ebook img

The Contours of Agency: Essays on Themes from Harry Frankfurt PDF

366 Pages·2002·2.31 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The Contours of Agency: Essays on Themes from Harry Frankfurt

Contours of Agency Essays on Themes from Harry Frankfurt edited by Sarah Buss and Lee Overton A Bradford Book The MIT Press Cambridge, Massachusetts London,England (2002MassachusettsInstituteofTechnology Allrightsreserved.Nopartofthisbookmaybereproducedinanyformbyany electronic or mechanical means (including photocopying, recording, or informa- tionstorageandretrieval)withoutpermissioninwritingfromthepublisher. This book was set in Sabon on 3B2 by Asco Typesetters, Hong Kong and was printedandboundintheUnitedStatesofAmerica. LibraryofCongressCataloging-in-PublicationData Contoursofagency:essaysonthemesfromHarryFrankfurt/editedby SarahBussandLeeOverton. p. cm. ‘‘ABradfordbook.’’ Includesbibliographicalreferencesandindex. ISBN0-262-02513-2(hc:alk.paper) 1.Act(Philosophy)—Congresses. 2.Agent(Philosophy)—Congresses. 3.Frankfurt,HarryG.,1929– —Congresses. I.Buss,Sarah. II.Overton,Lee. B105.A35C665 2001 191—dc21 2001044505 Contents Acknowledgments vii Contributors ix Introduction xi 1 Frankfurt-StyleCompatibilism 1 John Martin Fischer Reply to John Martin Fischer 27 Harry Frankfurt 2 Controland CausalDeterminism 33 Eleonore Stump Reply to Eleonore Stump 61 Harry Frankfurt 3 Hierarchy, Circularity, and Double Reduction 65 MichaelE. Bratman Reply to MichaelE. Bratman 86 Harry Frankfurt 4 Identification and Identity 91 J.DavidVelleman Reply to J.David Velleman 124 Harry Frankfurt 5 VolitionalNecessities 129 Gary Watson Reply to Gary Watson 160 Harry Frankfurt vi Contents 6 Reasons and Passions 165 T. M. Scanlon Replyto T. M.Scanlon 184 HarryFrankfurt 7 Frankfurt on Identification: Ambiguities of Activityin Mental Life 189 Richard Moran Replyto Richard Moran 218 HarryFrankfurt 8 The True, the Good, andtheLovable: Frankfurt’s Avoidance of Objectivity 227 Susan Wolf Replyto Susan Wolf 245 HarryFrankfurt 9 Bootstrapping 253 BarbaraHerman Replyto BarbaraHerman 275 HarryFrankfurt 10 Love’sAuthority 279 Jonathan Lear Replyto Jonathan Lear 293 HarryFrankfurt 11 On Frankfurt’sExplanation of Respect for People 299 Joseph Raz Replyto Joseph Raz 316 HarryFrankfurt 12 Deeper into Bullshit 321 G. A. Cohen Replyto G. A.Cohen 340 HarryFrankfurt Bibliography of Harry Frankfurt’sWork 345 References 349 Index 357 Introduction In a recent paper Harry Frankfurt describes human beings as ‘‘generally hard to pin down, difficult to sort out, and just about impossible to sum up.’’Hemighthavebeendescribinghisownwork.Foroverthirtyyears, in language at once elegant and direct, Frankfurt has been exploring the contours of human agency. The power of his insights is due, in part, to his refusal to sum up his complex, elusive subject. He calls attention to thecomplexity,acknowledgesthatmucheludeshim,and,intheprocess, prods us to continue the exploration ourselves. As he explains in the preface to the second collection of his papers, his goal as a philosopher hasalwaysbeentograpplewith‘‘linesofthought’’thatconfronthim‘‘as a human being trying to cope in a modestly systematic manner with the ordinary difficulties ofa thoughtful life.’’Thisiswhy wecannot readhis essays without acknowledging to ourselves that what he says matters, whether weagreewith him or not. The difficulties of a thoughtful life—orat least many ofthem—can be traced to one central fact abouthuman beings: we are capable of reflect- ing on ourselves; indeed, there are few things that come more naturally to us. This reflexivity generates problems because it divides us from our- selves.Itsplitsusinto theonewhoreflects andtheone whoistheobject of this reflection. And this split makes us vulnerable to real rifts in our psyche—to inner strife and self-alienation—which must be overcome if we areto becomewhole. The chief ‘‘ordinary difficulty’’ of human life is that we are not whole. AsFrankfurtputsit,mostofusfinditdifficulttoidentifywholeheartedly with all of our emotions, desires, and inclinations. This self-alienation takes two forms that especially interest Frankfurt. First, we are often filled with uncertainty about whether we really ought to care as we do xii Introduction about what we care about; we are often ambivalent. Second, we often discoverthatwehavedesires,orinclinations,thatwereallywouldprefer not to have; and this can reduce us to being ‘‘passive bystanders’’ to our own wills. The latter form of self-alienation preoccupies Frankfurt in his earlier work. It is, he argues, the key to understanding moral responsibility. AccordingtoFrankfurt,weareresponsibleforwhatwedoifandonlyif ourmotivesfordoingitaretrulyourown.Contrarytowhatmanyhave thought, whether our motives are truly our own does not depend on their causal history; nor does it depend