ebook img

The Critical Modernism of Hannah Arendt PDF

26 Pages·2006·0.1 MB·English
by  
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The Critical Modernism of Hannah Arendt

Theoretical Inquiries in Law 8.1 (2007) The Critical Modernism of Hannah Arendt Mark Antaki* Hannah Arendt grasps modernity in terms of crisis and political modernity in terms of the crisis of authority. Because she ties the crisis of authority not simply to liberal political thought but to the entireWesternphilosophicaltradition,Arendtrespondstothecrisisof authoritywithacriticalmodernism,i.e.,amodernismthatseekstolay barethegapbetweenpastandfuturethatwascoveredupbytheRoman trilogyoftradition,religion,andauthority.Thismodernismiscritical because it intensifies rather than shies away from crisis. With this critical modernism, judgment emerges as the successor to authority, opening the door to a possible overcoming of metaphysics and of the estrangement of doing and thinking. Arendt’s reworking of a parable ofKafka’sdealingwiththegapbetweenpastandfutureillustratesher turntojudgmentandherattempttoovercomemetaphysics. I. CRITIQUEANDCRISIS I nhisaccount ofthe"pathogenesisofmodernsociety,"ReinhartKoselleck argued that the "critical process of enlightenment conjured up the crisis" of modernity.1 In his account, as in others, the modern position of critique * Assistant Professor, Faculty of Law, McGill University. I would like to thank Kirsten Anker, Shai Lavi, and Alexandra Popovici for their helpful comments on various drafts of this paper. I would also like to thank the participants in the CriticalModernities:PoliticsandLawBeyondtheLiberalImaginationCeglaCenter conferenceattheUniversityofTelAviv.Inparticular,IwouldliketothankAnnabel Herzogwhograciouslycommentedonmypresentationofapreviousversionofthis paper. In her remarks, she rightly emphasized Arendt’s intellectual debt to Walter Benjamin.IamafraidIdidnoteventrytodojusticetothisrelationinthepresent text. 1 REINHART KOSELLECK, CRITIQUE AND CRISIS: ENLIGHTENMENT AND THE PATHOGENESISOFMODERNSOCIETY11(1988). 252 TheoreticalInquiriesinLaw [Vol.8:251 engendersthemodernconditionofcrisis.Modernismleads,orcontributes,to modernity.2InKoselleck’sstory,themoderncriticsubjectspoliticalauthority to relentless criticism but is unable to erect anything in its place except for a utopian philosophy of history that is alienated from the standpoint and constraintsofpractical,politicalaction.Thethemeofthedemiseofpolitical authority in the face of critique, the theme of the displacement of politics by an abstract and moralizing worldview, echoes not only the work of Carl Schmitt(anditspolemicsagainstliberalism)butalsothatofHannahArendt. Abstractthoughtdisplacesaproperunderstandingofconcreteaction.Inthe work of these authors, the modern condition appears not merely as one in whichpoliticalauthorityhasbeenlostormisapprehendedbutalsoasonein whichthe political itself — and for Hannah Arendt, political freedom — is threatenedwithloss andmisapprehension.3 Because she was a reader of Nietzsche, however, Arendt’s diagnosis of the critical condition of modernity leads to the observation that, to paraphrase Bruno Latour,4 "we have not been modern enough." Though Arendt’s modernism has been described — and with some reason — as "reluctant,"5 Arendt’s modernism (her position) in the face of modernity (our condition) is also "critical," one that calls for more, not less, critical thinking.Arendt’sturntothenegativepowerofcritiqueisnecessarytomake roomforjudgment.Indeed,ourwordsforcritiqueandcrisiscomefromthe Greekkrinein, which signifies discrimination or judgment.6Rediscovering the faculty of judgment can