ebook img

The Experience of Truth PDF

136 Pages·2017·0.883 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The Experience of Truth

The Experience of Truth SUNY series in Contemporary Italian Philosophy Silvia Benso and Brian Schroeder, editors The Experience of Truth Gaetano Chiurazzi Translated by Robert T. Valgenti Published by State University of New York Press, Albany © 2011 Mimesis Edizioni, L'esperienza della verità © 2017 State University of New York All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America No part of this book may be used or reproduced in any manner whatsoever without written permission. No part of this book may be stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means including electronic, electrostatic, magnetic tape, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise without the prior permission in writing of the publisher. For information, contact State University of New York Press, Albany, NY www.sunypress.edu Production, Jenn Bennett Marketing, Michael Campochiaro Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Names: Chiurazzi, Gaetano, author. Title: The experience of truth / Gaetano Chiurazzi ; English translation by Robert T. Valgenti. Other titles: L'esperienza della verità. Italian Description: Albany, NY : State University of New York, 2017. | Series: SUNY series in contemporary Italian philosophy | Includes bibliograph- ical references and index. Identifiers: LCCN 2016047189 (print) | LCCN 2017039126 (ebook) | ISBN 9781438466460 (e-book) | ISBN 9781438466453 (hardcover : alk. paper) Subjects:  LCSH: Truth. Classification: LCC BD171 (ebook) | LCC BD171 .C5413 2017 (print) | DDC 121—dc23 LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2016047189 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Contents Introduction vii Chapter 1 Before Judgment 1 Judgment and Truth 1 Hypárchein en tiní: Ontological Antecedence 2 Hypárchein tiní: The Essential Antecedence 4 The Inesse: From Boethius to Leibniz 7 The Presupposition of Truth 10 Chapter 2 Verbum Consignificat Tempus 13 The Nominal Phrase: The Presence and the Absence of 13 the Copula The Elimination of the Copula: Truth without Time 18 Signifying the Non-objectual: Synthesis and Time 21 The Speculative Proposition: The Time of Knowing 25 From Time to Consignificatio Existentiae 29 Chapter 3 The Experience of Truth as the Experience of Time 33 The Form of Truth: Deixis and the Elliptical Character 33 of Judgment Correspondence and Metaphysics 35 Beyond Parmenides: Excess as Future and Anticipation 37 The Ontological Background of Alétheia: Ontology of 41 the Possible v (cid:2) (cid:3) vi Contents Chapter 4 Truth and Transformation 45 Truth Changes 45 The Pragmatization of Hermeneutics 46 The Hermeneuticization of Pragmatism 48 The Truth of Experience: The Myth of the Cave 50 The “Anticonformist” Character of Truth 53 Chapter 5 More Than the Real 57 The Extra-Methodicalness of Truth as the Objectivity 57 of Happening The Abstraction of the Experimental Consciousness 60 and the Temporality of Presentation Truth as Transmutation into Form 64 Formation as Elevation to an Intensional Universality 69 Chapter 6 The Sense of Truth 73 Force and Interpretation 73 An Experimental Ontology 76 For Whom Is Truth? 78 Chapter 7 A Non-alienated Conception of Truth 83 The Form of Truth: Truth and Experiential Realism 83 Against the Equivalence-Thesis 87 Beyond Domination: Truth as Countervailing Power 90 Notes and Bibliography 97 Index 117 Introduction Today one can say of truth what Kant wrote about metaphysics in 1787, namely, that “the changed fashion of the time brings her only scorn; a matron outcast and forsaken, she mourns like Hecuba.”1 And the brief yet effective chronicle of the destiny of metaphysics that Kant traces in the lines imme- diately following this passage could also be adapted nicely to the destiny of truth: Her government, under the administration of the dogmatists, was at first despotic. But inasmuch as the legislation still bore traces of the ancient bar- barism, her empire gradually through intestine wars gave way to complete anarchy; and the sceptics, a species of nomads, despising all settled modes of life, broke up from time to time all civil society.2 The contemporary debate over truth seems to be caught in a similar sit- uation: between the defense of the metaphysical meaning of truth and its complete negation, between dogmatism and skepticism, or even between absolutism and relativism.3 However, as Kant attempted in his critique, one ought to ask if the negation of metaphysical knowledge is in fact the negation of all knowledge tout court, or if instead this brings about the val- orization of a more “terrestrial,” physical, form of knowledge that, as Kant would say, is limited to the field of possible experience. The expression “expe- rience of truth” is assumed in this book to have a similar intent, and above all to mark a problematic question: whether it makes any sense to speak of truth as something potentially extraneous to our experience in general, or whether it is not instead something intrinsic and constitutive of our expe- rience, real or possible. vii (cid:2) (cid:3) viii Introduction In fact it is the return to experience that allows Kant to separate himself both from dogmatic rationalism and also skeptical empiricism, and to resolve, on these grounds, the conflict of reason. The goal of this book is