ebook img

The Genealogy of Disjunction PDF

357 Pages·1994·21.24 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The Genealogy of Disjunction

The Genealogy of Disjunction This page intentionally left blank The Genealogy of Disjunction R. E. JENNINGS New York Oxford OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS 1994 Oxford University Press Oxford New York Athens Auckland Bangkok Bombay Calcutta Cape Town Dar es Salaam Delhi Florence Hong Kong Istanbul Karachi Kuala Lumpur Madras Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Nairobi Paris Singapore Taipei Tokyo Toronto and associated companies in Berlin Ibadan Copyright © 1994 by R. E. Jennings Published by Oxford University Press, Inc., 200 Madison Avenue, New York, New York 10016 Oxford is a registered trademark of Oxford University Press All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, without the prior permission of Oxford University Press Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Jennings, R. E. (Raymond Earl) The genealogy of disjunction / R. E. Jennings, p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-19-507524-2 1. Disjunction (Logic) 2. Or (The English word) I. Title. BC199.D56J46 1994 160—dc20 93-11592 987654321 Printed in the United States of America on acid-free paper For Hugues Leblanc This page intentionally left blank Preface Gilbert Ryle has remarked that the difference between philosophers and formal logicians is akin to the distinction between explorers of the moors and operators of tramways. The sensitive research logician may puzzle whether to accept the wayfarer's innocent admiration and wave back or to say something clever to disarm the social irony. For he is as likely as not to think of himself more on a footing with designers of tramways than with their operators, more on a social level with consultant to the corporation than with liveried employee. But the metaphor is more fundamentally misleading, and not intended as a slight. Much of the product of logical research has little anymore to do with secure inferential conveyance. Even the little light that might once have fallen fleetingly but usefully upon a ditch or a dead sheep shifts remorselessly ever toward the infrared. The vehicle is anymore only a logically possible tram. Ryle's imagery is, however, vividly correct in one particular: logic in its usual presentation is a recent invention, in fact, not much older than the tram. And, even if neglectfully of some of the newer track, he rightfully regards logic as, like the tram, restricted in the manner of its service. But again, as it places the logician too close to the ground, the imagery locates his philosopher wrongly in a wild, not urban landscape. The philosopher's problem is not one of finding unfamiliar things to prod. His subject matter crowds him round. If it is perplexing, it is so not because it is alien, but because it is human and so familiar. The difficulty is that, at the level at which we want understanding, we do not understand the linguistic things that we do or how we do them. If a geographical image is sought, let it be the image of a cityscape filled with long evolved, albeit human contrivances, so far removed from their original materials and uses that, though everyday they serve our purposes, we can no longer fit their form to their function. This book is an attempt to say how some of our logical vocabulary works in discourse. Its central subject matter is the word 'or', but the approach that it finally advocates it advocates for the study of other such vocabulary as well. 'Or' presents some curious and easily illustrated puzzles, that, possibly because they have not been recognized for what they are, have not been the source of entrenched philosophical doctrine. In this respect, 'or', unlike 'if, really is, to revert to something like Ryle's metaphor, virgin territory. There is yet time to save it from development, and from what seems to me to have been, in the case of 'if, the monopolistic application of wrong methods. My own perplexities about 'or' were sown in 1964 by a reading of von Wright's Logic of Preference and provided some of the subject matter for two theses, an M.A. thesis at Queen's University written under the supervision of the late Jon Wheatley and a Ph.D. thesis at the University of London under the su- Preface viii pervision of Bernard Williams. In the second, I proposed essentially the account of the puzzling conjunctive uses of 'or' that is further elaborated here, as well as the derivative account of the 'any/every' distinction that is the core of the one contained in this essay. But the punctuational explanation, as far as it had got, was unsatisfying inasmuch as it seemed unconnected with what I took to be the usual sentential uses that I simply assumed to be disjunctive. And there were other things to do. Several developments persuaded me to take it all up once again. The first was the large literature on 'if', a subject being called the logic of conditionals, that had never received the kind of simple-hearted scrutiny that had revealed so much that was perplexing about 'or'. The nearest to an analogous literature on 'or', as it seemed from the almost ostentatious isolation of academic philosophy, was pullulating within the confines of deontic logic under the heading of 'free choice permission'. It may be that no one had noticed essen- tially the same and odder features in the behaviour of 'or' throughout its uses in English, else there might have come into existence something calling itself the logic of disjunctions. News of the existence of a Counter-Earth in which lin- guists, with a much broader landscape in view, had been puzzling over the very problems that I had so long ago set aside reached me late in my application of CPR to older work. As might be expected, different starting points had yielded different emphases, though