THE DEEP ECOLOGY OF RHETORIC IN MENCIUS AND ARISTOTLE SUNY series in Chinese Philosophy and Culture Roger T. Ames, editor THE DEEP ECOLOGY OF RHETORIC IN MENCIUS AND ARISTOTLE A SOMATIC GUIDE DOUGLAS ROBINSON Published by State University of New York Press, Albany © 2016 State University of New York All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America No part of this book may be used or reproduced in any manner whatsoever without written permission. No part of this book may be stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means including electronic, electrostatic, magnetic tape, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise without the prior permission in writing of the publisher. For information, contact State University of New York Press, Albany, NY www.sunypress.edu Production, Ryan Morris Marketing, Fran Keneston Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Names: Robinson, Douglas, 1954– author. Title: The deep ecology of rhetoric in Mencius and Aristotle : a somatic guide / Douglas Robinson. Description: Albany : State University of New York Press, 2016. | Series: SUNY series in Chinese philosophy and culture | Includes bibliographical references and index. Identifiers: LCCN 2015027115 | ISBN 9781438461076 (hardcover : alk. paper) | ISBN 9781438461083 (e-book) Subjects: LCSH: Mencius—Criticism and interpretation. | Rhetoric, Ancient. | Aristotle— Criticism and interpretation. | Persuasion (Rhetoric)—History—To 1500. Classification: LCC B128.M324 R63 2016 | DDC 181/.112—dc23 LC record available at http://lccn.loc.gov/2015027115 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Contents Preface 1 Mencius and Aristotle as “Deep-Ecological” Theorists of Rhetoric 2 The Group Subject of Persuasion 3 Energy Channeled through Body Language 4 The Circulation of Social Value 5 Conclusion: Aristotle and Mencius on Ecosis Notes Glossary References Index Preface Scope of the Study This book explores a confluence of five different fields of study, namely rhetoric, deep ecology, somatic theory, Aristotle and ancient Greek philosophy, and Mencius and early Confucianism: rhetoric (§1.1) is traditionally the study of persuasion, and specifically of the structures and forms of persuasive discourse; the deep ecology of rhetoric suggests a broader and more holistic understanding of persuasion, or “persuasivity” (to pithanon), as part of the circulation through groups of evaluative affect-becoming- conation (see the Glossary) deep ecology (§1.1): as founded by the Norwegian philosopher Arne Naess, deep ecology is the study of the “Self-realization” of the ecological self, a concept derived from a number of sources, including Zen Buddhism, Spinoza, and Gandhi; lurking behind his conception of Self-realization as “realizing inherent potentialities,” however, is Aristotle’s notion of the entelekheia or entelechy; qì- driven moral maturation or self-realization is also Mencius’s focal concern somatics (§1.2): somatic theory studies the circulation of evaluative affect through groups as the primary channel of social regulation; to the extent that the deep ecology of rhetoric is an affective social ecology, it is specifically a somatic ecology, or what I call in §4.12 a somatic exchange Aristotle (§1.2–3, §1.5): the Athenian philosopher (384–322 BCE), considered the most important Platonist thinker after Plato himself, and in many ways more important, as he turned his master on his head—in ways that are remarkably reminiscent of Mencius, his near-contemporary Mencius (§1.3–5): the Chinese philosopher (ca. 372–ca. 303 BCE), considered the most important Confucian thinker after Confucius himself, and in many ways more important, as he expanded and complicated the basic Confucian concepts in salutary ways The sequence in which those fields appear in the list reflects something like my expertise and argumentative priorities in this book: I admire Mencius and Aristotle, consider myself something of a follower of both, but I am very far from being an expert in either, or in classical Chinese or Attic Greek; I mostly construct the two thinkers as guides to my main concern, namely the deep somatic ecology of rhetoric. I do firmly believe that my reading of the two contemporaries is fundamentally on target—that I am not willfully distorting their thought to suit my argumentative purposes—but I am not a trained Sinologist, Hellenist, or Sino-Hellenist. I have put in the requisite time with the bilingual dictionaries and other lexical tools designed specifically for the study of classical Chinese and Attic Greek, as well as with the last few decades of scholarship (in English) on both thinkers; my research assistant Rico Chung and various Chinese friends and colleagues have tracked down and in some cases translated important scholarly sources for me in Chinese; I have engaged the various English translations critically, even perhaps tenaciously, reading them stereoscopically against both the originals and (here and there) their classical commentators; and my Acknowledgments record my great debt to the scholars of ancient Greek, classical Chinese, and both philosophical traditions who have checked my claims about both the meanings of words and phrases in context and the philosophical positions both thinkers adopt. My readings of specific passages are on the whole tendentious, and perhaps lean more toward the radical than toward the conservative; but I would not call them idiosyncratic. My reading of Aristotle is closely aligned with the readings offered by Nancy Sherman (1989) and Jeffrey Walker (2000, 2008), for example; and my reading of Mencius is
Description: