manticism in reverse) and at the same time is trying to describe something mysterious and perhaps indescribable, an "imaginative whole of life," a "wholeness of vision at a particular moment of experience," something which "yields us the quality of the experience." If a poet had a toothache at the moment of con ceiving a poem, that would be part of the experience, but Mr. T?te of course does not mean anything like that. He is think ing about some kind of "whole" which in this essay at least he does not describe, but which doubtless it is the prime need of criticism to describe?in terms that may be publicly tested. Ill I went to the poets; tragic, dithyrambic, and all sorts. . . . I took them some of the most elaborate passages in their own writings, and asked what was the meaning of them. . . . Will you believe me? . . . there is hardly a person present who would not have talked better about their poetry than they did themselves. Then I knew that not by wisdom do poets write poetry, but by a sort of genius and inspiration. That reiterated mistrust of the poets which we hear from Socrates mav have been part of a rigorously ascetic view in which we hardly wish to participate, yet Plato's Socrates saw a truth about the mind which the world no sees? poetic longer commonly so much criticism, and that the most inspirational and most affec tionately remembered, has proceeded from the poets themselves. Certainly the poets have had something to say that the ana lyst and professor could not say; their message has been more exciting: that poetry should come as naturally as leaves to a tree, that poetry is the lava of the imagination, or that it is emotion recollected in tranquillity. But it is necessary that we realize the character and authority of such testimony. There is only a fine shade between those romantic expressions and a kind of earnest advice that authors often give. Thus Edward Young, Carlyle, Walter Pater: WIMSATT AND BEARDSLEY 475 I know two golden rules from ethicsy which are no less golden in Composition, than in life. 1. Know thyself; 2dly, Reverence thyself. This is the grand secret for finding readers and retaining them: let him who would move and convince others, be first moved and convinced himself. Horace's rule, Si vis me is in a wider sense than the literal one. To flerey applicable every poet, to every writer, we might say: Be true, if you would be believed. Truth! there can be no merit, no craft at all, without that. And further, all beauty is in the long run only fineness of truth, or what we call expression, the finer accommodation of speech to that vision within. And Housman's little handbook to the mind the poetic yields illustration: following Having drunk a pint of beer at luncheon?beer is a sedative to the brain, and my afternoons are the least intellectual portion of my life?I would go out for a walk of two or three hours. As I went along, thinking of nothing in par ticular, only looking at things around me and following the progress of the seasons, there would flow into my mind, writh sudden and unaccountable emotion, sometimes a line or two of verse, sometimes a whole stanza at once. . . . This is the logical terminus of the series already quoted. Here is a confession of how poems were written which would do as a definition of poetry just as well as "emotion recollected in tranquillity"?and which the young poet might equally well take to heart as a practical rule. Drink a pint of beer, relax, go walking, think on nothing in particular, look at things, surrender yourself to yourself, search for the truth in your own soul, listen to the sound of your own inside voice, discover and express the vraie v?rit?. 2 476 THE INTENTIONAL FALLACY It is probably true that all this is excellent advice for poets. The young imagination fired by Wordsworth and Carlyle is probably closer to the verge of producing a poem than the mind of the student who has been sobered by Aristotle or Richards. The art of inspiring poets, or at least of inciting something like poetry in young persons, has probably gone further in our day than ever before. Books of creative writing such as those issued from the Lincoln School are interesting evidence of what a child can do if taught how to manage himself honestly.10 All this, however, would appear to belong to an art separate from criticism, or to a discipline which one might call the psychology of com position, valid and useful, an individual and private culture, yoga, or system of self-development which the young poet would do well to notice, but different from the public science of evaluating poems, Coleridge and Arnold were better critics than most poets have been, and if the critical tendency dried up the poetry in Arnold and perhaps in Coleridge, it is not inconsistent with our argu ment, which is that judgment of poems is different from the art of producing them. Coleridge has given us the classic "anodyne" story, and tells what he can about the genesis of a poem which he calls a "psychological curiosity," but his definitions of poetry and of the poetic quality "imagination" are to be found else where and in quite other terms. The day may arrive when the psychology of composition is unified with the science of objective evaluation, but so far they are separate. It would be convenient if the passwords of the intentional school, "sincerity," "fidelity," "spontaneity," "au thenticity," "genuineness," "originality," could be equated with terms of analysis such as "integrity," "relevance," "unity," "func tion"; with "maturity," "subtlety," and "adequacy," and other more precise axiological terms?in short, if "expression" always meant aesthetic communication. But this is not so. "Aesthetic" art, says Professor Curt Ducasse, an ingenious