there had as well been some points of contact. In addition, the aims of the linguists were at an angle oblique to the aim of this essay: to try to say how we come to have a notion of logical disjunction. Much of the linguists' thinking about 'or', it seems, has had the truth-tabular V as one of its light sources, so that the ideas of disjunction and set-theoretic union contribute perceptibly to its cast. So while I have tried to acknowledge points of contact and parallel developments, it has seemed best not to seem to be offering this essay as a response to current linguistic approaches, but to address myself to the philosophical problem I have set. Linguists by now are surely justified in assuming title to this portion of the moor and may, come to that, have their own ideas about which is Earth and which Counter-Earth. So I beg their indulgence as a former denizen if I seem to wander their marches in a stupor and to see the landscape as it was. Two recent developments within linguistics have seemed to confirm this course. The first is Victor Dudman's investigation of if... then . . . sentences which has brought us back from rhapsodic mythologizing about conditionals to something like simple systematic observation of if-clauses as adverbial modifications. The second is Laurence Horn's study of negation, which, in questioning the centrality of sentence-negation, provides a confirming datum to the view I shall put forward. Within this family of studies, as I hope to have demonstrated, 'or' deserves a volume to itself. If this work forestalls a wholly unwarranted development of logics of funny disjunctions, it will have served one of the purposes for its existence. The second reason lies in the growing abundance of logic textbooks retailing wholly gratuitous (and with a moment's reflection, perfectly apparent) falsehoods about the relationship between the disjunction of prepositional logic and the 'or' of English (and some of its counterparts in Latin), and that to no very important expository end. It seemed worthwhile to register the errors in an ix Preface essay large enough to discuss a sufficiency of convincing examples and also begin a more plausible alternative account. The third reason arises out of the second. As it seems from its fringe, emerging research in computer discourse generation is ill served by the prejudice, which the glib myth making of the logic texts tends to instil, that the central uses of 'or' and other 'logical' vocabulary of natural language are wholly to be accounted for by a truth conditional theory along the lines of formal semantics. To the extent that such research programmes are aided by possession of the right general principles, it seems worthwhile to try to pick out the regularities that a proper set of principles would codify and above all, to try to get right the vocabulary of the observation language. If an instructively oversimple slogan were to emerge from my efforts and be offered as amicular advice to discourse generation researchers, along the lines of the earlier 'Don't ask for the meaning; ask for the use', it would be 'Mainly we emit sounds'. In trying to understand, in a usefully general way, the sounds that we make, the pragmatic notions of discourse status and discourse adverbiality, however im- perfectly formulated here, are likely to be more central than the notion of truth conditions, which after all applies only to theoretical entities of dubious origins whose relationship even to the narrow range of indicative speech that it is taken to explain is as tenuous as it is mysterious. In the end, whether it has been worthwhile to write so long a book about so short a word is for the reader, not the writer, to say. But the writer, who best knows the reason for the work, is best placed to offer negative criteria of adequacy. One would be this: if the essay does not suggest strongly to the reader that a large part of our so-called logical vocabulary comes to its present uses from metalinguistic applications of the language of physical relationship, and that in much of its ordinary use it retains the kind of adverbiality that is claimed here for 'or', then I will have missed my mark. Second, if it does not demonstrate convincingly the worth of simply trying to sort out how the same logical vocabulary works in discourse, then it will have been insufficient means to one of its ends. No part of its task is to attempt a formal representation within logical theory, rather the reverse. I am indebted to the late Jon Wheatley, who encouraged me to enter Philosophy and who supervised the earlier thesis, to Bernard Williams, who supervised the second, and the late Arthur Prior who examined it, to Risto Hilpinen, who encouraged me to take the project up again, or at the very least to publish the earlier work as an historical curiosity. In the course of writing and presenting to various forums what eventually became the present document, many colleagues have offered invaluable criticisms and advice and asked useful questions. Among them I should mention (in more or less chronological order) Rolf George, Max Cresswell, Peter Schotch, Jeff Pelletier, Johan van Benthem, Souren Teghrarian, Robert O'Toole, Hugues Leblanc, Michael Dowad, Robin Taylor, Charles Travis, Dorothy Edgington, Martin Hahn, Norman Swartz, and Mary Shaw. I especially wish to thank an anonymous Oxford University Press referee for useful truths about the state of the academic solar system and many detailed bibliographical and substantial suggestions.

Description:
This is a comprehensive study of the English word or, and the logical operators variously proposed to present its meaning. Although there are indisputably disjunctive uses of or in English, it is a mistake to suppose that logical disjunction represents its core meaning. Or is descended from the Angl
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.