ebook img

The Concept of Socialist Law PDF

212 Pages·1990·7.856 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The Concept of Socialist Law

V .'.i ■ j ■ ‘ THE CONCEPT OF SOCIALIST LAW 4 1 1 ■ THE CONCEPT OF SOCIALIST LAW Christine Sypnowich CLARENDON PRESS • OXFORD 1990 i Oxford University Press, Walton Street, Oxford OX2 6DP Oxford New York Toronto Delhi Bomba)' Calcutta Madras Karachi Relating Jaya Singapore Hong Kong Tokyo Nairobi Dar es Salaam Cape Town k Melbourne Auckland | and associated companies in I Berlin Ibadan Oxford is a trade mark of Oxford University Press Published in lhe United Stales by Oxford University Press, New York © Christine Syftnondcli rggo All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, without lhe prior permission of Oxford University Press British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Sypnowich, Christine The concept of socialist law. 1. Law. Socialist theories I. Title 340'.! ISBN 0-19-825246-3 Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Sypuowich, Christine. 'Hie concept of socialist law / Christine Sypnowich. Revision of the author's thesis, Oxford University, 1987. Bibliography: p. Includes index. 1. Law and socialism. I. Title. K3S7.S88 1990 3-/o'.,l5—dc20 89-15985 ISBN 0-19-825246-3 Typeset by Hope Services, Abingdon Printed in Great Britain by Biddles Ltd, Guildford and King's Lynn For My Parents i Preface It belongs to man to judge the law at the risk of being judged by it. Maurice Mcrlcau-Ponty1 This book aims to refute the idea advanced by socialists, and particularly Marxists, that an ideal socialist society would have no need of law. The rejection of law is symptomatic of a larger failing in Left­ wing thought: the neglect of the entire realm of politics, culture, and law, the ‘superstructure’, which according to orthodox Marxist theory is determined by the more fundamental realm of the economy. While Marxism has made an important contribution to the critique of capitalist economic relations, its political significance has been crippled by an inability to consider seriously the fate of the superstructure once capitalist relations arc swept away. The principal manifestation of what one writer calls this ‘deepening crisis in Marxist theory’2 is that the Left can say very little about the ways in which an ideal socialist society would be governed. While Marx repeatedly affirmed that ‘men need and always have needed each other’, he seldom examined how this need was to be met in a freely chosen political framework; state and law arc said to simply ‘wither away’ upon the full flowering of socialist society. This has proved to be an inadequate response to the problem of the nature of a socialist polity. As I intend to demonstrate, Marx’s project of emancipating man from capitalist property relations requires, not the dissolution of the legal and political spheres, but their reconstitution, however radical. Some clarification of terms is necessary. I use the word ‘socialist’ without defining it in any precise way. By socialism I mean a society where private property in the form of capital has been eliminated and replaced by common ownership of the means of production, thereby permitting a large measure of equality and fraternity in social relations. A more detailed definition would prejudge my analysis which, by 1 Humanism and Terror^ trans. John O’Neill (Boston, 1969). 2 Andrew Eraser, ‘The Legal Theory We Need Now’, Socialist Review, 40-1 (July- Oct. 1978), 147. viii Preface setting out why a socialist society would need legal institutions, seeks to enrich our understanding of socialism itself. To this extent I am in keeping with the spirit of Marxist theory, which considers the business of drafting blueprints for the future a futile task. Marxists hold, no doubt accurately, that the nature of any society cannot help but be determined by its participants in light of the circumstances in which the society emerges. Nevertheless, I do not think this permits socialists to abdicate all responsibility for discussing the nature of the socialist polity. The reluctance of socialist theorists to commit themselves to what Marx derided as ‘recipes for the cookshops of the future” also militates against an attempt to provide a detailed description of a socialist legal system. I have therefore avoided many practical questions. The work is silent on a number of questions: what the nature of a socialist constitution would be, e.g. whether it would be written or unwritten; whether legal decisions would be made on the basis of precedent; what function, if any, higher courts would have; and whether a socialist judiciary would be empowered, like, say, the American Supreme Court, to override legislative decisions. And while some of my arguments may betray a preference for adversarial systems of justice, I do not rule out the possibility that a socialist system of law could adopt an inquisitorial approach. This study seeks only to establish the possibility of a socialist concept of law, not to give a full and definitive exposition of a socialist legal system, code of law, or bill of rights. Similarly, in my use of examples from Soviet legal history, 1 do not seek to supply a comprehensive survey of Soviet legal institutions, or even of Soviet legal theory. Nor do I refer to Soviet cases because I see them as necessarily paradigmatic of the practice of socialist or Marxist theory. Rather, I have selectively chosen some theory and evidence from the ‘existing socialist society’ of the Soviet Union to show how Marxist theory, whether out of optimism, pragmatism, incompleteness, or opportunism, can lend itself to certain interpretations and practices. The term ‘Marxist’ is no more straightforward than ‘socialist’. While it is used to refer to the principles and theories set out by Karl Marx, just what these amount to has notoriously been the subject of both theoretical controversy and political conflict. Marxism has wide meaning: it refers to a conception of socialism, as well as to a view 1 ‘Afterword to the German edition of Capital', MESW 2: 96. Preface ix about how socialism comes about, that is, through the immanent collapse of capitalism and the rise of the working class. Marxism also involves a theory of man and society, and the term Marxist describes an approach to the study of social life found in fields ranging from literature to anthropology. I begin my study by using the word Marxist to refer to an ‘orthodox’ set of beliefs, in particular what I call the ‘withering away thesis’. However, I argue that Marxism should be regarded, not as a biblical canon, but as a dynamic approach to political and social questions, and that it is possible to give up some of its purportedly orthodox tenets without giving up what is essential to that approach. My purpose is to break down the Marxist’s resistance to the concept of socialist law by showing that law is compatible with certain socialist ideas and, indeed, that Marxist theory can inform the analysis of legal theory. In the process, I hope that what constitutes as ‘Marxism’ develops and expands. I would emphasize that while my argument focuses on legal concepts, the study is intended to be an exercise in political theory. In arguing that law is an essential part of the study of politics, I do not pretend to explain the nature of law or legal theory perse. My strategy is to examine the concepts and theories of ‘mainstream’ liberal juris­ prudence to see whether they can be adapted by Marxist theories of socialism, whether they should be, and how. It may be argued that because the institution of law pre-dated liberalism, an attempt to defeat the idea that there would be no law under socialism need not address liberal theory at all. To some extent, however, I accept Marx’s argument that legal concepts reached the apex of their development with the emergence of doctrines of the rights of man in ‘bourgeois’ societies. And I believe that the wealth of theory on justice and rights which has appeared since the time of Marx justifies a focus on a liberal perspective. Furthermore, influenced by the rise of socialist and social welfare ideas in this century, contemporary liberal theory is now a particularly rich source for fruitful analysis of the problem of socialist law. I thus adopt C. B. Macpherson’s strategy of‘retrieval’, trying to do for law what he has done for democracy, that is to extract the valuable moral and political insights of liberal theory in order to reconstitute them in a socialist framework.4 4 Indeed, Leo Panitch argues that, in light of Marxism’s deficiencies, Macpherson’s message must be that it is arguable that only liberal democratic theory ‘can truly address the question of the individual and the state in a classless society’, ’Liberal Democracy and Socialist Democracy: the Antinomies of C. B. Macpherson’, in Ralph Miliband and

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.