to adopt a strategy similar to the one Kant uses in relation to metaphysics: bringing the problem of truth back to experience, intended not solely in epistemological terms but as the background that constitutes—and results from—every one of our relations with the world. This occurs in the way that Hegel, after Kant, utilized the term: “experience” is for Hegel a formative journey, which implicates not only our relation to the natural world, to objects, but also our relation to the human world, to others and to those “spiritual objects” that are cultural formations. In my view, the hermeneutic treatment of truth has to be set against such a background. “The experience of truth” is in fact a recurring expression in philosophical hermeneutics: Heidegger refers to the “primordial” experi- ence of truth that the Greeks had when he seeks to illustrate the significance of the word alétheia; Gadamer refers to the concrete experience of historical life in his attempt to rehabilitate an extra-methodical dimension of truth that supports the claim to truth of the human sciences.4 A hermeneutic con- ception of the experience of truth first of all requires a clarification of the hermeneutic conception of experience, such as the one Gadamer sets forth in the second part of Truth and Method. This makes it possible to avoid the risk of intuitionism,5 namely, to avoid considering the hermeneutic notion of truth as alétheia or disclosedness as another formulation of the phenom- enological concept of “evidence.” For Husserl, evidence is not Cartesian certitude, the imposition upon consciousness of an absolutely true content, but is the pure givenness—the “in the flesh”—of something to consciousness: To speak of self-evidence, of self-evident givenness, then, here signifies nothing other than self-givenness, the way in which an object in its given- ness can be characterized relative to consciousness as “itself there,” “there in the flesh,” in contrast to its mere presentification [Vergegenwärtigung], the empty, merely indicative idea of it.6 In comparison to this objectivistic conception of evidence as the appre- hension of something simple7 given to consciousness, in Heidegger evidence is thought rather as a “coming foremost into view.” It is defined in relation to a background, as occurs in a game between two elements or between two levels. Now, if there is a difference that radically distinguishes intuition (cid:2) (cid:3) Introduction ix from understanding, it is precisely the fact that the former concerns simple objects and the latter concerns relations,8 namely, senses, understood as forms or modes of relating to something rather than as objects to which a noun refers. In experience, understood in this way and thus in hermeneutical terms as a phenomenon of understanding, we are no longer dealing with objects, but above all with senses, relations, which in turn are only defined on the basis of a point of coordination, namely, the origin-point that for Heidegger is Dasein. The way that Heidegger develops his “existential analytic” not only recalls a similar chapter in Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason entitled “The Analytic of Concepts”; I believe it also recalls certain assumptions of the modern sci- entific revolution that derive from Descartes. Analytic geometry has shown that it is possible to describe the world not by describing objects, but relations: in order to do this, it is no longer necessary to make reference to some essences, but rather it is necessary to single out an Archimedean point, an origin-point, from which such relations can be established. The deictic definition of Dasein that Heidegger gives in Being and Time is, in my view, nothing other than the transposition onto a semantic plane of the revolution brought about by Descartes’s analytic geometry in the physical field: the describability of the world (understood as a web of senses) is grounded in the same principle that allows the describability of physical space—the definition of an origin-point. In my view, one can thus with good reason speak of a “Cartesian aspect” in Heidegger, which does not consist in the resumption of the metaphysics of the cogito, as happens with Husserl, even if it lacks its apodictic moment, but in the resumption of the methodological formulation of analytic geome- try: the invention of a system of coordinates that for Heidegger have their zero point in Dasein, namely, in that “absolute deixis” that is the Sum. According to Heidegger, no description of the world can leave out the deictic reference to this Sum. The result of this “semantic schema” is that there is no longer sense9 (and therefore, a fortiori, truth) without Dasein, which involves neither a negation nor a subjectification of truth, but the elaboration of a concept of truth formally more complex than the traditional version,10 more complex than the representational notion of truth, understood thus as the simple cor- respondence to sensorial data or a state of affairs. Only in this way can the full semantic content of truth finally be appreciated. What in fact do we mean when we say that something “is true”? A hermeneutic approach to the problem of truth must begin with this question, which is not the question “what is” truth, but rather a question about its significance in our experience. Posing the question in these terms

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.