rescue us from the crisis of political authority and,moreimportantly,fromthatofthepolitical.Critiquefreesupthespace ofpracticalaction,exposesthegap,thenothing,inwhichhumanbeingsmust dwell. But critique misunderstands its task when it goes further. The space openedupbycritiqueisnottobefilledwiththe"fruits"ofcriticalthinking— forcriticalthinkingbearsnotangible"fruits"—butistobeconfrontedwith thehelpofthefacultyofjudgment,thatmentalfacultywhichismostworldly, 2 On the contrast of modernity and modernism, of condition and position, see Mark Antaki, Leading Modernity (To) A-Ground, 19 AUSTL. FEMINIST L.J. 115 (2003), whichengagesPETERFITZPATRICK,MODERNISMANDTHEGROUNDSOFLAW(2001). 3 See alsoSHELDONS.WOLIN, POLITICSANDVISION: CONTINUITYANDINNOVATION INWESTERNPOLITICALTHOUGHT (2004) (especially chapter nine of the first part, "LiberalismandtheDeclineofPoliticalPhilosophy"). 4 BRUNOLATOUR,WEHAVENEVERBEENMODERN(CatherinePortertrans.,Harvard Univ.Press1993)(1991). 5 SELYABENHABIB,THERELUCTANTMODERNISMOFHANNAHARENDT(1996). 6 See H.G. LIDDELL& ROBERTSCOTT, ANINTERMEDIATEGREEK-ENGLISHLEXICON 450-51(Oxford,ClarendonPress7thed.1889). 2006] TheCriticalModernismofHannahArendt 253 mosttiedtothedemandsandthestandpointofaction—indeedmostfreeing ofaction,mostpolitical. In order to properly come to terms with the loss of authority and make room for the possibility of judgment,7 Arendt suggests that we must free ourselvesfromaliberalimaginationthatconfusesauthoritywithviolencein itsthoroughgoingfunctionalism(i.e.,itsreductionofauthorityto"whatever makespeopleobey"8).Wemustfreeourselvesfromaliberalimaginationthat confusestotalitarianismwithauthoritarianismbecauseitmisapprehendsthe demiseofauthorityforthetriumphoffreedomandfailstoseethatauthority andfreedompossiblybelongtogether.9Todistinguishauthorityfromviolence, Arendtargues,itisalsonecessarytoovercomealiberalmodeloftheruleand role of law in which judgment is reduced to the application of pre-existing rules. It turns out that the misapprehension of authority is bound up with a misapprehension of judgment — and that both misapprehensions threaten human,politicalfreedom. Attempting to overcome the confusion of authority with violence leads Arendt to argue that the failure to properly apprehend authority lies deeper than liberalism as a political theory: this failure has its origins in the Western tradition of thought and, ultimately, in metaphysics, i.e., the belief in a better, truer world in which this world finds its ground. According to Arendt, the crisis of modernity is not simply — as is often suggested in this epoch of "post-foundational" thinking10—thelossofmetaphysical ground.Thecrisisofmodernityisthe(threatened)lossofworld.Thus,Arendt writes,thelossofauthorityis"tantamounttothelossofthegroundworkofthe world."11 Whereas authority endowed the world with stability and whereas judgment presupposes and affirms a world peopled by a plurality of fellow humanbeings,metaphysics,initseffort togroundthisworld,deprivesitof its worldly and political character. Metaphysics turns the problem of world intooneofground.Itcoversupthesharingofaworldbyapluralityofhuman 7 Some of the secondary literature on Arendt also pairs the theme of the demise of authority with that of the need for judgment. See, for example, ROBERTC. PIRRO, HANNAHARENDTTHEPOLITICSOFTRAGEDY (2001), in which Chapter 3, "Tragic Foundations:PromotingPoliticalFreedominaPost-AuthorityWorld,"isfollowed byChapter4,"TragicIntuitions:JudgmentasanInstanceofPoliticalFreedom." 8 HANNAH ARENDT, What is Authority?, in BETWEEN PAST AND FUTURE: EIGHT EXERCISESINPOLITICALTHOUGHT91,103(1968). 9 ARENDT,supranote8,at95. 10 For a thoughtful reflection on the theme of foundation, see John E. Seery, Castles intheAir:AnEssayonPoliticalFoundations,27POL.THEORY460(1999). 11 ARENDT,supranote8,at95;seealsoMarkAntaki,TheWorld(lessness)ofHuman Rights,49MCGILLL.J.203(2004). 254 TheoreticalInquiriesinLaw [Vol.8:251 beings with violence or fixed standards of truth that, each in its own way, compelsorcoercesagreementanddoesawaywiththedimensionofplurality of human being-in-the-world.Truth is confounded with, indeed reduced to, certainty. Judgment appears, then, not only as a practical response to the crisis of authority but also as the faculty that bridges the distance between thinking and doing, the distance that makes metaphysics (and hence nihilism) a "natural" propensityof thought.12 Judgment appears at once as a political or practical solution to the rule of law or the rule of rules, and as a philosophical solution to abstract thinking. Like the political practice of authority, judgment — unlike either physical violence or the coercion of philosophical truth — is compatible withhumanfreedom.Accordingly,inherlaterwork,ArendtturnstoKant’s work on judgment (and away from Kant’s work on reason — whether pure orpractical)whereimaginationandthepossibilityofsharedjudgmentsthat arenotcompelledfigureprominently.Arendtturnsfromascienceofpolitics to an art of politics, from the lone moral actor (practical reason) or lone observer(theoreticalreason)tothejudgingspectatorwhoisalwaysalready concerned withthe worldofpublic, politicalaction. However, the turn to the spectator is not necessarily a turn away from the actor, and the turn to Kant need not be construed as a turn away from Aristotle(andphronesis).13Itisimportanttokeepinmindthemultivocalityof "judgment."Our(andArendt’s)useof"judgment"bridgesthepractice-theory divide: we speak of judgment with regard to the kind of discernment that accompanies — or ought to accompany — action, we speak of judgment with regard to the backward glance of the historian, we speak of judgment with regard to a legal or moral assessment of specific acts, we speak of judgment with regard to determinations of the beauty of a work or thing.14 And, as we shall see, Arendt believes that the distinctions between thought 12 HANNAHARENDT,THELIFEOFTHEMIND176(1978). 13 IfollowLisaJaneDischinnotseeing"Arendt’slecturesonjudgmentasadecisive retreat from the political writings," LISAJANEDISCH, HANNAHARENDTANDTHE LIMITSOFPHILOSOPHY142(1994),andDanaVillainnotseeing"anirreduciblegap between Arendt’s early, actor-centered account of judgment and her later, critical or historical one," DANAVILLA, POLITICS, PHILOSOPHY, TERROR: ESSAYSONTHE THOUGHTOFHANNAHARENDT99(1999).Ofcourse,notpittingthepoliticalagainst the critical Arendt does not mean that her account of judgment neatly succeeds in reconcilingactionandthought. 14 Seyla Benhabib identifies three of these senses of judgment with regard to the Eichmannaffair.BENHABIB,supranote5,at185-86. 2006] TheCriticalModernismofHannahArendt 255 and action,between thepoliticaljudgmentof theactorand thehistorical or criticaljudgmentofthespectatorbreakdownintimesofcrisis.Totheextent thatcrisiscanbeusedasawindowintothehumanconditionmoregenerally, Arendt’sfocusoncrisismightbethefirststepinleavingbehindorreconciling thesedistinctions. Part II of this Article, "The Crisis of Authority," turns to Arendt’s conception of modernity as an epoch of crisis in which the "now," the gap between past and future, becomes, with the disappearance of authority, a political problem for man. It also shows how, according to Arendt, the loss of understanding of the experience of authority is concomitant with the rise of