on whether we have the power to replace them. When moral responsibility is at issue, what matters is whether the motivating force of our desires is in harmony with our atti- tudes toward beingmoved in this way. Insofar asourattitudes conflict, weareambivalent.And insofaraswe are ambivalent, we lack confidence in our own ‘‘take’’ on things. In his more recent work, Frankfurt has become especially interested in those attitudes which are immune to doubt because we identify with them ‘‘wholeheartedly.’’Ineffect,hehasshifted hisfocusfrom theself-control sufficientformoralresponsibilitytotheself-integrationthat,heclaims,is animplicitgoalofeveryhumanagent.Withthisshift,hehasbecomeless concerned about how our power as agents is manifested in the power of ourdesires,andmoreinterestedinhowourwholeheartedpsychicinvest- ments in people, institutions, and projects impose authoritative limits on the power of our own wills. According to Frankfurt, the most fundamental ideal of human agency iswholeheartedness.Unlessonecareswholeheartedlyaboutsomething— unless, that is, one is fully satisfied with the fact that one cares about it—one’s life lacks balance, continuity, and structure. Caring about something ‘‘guides [a person] in supervising the design and the order- ing of his own purposes and priorities.’’ And to care wholeheartedly about something is to trust the guide without reservation. Someone who wholeheartedly endorses his motives is as actively involved in producing hisown actions asan agentcan possibly be. Frankfurttellsusthatthedefiningcharacteristicofpersonsisthatthey care about things. And, following Hume, he insists that whatever we havereasontodo(orrefrainfromdoing)dependsonwhat,inparticular, we care about. Love, he says, is a special kind of care. When one loves Introduction xiii something, or someone, one cannot help caring about this thing, or per- son.Moreimportant,onecannotdoubttheauthorityofthereasonsthat are grounded in this care. In short, the authority that turns certain facts into reasons for action is the authority of love; the ‘‘ought’’ of practical reason is grounded in love’s nonrational ‘‘must.’’ To discover that one cannot help caring about something (and that onecannothelpbeingsatisfiedwiththefactthatonecannothelpcaring) is to come up against a ‘‘volitional necessity.’’ A person who is subject to volitional necessity ‘‘accedes to [a constraint on his will] because he is unwilling to oppose it and because, furthermore, his unwillingness is itself something which he is unwilling to alter.’’ On Frankfurt’s account, such necessities are the key to self-integration, and to the self-confidence that is tied to wholeheartedness as both cause and effect. In giving us reasons, volitional necessities are also the source of values. And because they areconstitutiveofwho weare, theydetermine theconditionsunder which wesucceed ingoverning ourselves. When we truly govern ourselves—when we are truly autonomous— thisisnot,Frankfurtinsists,becausethereismorethanonepossibleway we can act. Rather, it is because certain possibilities are closed off by what we truly care about. Being truly autonomous is one and the same thing as being truly wholehearted. An autonomous agent ‘‘identifies himself fully and uninhibitedly with the volitional configurations that define his final ends.... There is no part of him—no part with which he identifies—that is opposed to or that resists his loving what he loves.’’ Just as being at war with oneself is incompatible with self-government, so, according to Frankfurt, self-love is a defining characteristic of the autonomous agent. Thethemesthatarecentraltocopingwiththedifficultiesofathoughtful human life are among the themes of greatest philosophical importance. This is evident in the essays collected here. Written to honor a distin- guished colleague, these essays cover a wide range of topics in meta- physics, metaethics, normative ethics, and action theory. They are the work of eminent philosophers who defend their own original philosoph- ical positions at thesame time that they respond to Frankfurt’s. In his contribution to this volume, John Martin Fischer addresses Frankfurt’s claim that causal determinism poses no threat to moral xiv Introduction responsibility.Frankfurthastworeasonsfortakingthisposition:hedoes not believe that the history of an agent’s motives is relevant to whether they are truly her own; and he does not believe that moral responsibility requires alternate possibilities. Fischer rejects the antihistorical aspect of Frankfurt’s conception of moral responsibility. But he joins Frankfurt in attacking the assumption that an agent is responsible for her action only ifshecouldhavedoneotherwise.FischerconcedesthatevenifFrankfurt isrightonthisscore,thereareotherreasonsonemighthaveforthinking that an agent cannot be responsible for an action that was causally de- termined by the state of the world in the far distant past, together with the laws of nature. He examines these additional considerations, argues that they are not compelling, and thus concludes that whether an act is causally determined is irrelevant to whether the agent is morally respon- sible for performingit. Eleonore Stump shares Fischer’s sense that Frankfurt’s account of moral responsibility attributes too little importance to the history of an agent’s motives. But she raises concerns about Fischer’s attempt to rec- onciletherelevanceofhistorywiththeirrelevanceofcausaldeterminism. She argues that the most compelling argument for the incompatibility of causal determinism and moral responsibility relies on a principle that Fischer has not succeeded in undermining. And she strengthens her case againstapproacheslikeFischer’sbyshowinghowtheydonobetterthan Frankfurt’s ahistorical approach in distinguishing causally determined action from action caused by direct brain manipulation. Even incompatibilists concede that being free from determination by eventsinthepastdoesnotsufficeforbeingmorallyresponsibleforone’s actions. In developing his own compatibilist account, Frankfurt intro- duces a notion that many others have found suggestive. An agent is morally responsible for his act, he says, if and only if he identifies with the desire that moves him to perform it. Otherwise, the desire is just a motivational force he suffers passively, like a reflex bodily movement that occurs in spite of himself. In his essay Michael Bratman focuses on this elusive notion of identification. What is it exactly? On Bratman’s readingofFrankfurt,toidentifywithagivendesireDistohave‘‘higher- order attitudes in support of D.’’ Bratman believes that the sort of iden- tification that is especially important to agency involves a proattitude towardD’sprovidingajustifyingreasonforaction;andhedevotesmost Introduction xv of his essay to analyzing this attitude and its propositional content. Frankfurt, he notes, suggests that ‘‘treating D as reason-providing’’ can be reduced to ‘‘D’s functioning as an effective motive because of the higher-order attitude in favor of that functioning.’’ Like many other contributors to this volume, however, Bratman is skeptical of any such reduction. After all, he points out, ‘‘A desire for E may motivate action without any thought that E is a justifying consideration.’’ He thus rec- ommends an alternative analysis: to identify with some desire D is to have a higher-order attitude toward D’s ‘‘functioning as end-setting for practical reason.’’ The relevant attitude, he claims, is a ‘‘higher-order self-governing policy.’’ Such policies have authority to represent the agent’s standpoint because of the essential role they play in the unity of agency. In offering this analysis of identification, Bratman aims to call attention to the significant role that higher-order attitudes and policies playinouragency.Hebringshisessaytoaclosebyreviewingadditional ways inwhich such attitudesand policiescansupport our motives. Bratman’s interest in identification is an interest in the attitudes an agent has qua practical reasoner. This reflects the fact that our inten- tional actions are actions we perform for a reason. David Velleman also believes that the ‘‘self whose participation in causing behavior is neces- sary and sufficient’’ for intentional agency is the self conceived as the point of view from which reasons for action are assessed. Velleman argues that this participating, identifying self need not persist over time in order for a person to remain in existence. In other words, one can be- tray even one’s deepest evaluative commitments without ceasing to be the person one was. Persons, Velleman argues against Frankfurt, do not have volitional essences. If we are tempted to think that they do, this may wellbe because it is comfortingto dissociate ourselves from aspects of ourselves we find threatening, or otherwise painful. With reference to Freud,Vellemanremindsusofthepsychicdamagethatsuchdissociation can cause. ThethemeofGaryWatson’sessayisthevolitionalnecessitiesthatare, allegedly, grounded in our volitional essences. To gain an understand- ing of this special sort of limit on one’s will, Watson compares it with manyother‘‘constraintsonone’sabilitytodosomething.’’Tobesubject to volitional necessity is not to be constrained by psychic impediments, suchasphobias.Norisitthesamethingas‘‘normativenecessity,’’orthe

Description:
The original essays in this book address Harry Frankfurt's influential writing on personal identity, love, value, moral responsibility, and the freedom and limits of the human will. Many of Frankfurt's deepest insights come from exploring the self-reflective nature of human agents and the psychic co
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.