THE BATTLE OF THE GODS AND GIANTS STUDIES IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY AND THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY M. A. Stewart and David Fate Norton, Editors This is a monograph series whose purpose is to foster improved standards of historical and textual scholarship in the history of philosophy and directly related disciplines. Priority is given to studies that significantly advance our understanding of past thinkers through the careful examination and interpretation of original sources, whether printed or manuscript. Major works and movements in philosophy often reflect interests and concerns characteristic of a particular age and upbringing, and seemingly timeless concepts may vary with the changing background of knowledge and belief that different writers assume in their readers. It is the general editors' assumption that a sensitivity to context not only does not detract from the philosophical interest or rigor of a commentary but is actually essential to it. They wish to encourage studies that present a broad view of a subject's contemporary context, and that make an informative use of philosophical, theological, political, scientific, literary, or other collateral materials, as appropriate to the particular case. Other Books in the Series Steven M. Nadler, Arnauld and the Cartesian Philosophy of Ideas Catherine Wilson, Leibniz's Metaphysics: A Historical and Comparative Study Copyright © 1993 by Princeton University Press Published by Princeton University Press, 41 William Street, Princeton, New Jersey 08540 In the United Kingdom: Pnnceton University Press, Chichester, West Sussex All rights reserved Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Lennon, Thomas M. The battle of the gods and giants : the legacies of Descartes and Gassendi, 1655-1715 / Thomas M. Lennon. p. cm. — (Studies in intellectual history and the history of philosophy) Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-691-07400-3 1. Gassendi, Pierre, 1592-1655. 2. Descartes, Rene, 1596- 1650. 3. Locke, John, 1632-1704. I. Title. II. Series. B1887.L46 1993 194—dc20 92-26088 CIP This book has been composed in Linotron Times Roman Princeton University Press books are printed on acid-free paper and meet the guidelines for permanence and durability of the Committee on Production Guidelines for Book Longevity of the Council on Library Resources Printed in the United States of America 1 3579 10 8642 L 0C, Contents Preface ix Note on Documentation xiii I. The Philosophical Terrain 3 1 The Gassendist Failure 3 2 The Gassendist Success 26 3 The Interminable Battle 34 4 Other Wars 52 II. The Giants of the Seventeenth Century 63 5 Dramatis Personae 63 6 Mind versus Flesh 106 7 Gassendist Theories of Space: Apotheosis and Annihilation 117 8 PhysicalandMetaphysicalAtomism 137 III. Locke: Gassendist Anti-Cartesian 149 9 Locke and Gassendi 149 10 Locke and Descartes 163 11 Enthusiasm 169 IV. The Gods of the Seventeenth Century 191 12 Descartes's Idealism 191 13 Malebranche's Realism 210 14 Malebranche s Idealism 229 V. Ideas and Representation 240 15 Two Patterns of Ideas 240 16 Arguments for Representationalism 248 17 Two Versions of the Causal Argument 255 VI. The Untouchable and the Uncuttable 274 18 Space and Solidity 276 19 Simple and Complex Ideas 288 viii CONTENTS 20 Primary and Secondary Qualities 298 21 Powers 304 22 Matter and Creation 309 23 TheBestialSouI 314 VII. Innateness, Abstraction, and Essences 334 24 innateness 334 25 Essences and Abstraction 340 26 The Polemic with Stillingfleet 354 VIII. Philosophy and the Historiography of Philosophy 367 27 DissimulationandMeaning 368 28 What Locke Said 374 29 Two Camps of Historians 378 30 History and Interpretation 383 Works Cited 393 Index 411 Preface THIS IS A HISTORY of philosophy that examines the period defined by the death dates of Gassendi and Malebranche. It explores what in my view is most of philosophical interest in the period, namely, the contest between the philoso phies of Gassendi and Descartes as the appropriate scientific image of the world to replace the commonsense, manifest image associated with Aristotle and his scholastic epigones. Primarily because of the recrudescence of skepticism and the emergence of the New Science—contradictory circumstances that nonethe less reinforced each other—the world was thought to be other than as it is perceived to be. A main concern will thus be the dialectic of appearance and reality, which, while involving a broad range of philosophical issues, in this period focused on the analysis of space, the things in it, and how we know them. Not often explicit, but almost always implicit at the core of these analyses is the grand metaphysical question of why there exists anything at all. While the period here studied postdates the death of Descartes, some account of his relevant views is obviously necessary. This is especially so since my overall interpretation, although anticipated by Cousin and perhaps others in the nineteenth century, is highly controversial. Few of the components of this interpretation seem to me problematic, yet no one has quite put them together in this fashion. The key to my idealist interpretation of Descartes is, in any case, that for him the ontological analysis of material things is the same as Mal- ebranche's ontological analysis of the mental representations of material things. Descartes's things are Malebranche's perceptions of things. (Not inci dentally, many late seventeenth and early eighteenth-century debates over the nature of ideas saw each side accuse the other of confusing things with our ideas of things.) Moreover, the material things of which our perceptions are represen tations according to Malebranche turned out to be, as Berkeley most notably argued, ontologically and epistemologically idle. Thus, Descartes's view as I interpret it is, however controversial, most characteristic of Cartesianism. The extent to which Malebranche may be taken as the later standard-bearer of Cartesianism may of course be debated—as it was by Arnauld—but as to the idealism here attributed to Descartes, other Cartesians such as Desgabets and Regis were only more explicit. This work is not about Cartesianism, however, but its contest with Gassend- ism. Long neglected, Gassendi is now beginning to approach the prominence he once enjoyed. Translations have made his difficult texts more accessible, and the analyses by Rochot a few decades ago, and more recently by Bloch, Joy, and others, have shown their importance. As with Descartes's philosophy, the con-
Description: