The Art of Veiled Speech This page intentionally left blank The ArT of Veiled Speech Self-censorship from Aristophanes to hobbes edited by han Baltussen and peter J. davis university of pennsylvania press philadelphia copyright © 2015 University of pennsylvania press All rights reserved. except for brief quotations used for purposes of review or scholarly citation, none of this book may be reproduced in any form by any means without written permission from the publisher. published by University of pennsylvania press philadelphia, pennsylvania 19104- 4 112 www.upenn.edu/pennpress printed in the United States of America on acid- free paper 1 3 5 7 9 10 8 6 4 2 A cataloging- i n- publication record is available from the library of congress The art of veiled speech : self-censorship from Aristophanes to hobbes / edited by han Baltussen and peter J. davis. pages cm includes bibliographical references and index. iSBN 978-0-8122-4735-0 (alk. paper) 1. classical literature—history and criticism. 2. politics and literature—history. 3. freedom of speech in literature— history. 4. freedom of speech—history. 5. censorship— history. i. Baltussen, han, editor, author. ii. davis, peter J., editor, author. pA3015.p63A78 2015 363.31—dc23 2015005388 contents chapter 1. Parrhêsia, free Speech, and Self- censorship 1 Han Baltussen and Peter J. Davis chapter 2. Self- censorship in Ancient Greek comedy 18 Andrew Hartwig chapter 3. Parrhêsia and censorship in the Polis and the Symposium: An exploration of hyperides Against Philippides 3 42 Lara O’Sullivan chapter 4. A Bark Worse Than his Bite? diogenes the cynic and the politics of Tolerance in Athens 74 Han Baltussen chapter 5. censorship for the roman Stage? 94 Gesine Manuwald chapter 6. The poet as prince: Author and Authority Under Augustus 115 Ioannis Ziogas chapter 7. “Quae quis fugit damnat”: outspoken Silence in Seneca’s Epistles 137 Marcus Wilson chapter 8. Argo’s flavian politics: The Workings of power in Valerius flaccus 157 Peter J. Davis vi contents chapter 9. compulsory freedom: literature in Trajan’s rome 176 John Penwill chapter 10. christian correspondences: The Secrets of letter- Writers and letter- Bearers 209 Pauline Allen chapter 11. “Silence is Also Annulment”: Veiled and Unveiled Speech in Seventh- century Martyr commemorations 233 Bronwen Neil chapter 12. “Dixit quod nunquam vidit hereticos”: dissimulation and Self- censorship in Thirteenth- century inquisitorial Testimonies 251 Megan Cassidy- Welch chapter 13. inquisition, Art, and Self- censorship in the early Modern Spanish church, 1563–1834 269 François Soyer chapter 14. Thomas hobbes and the problem of Self- censorship 293 Jonathan Parkin epilogue 318 Han Baltussen and Peter J. Davis list of contributors 321 index 323 Acknowledgments 329 chapter 1 Parrhêsia, free Speech, and Self- censorship Han Baltussen and Peter J. Davis prologue Jocasta: What is hard for exiles? Polynices: one thing is biggest: he has no parrhêsia. Jocasta: Not saying what you think, that’s typical of a slave. Jocasta: That is painful, being foolish with the foolish. Polynices: for the sake of gain you have to be a slave against your nature. — euripides, Phoenician Women in this brief exchange between a mother and her exiled son, euripides has Jocasta and polynices discuss the place of parrhêsia in fifth- century Athenian thinking.1 first, parrhêsia is the property of a free citizen: it characterizes a man who is free (i.e., he is not a slave) and who participates in the affairs of his native city (i.e., he is not an exile). Second, parrhêsia is defined not as “free speech” as commonly understood in the twenty- first century, as a universal human right, but as “frank speech,” the ability to “say what you think.” in the view of Jocasta and polynices, slaves and exiles must hide their true thoughts. The tension between “frank speech,” typical of the ideal free citizen, and the art of “veiled speech,” that is, the methods of expression adopted by the less- t han- free, is this book’s central theme. This opening chapter both sets out the broader conceptual framework we 2 han Baltussen and peter J. davis use for this collection and clarifies the ways in which subsequent chapters share this common theme of veiled speech and self- censorship. one point in need of clarification is why we focus on veiled speech as a form of subversion. Another is what the common thread is in the selection of authors ranging “from Aristophanes to hobbes,” despite their chronological spread and range of different historical and literary contexts. We have taken a broad sweep at the evidence because censorship is a phenomenon that seems to have no temporal or geographical boundaries: it characterizes both totalitarian dictatorships and liberal democracies from an- cient Athens to the twentieth century and is still with us in the twenty- first. While the centralized forms of censorship