ebook img

The Chief Concern of Medicine: The Integration of the Medical Humanities and Narrative Knowledge into Medical Practices PDF

473 Pages·2013·2.967 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The Chief Concern of Medicine: The Integration of the Medical Humanities and Narrative Knowledge into Medical Practices

the chief concern of medicine The Chief Concern of Medicine The Integration of the Medical Humanities and Narrative Knowledge into Medical Practices Ronald Schleifer and Jerry B. Vannatta with Sheila Crow and a contribution by Seth Vannatta The UniVeRSiTy of MiChigan PReSS ann aRBoR Copyright © by the University of Michigan 2013 all rights reserved This book may not be reproduced, in whole or in part, including illustrations, in any form (beyond that copying permitted by Sections 107 and 108 of the U.S. Copyright Law and except by reviewers for the public press), without written permission from the publisher. Published in the United States of america by The University of Michigan Press Manufactured in the United States of america c Printed on acid- free paper 2016 2015 2014 2013 4 3 2 1 a CiP catalog record for this book is available from the British Library. Library of Congress Cataloging- in- Publication Data Schleifer, Ronald. The chief concern of medicine : the integration of the medical humanities and narrative knowledge into medical practices / Ronald Schleifer and Jerry B. Vannatta with Sheila Crow and a contribution by Seth Vannatta. p. ; cm. includes bibliographical references and index. isbn 978- 0- 472- 11859- 5 (cloth : alk. paper)— isbn 978- 0- 472- 02886- 3 (e- book) i. Vannatta, Jerry. ii. Crow, Sheila. iii. Title. [dnlm: 1. narration. 2. Physician- Patient Relations. 3. ethics, Medical. 4. Medical history Taking. w 62] 616.07'51— dc23 2012033644 to our students and colleagues and the years of our working friendship Preface The Chief Concern of Medicine aims at enlarging our sense of the profession of medicine and, more important, enlarging its effectiveness and service, by including a self- conscious awareness of the nature of narrative within a work- ing definition of the way medicine understands itself as a profession and its very activities. Medicine seeks to heal, to care, and to comfort, and we be- lieve that each of these goals is improved with the understanding of how narrative functions, both in general and within medical practices. To this end, we offer, first of all, a pragmatic understanding of the science on which medicine is based, particularly in relation to the larger theme of Part 1 of the book, the definition and the practical and ethical strategies of what aristotle calls phronesis (translated often as “practical reasoning” and sometimes even as “practical wisdom”). aristotle believed that phronesis was the means to a “good life” (eudaimonia), and one of his chief models for the accomplish- ment of phronesis was successful doctoring. We argue here that phronesis is closely related to narrative— to its structures and, most notably, its purposes, particularly the “end” or “concern” of any particular narrative. We also argue that the logic of hypothesis formation that informs medical diagnosis closely aligns itself with narrative and what we are calling “narrative knowledge.” Thus Part 1 of The Chief Concern of Medicine aims at enlarging our sense of science and scientific understanding and procedures in order to complement evidence- based medicine. evidence- based medicine aims, ide- ally, at what atul gawande has called “the idea that nothing ought to be in- troduced into practice unless it has been properly tested and proved effec- tive by research centers, preferably through a double blind, randomized controlled trial” (2007: 188). We hope to complement— not replace— evidenced- based medicine with what we are calling “schema- based medi- cine.” The schemas we set forth— on the model of schemas as they appear in cognitive psychology and artificial intelligence— are schemas of narrative, ethical actions, and procedures for the medical interview. in appendix 1, we even suggest that schemas might allow us to understand what might be called “humanistic understanding” more generally, in terms of a model of discipline building in the humanities. The simplest, but perhaps most profound, of these schemas is the suggestion, as we note in both the introduction and chapter 3, that doctors elicit a patient’s chief concern as well as a chief com- plaint in the formal procedure of conducting the history and Physical exam and eliciting the history of Present illness. We believe that the understand- ing of the schemas and procedures we describe in this book that grow out of humanistic understanding can find their place alongside scientific under- standing in governing how physicians and health care workers conceive of and go about their everyday encounter with people who are suffering, in