metaphysics, which covers up the gap between past and future in a way that divorces thought and deed. Part III, "The Gap Between Past and Future," explicates Arendt’s dominant metaphor for modernity, i.e., the gap between past and future, by way of a parable of Kafka’s to which Arendt turns.Arendt’s treatment of Kafka’s parable points starkly to metaphysics and the divorce of thought from deed. Part IV, "The Critique of Judgment," shows how judgment becomes pivotal in overcoming the divorce of thought from deed characteristic of metaphysics and of Kafka’s parable. In Arendt’s reworking of Kafka’s parable, "thinking" is quietly transformed into "judging." The theory that belongs to the observer gives wayto thetheory (asintheatre15)thatbelongstothespectator. Though it focuses on Arendt as a political theorist and not as a legal theorist, this Article was inspired by developments in legal theory. Over thepastseveraldecades,anincreasingnumberoflegaltheoristshavemade "imagination" occupy a central place in their thinking about law. At least some of these theorists have sought to conceive of the binding character of lawin"aestheticterms"ratherthanintermsofthethreatofphysicalviolence (as in Austin’s gunman) or the inexorable force of a rule-bound reason.16 TheseaccountsshareArendt’sfocusonworldratherthangroundandechoher understandingofbothauthorityandjudgmentasbeingirreducibletoviolence oranarrowly-conceivedrationality.17 It is precisely the manner in which these accounts turn to "imagination" that makes them so unsettling to a legal liberalism that insists on reasons that can compelagreement. Indeed, seeking to restrainoreliminatepolitics 15 Pirrowrites:"ItisworthspeculatingwhatArendtwouldhavemadeofthecommon etymologicalrootsandculturalderivationof"theatre"and"theory"inacompleted versionofJudging."PIRRO,supranote7,at127. 16 See, e.g., ANTHONY T. KRONMAN, THE LOST LAWYER: FAILING IDEALS OF THE LEGALPROFESSION(1993);JAMESBOYDWHITE,THELEGALIMAGINATION(1985). 17 See,e.g.,JOSEPHVINING,THEAUTHORITATIVEANDTHEAUTHORITARIAN(1986). 256 TheoreticalInquiriesinLaw [Vol.8:251 bywayoflaw,thislegalliberalismseesthespecteroftotalitarianismbehind any "aesthetic" account of law and legal and moral judgment.18 Arendt toosawauthorityandlawaslimiting,butalsotherebyenablingpolitics19but could not conceive of a law that would replace or do away with politics.20 Thus,inTheOriginsofTotalitarianism,Arendt’sarticulationoftheessence of human rights as the right to have rights21 serves to make primordial one’sbelongingnotonlytoalegalorderbuttoapolitical community. And whereas the "unruliness of judgment"22leadssometofeararbitrarinessand evil,ArendtattributesEichmann’sevildoingtohisthoughtlessnessandtohis lackofimagination,i.e.,totheutterconformityofhisthoughttopre-existing standards and cliche´s — to the "rule-boundedness" of his judgment23 and not to the inherent unruliness of judgment in general. Thoughtlessness and worldlessnessappearasconstitutiveof(modern)evil. Thus,whereasthereisoftenalaudabletendencyincontemporarythought to turn to rule-bound reason to avoid or prevent times of crisis, Arendt worries that, precisely in times of crisis, adherence to inherited standards andrulesmaybeinsufficient toinspireproperaction—andindeedmaybe mostdetrimentaltoproperaction.Thus,itispreciselybecauseArendttends toconceiveofthinkingasnegative,asdissolvingtakenforgrantedstandards, 18 See,e.g., R. GeorgeWright, WhosePhronesis? WhichPhronimoi?: AResponse to DeanKronmanonLawSchoolEducation,26CUMB.L.REV.817(1995-1996). 19 Inheressayonauthority,Arendtreferstothedistinctionbetween(lawless)tyranny and(lawful)authoritarianism.ARENDT,supranote8,at97. 