practiced in countries like china and iran are notorious, we should not forget that even states with a constitu- tional commitment to freedom of speech impose limits on that freedom; nowhere is the right absolute. And this is not by any means a bad thing.2 how to balance the right to free speech against other legitimate concerns is a pe- rennial issue. The most extreme form of free speech is no doubt frank speech, parrhêsia, which etymologically originates in pan (“everything”) and rhêsia (“speaking”): in other words, the freedom to “say all.” But it will be obvious that in practice this is hardly ever possible. cultural and social conventions impose limits on what we can say, whether in interactions between private persons (family, friends, colleagues) or in the public sphere between individu- als and the state. in general terms, censorship can be defined as the regulation of a person’s political and moral expression by the imposition of limits on the free circulation of ideas, images, and information.3 All democratic states rec- ognize that there is an inherent tension between the individual’s right to free speech and the public’s interest in such matters as privacy, security, the ad- ministration of justice, and the protection of community standards. The collection’s chronological spread of essays was chosen to cover a number of flashpoints in classical and later periods, ending just before the modern age when the concept was about to change (Bce: fifth, fourth to third, and first centuries; ce: first, second, fourth to sixth, seventh, thir- teenth, sixteenth to seventeenth, and eighteenth centuries). it should be kept in mind that the selection is also in part a result of the availability of good material, especially in periods when the tension around free speech (and at- tempts to control it) intensified, as for instance in imperial rome or the christian era. furthermore, the essays cover not only different literary genres (that is, poetic texts as well as historical, epistolary, and philosophical prose) and many periods in history, but also many modes of expression (the Parrhêsia, free Speech, and Self- censorship 3 collection is “multimodal” in that it makes use of examples from oral culture and theater, written sources, and images to illustrate the persistent presence of self-r egulating measures by writers and creative artists of a variety of works). These three aspects of the topic under scrutiny (diversity in chronology, theme, and medium) raise another issue regarding the theoretical framework of this collection. These considerations about the ubiquity of self- censorship not only help to illustrate that this is a perennial problem, but also help to define self- regulation as a social and cultural phenomenon. While traditional treatments tend to position the discourse on censorship solely within the political environment, there is as yet little debate on self- regulation in antiq- uity. in other words, these essays are taking the first steps to study this aspect based on carefully selected samples, and the volume as a whole puts forward a number of claims that we hope will change the focus and widen the scope regarding the debate on parrhêsia and the limits different groups choose to impose on it. While it would go too far to claim that our investigations will produce a “theory” of self-c ensorship, the chapters clearly emphasize the many ways in which the (potentially) oppressed respond to the threat of controlling au- thorities. As a result a picture emerges that throws light on the dynamics of the subtle subversion in different kinds of context. By carefully defining the core terms such as parrhêsia, libertas, and (self-) censorship, we aim to ensure that our perspective is built on clear principles and distinctive from the stan- dard one, in which the censoring party is often central and regularly subjected to a modern (negative) judgment. The evidence also justifies the importance of antiquity— which is why the weight of chapters leans toward classical and late antique/medieval times. The inclusion of two chapters relating to the early modern period puts us in a position to add a further dimension to the discussion (the religious censure of images), and to sketch the views of a theorist about self- censorship based on his own experience (suppression of his work).4 combined, the chapters show how the concrete situations that are analyzed underscore the social ori- gin of subversion and censorship. Thus each chapter shores up the broader thesis we articulate. We hope that this will eventually allow for a theoretical framework that clarifies the dynamics between “oppressors” and “the op- pressed,” even if (1) we use these terms not just in a political sense, (2) we privilege the perspective of the oppressed (and those under the threat of op- pression), and (3) we allow for some gaps in coverage— it is impossible to