distress, and in need of help. for this reason, it is our contention that the nomological sciences— law- governed understandings, based on thoroughly repeatable experiments or large- scale statistical measurements—c an be complemented by the human sciences, which depend on schematic understanding of forms and structures that govern cognition, experience, and judgment more generally. a model for such complementarity is the science of evolutionary biology, whose re- sults are widely accepted by physicians, medical- school faculty, and students aspiring for a career in medicine, even though the kind of randomized con- trol trials that epitomize evidence-b ased medicine is rarely possible in the study of evolution. evolution, Stephen Jay gould has persuasively argued (see especially 1986, 1989), is not a nomological science—r ather, he says, it is a historical science—y et it still bases itself, at times, on retrospective evi- dence (see Weiner 1995 for remarkable empirical evidence of generations of finches on the galapagos islands). a third category of science—w hat we sug- gest, early in the book, seeks functional knowledge— bases itself on the prag- matic achievement of goals in the systematic pursuit of understanding. inso- far as it does so, we suggest, it is a species of narrative science (or at least systematic analyses of narrative), which is based neither on the deductive laws and quantifiable evidence of nomological science nor on the inductive retrospective understanding of evolutionary- biological science but on the schemas of the humanities in general and of abductive logic more specifi- cally. (in chapter 4, we closely examine Charles Sanders Peirce’s “logic of abduction,” which is a systematic understanding of hypothesis formation.) in Part 1 of The Chief Concern of Medicine, we trace the functioning of such schemas in the ethical understanding of aristotle’s phronesis, in the viii / preface evolutionary- structural understanding of narrative cognition (or “narrative knowledge”), in a general accounting of narrative structures, and in Peirce’s logic of abductive reasoning. This is more or less the theoretical or philo- sophical basis of The Chief Concern of Medicine. in Part 2, we examine the particular everyday practices of medicine in relation to narrative. almost all medicine, we note, begins with the encoun- ter of patient and physician, and this encounter is organized around the his- tory of Present illness (hPi). Such a history begins, of necessity, with the patient’s chief complaint, but as we already mentioned, we argue that in the physician’s encounter with the patient, the chief complaint should be for- mally complemented with the inclusion of the patient’s chief concern as well. That concern is the patient’s awareness of what his illness means in relation to the ongoing story of his life, and because of this, its inclusion within the history and Physical exam—s omething that physicians would routinely ask in the way that family history is a routine part of the history and Physical exam itself— would make conscious awareness of narrative an important tool of medical diagnosis and treatment growing out of the patient- physician en- counter. as we note in chapter 3 and argue throughout Parts 2 and 3, a sig- nificant feature of narrative and narrative cognition is the deliberation be- tween its teller and its listener— an important feature of narrative, we note, is a witness who learns— and such collaborative deliberation, we believe, is at the heart of good doctoring. Deliberation is also at the heart of aristotle’s conception of phronesis. Thus the chapters of Part 2 examine the scene of narrative, which is the patient- physician relationship, the understanding of narrative, and the engagement with and responses to narrative available and proper to the practice of medicine. finally, Part 3 spells out schemas of narrative and ethical behavior that can help physicians pursue their work most efficiently, compassionately, and comprehensively in the face of human suffering. These schemas are orga- nized in relation to the theoretical sense of science and understanding that Part 1 describes and the empirical sense of what happens— or ought to hap- pen, given its goals and practical organization—i n practices of medicine. Throughout all these chapters, we distinguish between everyday or “popu- lar” narrative and aesthetic or “art” narrative, and we do so with the assump- tion that while narrative cognition is, indeed, part of our human inheritance as a species, the development of aesthetic narrative forms allows us to see more clearly how narrative works and how we can be more consciously atten- tive and receptive to the stories patients tell and to the narrative knowledge they present. Moreover, we argue, aesthetic narrative creates vicarious expe- preface / ix

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.