20 See also JILLFRANK, A DEMOCRACYOFDISTINCTION: ARISTOTLEANDTHEWORK OFPOLITICS(2005)(particularlyChapter4,"TheRuleofLaw"). 21 HANNAH ARENDT, THE ORIGINS OF TOTALITARIANISM 296 (Harcourt Brace Jovanovich1973)(1951). 22 SeePhilippeNonet,Judgment,48VAND.L.REV.987(1995);seealsoLindaRoss Meyer,IsPracticalReasonMindless?,86GEO.L.REV.647(1998). 23 Arendt attributes Eichmann’s wrongdoing to his "sheer thoughtlessness," to "his lackofimagination,""tohisremotenessfromreality."HANNAHARENDT,EICHMANN IN JERUSALEM: A REPORT ON THE BANALITY OF EVIL 287-88 (1964) [hereinafter ARENDT, EICHMANN IN JERUSALEM]. Arendt writes that Eichmann "had not the slightest difficulty in accepting an entirely different set of rules. He knew that what he had once considered his duty was not called a crime, and he accepted this new code of judgment as thought it were nothing but another language rule." HANNAH ARENDT, Thinking and Moral Considerations, in RESPONSIBILITY AND JUDGMENT 159, 159 (Jerome Kohn ed., 2003) [hereinafter ARENDT, Thinking and Moral Considerations]. The key here isthe ease with which Eichmann exchanged one set of rules for another without thinking, without being worldly. Cf. George Orwell,PoliticsandtheEnglishLanguage,inORWELL’SNINETEENEIGHTY-FOUR: TEXT,SOURCES,CRITICISM248(IrvingHoweed.,1982). 2006] TheCriticalModernismofHannahArendt 257 andpreciselybecauseshetendstodivorcethinkingfromdoing,thatArendt canassertthat"[t]hinkingceasestobeamarginalaffairinpoliticalmatters" in moments of mass conformity.24The problemshe identifiesisnotoneof certaintyorknowledgebutoneofhistorical—andpractical—discernment: "The manifestation of the wind of thought is no knowledge; it is the ability to tell right from wrong, beautiful from ugly. And this indeed may prevent catastrophes, at least for myself, in the rare moments when the chips are down."25 (Critical) thought becomes a — if not the — mode of action in times of crisis. II. THECRISISOFAUTHORITY A. The CrisisofModernity Scholars have located the "beginning" of modernity in the eighteenth century, with the "final victory" of the moderns over the ancients26 or even with the coming into its own of history as a discipline. For example, Reinhart Koselleck writes that modernity (Neuzeit) designates that epoch in which "the discipline of history (Geschichtwissenschaft)" outgrows "the mere employment of its methods" and develops "a theory of its own."27Koselleckemphasizesthat,morethansignifyingadateablehistorical epoch,modernityisthethematizingandbecomingever-present ofacertain set of problems, tensions, or experiences relating to man’s historicity: for example,"theknowledgethatoneislivinginaperiodoftransitioninwhichit becomesharderandhardertoreconcileestablishedtraditionswithnecessary innovations,""thefeelingofaccelerationbywhichprocessesofeconomicor politicalchangeappeartobetakingplace."28 Taking our cue in part from Koselleck, but shifting our emphasis from the "new" (Neuzeit) to the "now" (modernity29), we can say that modernity is that condition in which the "now" or, as Arendt calls it, "the 24 ARENDT,ThinkingandMoralConsiderations,supranote23,at188. 25 Id.at189. 26 See,e.g.,TiloSchabert,ANoteonModernity,7POL.THEORY123(1979). 27 REINHARTKOSELLECK, The Eighteenth Century as the Beginning of Modernity, in THE PRACTICE OF CONCEPTUAL HISTORY 154, 167 (Todd Samuel Presner trans., 2002). 28 Id.at168. 29 The German Neuzeit points to the "new" whereas the English modernity points to the"now"fromtheLatinmodo,justnow. 258 TheoreticalInquiriesinLaw [Vol.8:251 gap between past and future"30 becomes a problem for man. For Arendt, the "now" became a problem as the "Roman trinity" of "religion, authority, andtradition"31brokedown.Withouttheguidanceoftradition,religion,and authority, man is thrown back upon himself and threatened with the loss of the past (the breakdown of tradition), the loss of faith (the breakdown of religion),andthelossoftheworld(thebreakdownofauthority).32According to Arendt, the breakdown of authority occurred last but is most significant politically, i.e., most constitutive of political modernity. In a manner akin to Koselleck’s account of the unsettling power of the "new," Arendt notes thatauthorityprovidestheworlda"permanenceanddurabilitywhichhuman beingsneedpreciselybecausetheyaremortals."33Thus,withthebreakdown ofauthority,manispotentiallythreatenedwiththelossofthe"conditionsof human existence,"34 such as the "world," i.e., the "in-between" that "relates andseparatesmenatthesametime."35ThisbreakdownoftheRomantrilogy pointstothe"generalcrisisthathasovertakenthemodernworldeverywhere andinalmosteverysphereoflife."36 Thoughwecommonlythinkofcrisesintermsofrisks,losses,anddangers, Arendt’s account also points to crises as moments in which the burden of freedom is placed squarely on the shoulders of men, whether they "feel" it or not, and in which a space for a decision that is sorely needed opens up whether this space is recognized as such or not. As we shall see, the crisis of the modern world37presentsitselfasanopportunityformanto"lose"— butalsoto"win"—hishumanity. 30 See,e.g.,HANNAHARENDT,Preface:TheGapBetweenPastandFuture,inBETWEEN PASTANDFUTURE:EIGHTEXERCISESINPOLITICALTHOUGHT,supranote8,at3. 31 ARENDT,supranote12,at212. 32 ARENDT,supranote8,at94-95. 33 Id.at95. 34 HANNAHARENDT,THEHUMANCONDITION11(1958). 35 Id.at52. 36 HANNAHARENDT,TheCrisisinEducation,inBETWEENPASTANDFUTURE:EIGHT EXERCISESINPOLITICALTHOUGHT,supranote8,at173,173[hereinafterARENDT, TheCrisisinEducation].CrisisisaprominentthemeinArendt’swork.Inadditionto theabove,notethetitlesof,forexample,HANNAHARENDT,TheCrisisinCulture:Its SocialandPoliticalSignificance,inBETWEENPASTANDFUTURE:EIGHTEXERCISES INPOLITICALTHOUGHT, supra note 8, at 197 [hereinafter ARENDT, The Crisis in Culture];HANNAHARENDT,CRISESOFTHEREPUBLIC(1972). 37 In her introduction to The Human Condition, Arendt writes, "[T]he modern age is not the same as the modern world. Scientifically, the modern age which began in the seventeenth century came to an end at the beginning of the twentieth century; politically,themodernworld,inwhichwelivetoday,wasbornwiththefirstatomic explosions."ARENDT,supranote34,at6. 2006] TheCriticalModernismofHannahArendt 259 B. MetaphorsofModernity Arendt turns to several metaphors of modernity, of crisis, to outline the predicament of modern man.38 For example, Arendt explicitly draws on Jacob Burckhardt to describe the beginning of the Western philosophical tradition(withPlatoandAristotle)as"a‘fundamentalchord’whichsoundsits endlessmodulationsthroughoutthewholehistoryofWesternthought."39The chordcouldnotstrikeman"moreforcefullyandmorebeautifully"thanatthe beginningofthetradition,writesArendt,butattheendofthetradition(with Marx) "never more irritatingly and jarringly."40 The "fundamental chord" attunes man to the world as long as it resonates beautifully but it turns destructiveintheend. Arendtalsoturnstothemetaphorofthe"thread"oftradition.Thisthread, she writes, "safely guided us through the vast realms of the past."41 The wearing thinand breaking of the thread invite forgettingand thus endanger thepast,the"dimensionofdepthinhumanexistence."42Withoutatradition "whichselectsandnames,whichhandsdownandpreserves"43thetreasuresof humanbeing-in-the-world,thedimensionsofpastandfuturethatconstitute man’s humanity are threatened. The loss of past and future threatens the present as well: there arises the risk of the reduction of man to a biological beingleftwith"onlysempiternalchangeoftheworldandthebiologicalcycle of livingcreaturesinit."44As Arendt writesinthe concluding pages to The Human Condition, man "is on the point of developing into that animal speciesfrom which,since Darwin,heimagines he hascome."45 Perhaps the most important metaphor of modernity, of crisis, to which Arendt turns is that of the "gap between past and future." Arendt writes of the "gap between past and future" being "bridged over by what, since the Romans,wehavecalledtradition."46Thebreakdownofthebridgeoftradition, 38 Though the language of "past" and "tradition" figures prominently in Arendt’s use of the metaphors discussed below, these metaphors apply to the breakdown of the Roman trilogy of tradition, religion, and authority. Often, Arendt mixes her categories,writing,forinstance,oftheauthorityofthepast. 39 HANNAHARENDT,TraditionandtheModernAge,inBETWEENPASTANDFUTURE: EIGHTEXERCISESINPOLITICALTHOUGHT,supranote8,at17,18. 40 Id. 41 ARENDT,supranote8,at94. 42 Id. 43 ARENDT,supranote30,at4. 44 Id.at5. 45 ARENDT,supranote34,at322. 46 ARENDT,supranote30,at13-14. 260 TheoreticalInquiriesinLaw [Vol.8:251 then,wouldappeartohurlmanintothegap,intothenothing,intotheabyss. However,Arendtwritesthatwhereasthebreakdownofthebridgecovering thegapisconstitutiveofourmodernity,thegapisconstitutiveofourhumanity. Arendtexplains:"Thegap,Isuspect,isnotamodernphenomenon,itisperhaps notevenahistoricaldatumbutiscoevalwiththeexistenceofmanonearth."47 Inotherwords,beinghumanisbeing-in-thegap,being-towards-the-nothing. Arendt’s inquiry into authority is thus not only an inquiry into a part of the Roman trilogy that helped cover up the gap, and thus an inquiry into the crisis of modern times, but also a contribution to the uncovering of the gap, and thus a critique. In her essay on authority, Arendt inquires intotheformofauthoritythatheldswayinWesternhistory.Hercritiqueof authorityaimsatexposingthe"original"experienceofauthority,anoriginal experience that has been layered over, and therefore lost, by successive misappropriationsandmisinterpretations.Hercritiquealsoaimsatoutlining the challenge we moderns face in being responsible for the world without thehelp ofauthority. C. Authority Arendt’saccountofauthorityisguidedbytheconvictionthatitisimportant todiscriminate,tomakedistinctions,i.e.,tojudge.Arendtexplainsthatsheis writingagainsttwostrongcontemporarytrendsthatleadtotheconfounding ofauthoritywithviolence.Ontheonehand,sheexplains,liberalwriterssee theprogressofhumanityasamarchtowardsgreaterfreedom,lookingupon each deviation from this course as a reactionary process leading in the opposite direction. This makes them overlook the differences in principle between the restriction of freedom in authoritarian regimes, the abolition of political freedom in tyrannies and dictatorships, and the total elimination of spontaneity itself, that is, of the most general and most elementary manifestation of human freedom, at which only totalitarian regimes aim by means of their various methods of conditioning.48 Contrary to liberal writers, Arendt claims that the loss of authority paved the way for totalitarianism. On the other hand, Arendt ties liberalism to "the almost universal functionalization of all concepts and ideas,"49 47 Id.at13. 48 ARENDT,supranote8,at96. 49 Id.at101.

Description:
of Kafka's dealing with the gap between past and future illustrates her .. helmsman, as the master who knows, as educator, as the wise man — all.
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.