ebook img

The Affirmation of Life: Nietzsche on Overcoming Nihilism PDF

349 Pages·2008·2.52 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The Affirmation of Life: Nietzsche on Overcoming Nihilism

The Affirmation of Life The Affirmation of Life BERNARD REGINSTER To my father and the memory of my mother Preface The present book develops a systematic interpretation of Nietzsche's ethical thought. I have relied on the critical edition of Nietzsche's works by Colli and Montinari, and I have referred to the still-classic translations of his works by Walter Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale, including, no doubt controversially, their collaborative translation of The Will to Power. I have done so on the assumption that these are the translations with which the reader is most likely to be familiar. However, I have also consulted some new translations, such as that of On the Genealogy of Morality by Maudemarie Clark and A. J. Swensen. In general, I have left those translations intact, occasionally reproducing the original German, except in a few cases in which I estimated that they were simply too misleading. For Kant and Schopenhauer, I have also used the classic translations, and relied on the standard Akademie edition of Kant's original works, and the Brockaus complete edition of Schopenhauer's original works. Here, too, I have remained largely faithful to the translations. I have indicated omissions of parts of the original text in all of my quotations with the convention "[ ... ]." I gratefully acknowledge permission to reproduce the following of my already- published materials: parts of "Nietzsche on Ressentiment and Valuation" in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (June 1997), pp. 281-305, have been reproduced in Chapter 6; parts of "Happiness as a Faustian Bargain" in Daedalus 133 (2) (Spring 2004), pp. 52-59, have been used in Chapters 3 and 6; and parts of "Nihilism and the Affirmation of Life" in International Studies in Philosophy 34(3) (2002), pp. 55-68, have been used in Chapters 1 and 6. Portions of this book were written under the auspices of the National Humanities Center, at which I was a fellow during spring 2000. I am deeply grateful for the support I received then. I have also, to varying degrees, incurred debts of gratitude to many colleagues, friends, and students during the conception and preparation of this book. They include, in alphabetical order, R. Lanier Anderson, Neera Badhwar, Akeel Bilgrami, Justin Broackes, Maudemarie Clark, Garrett Deckel, James Dreir, Jorge Fernandez, Harold Hodes, Robert Howell, Nadeem Hussain, Jonathan Ichikawa, George Kateb, Jaegwon Kim, Joshua Landy, Charles Larmore, Brian Leiter, Wolfgang Mann, Frederick Neuhouser, Martha Nussbaum, Robert Pippin, John Richardson, Matthias Risse, Ivan Soll, Richard Schacht, R. Jay Wallace, and Linda Zag- zebsky. I owe special thanks to Alexander Nehamas, who showed me the possibility of an interpretation of Nietzsche that is at once philosophical and distinctive, and to Robert Howell and Brian Leiter, who wrote detailed comments on the entire manuscript. It is in spite of the assistance of all mentioned here that this book remains marred by many shortcomings. I have also benefited from discussions following presentations of parts of this book with audiences at Brown University, the University of Illinois at Champaign-Urbana, Stanford University, Cornell University, Wellesley College, the University of New Mexico, the University of Oklahoma, the Radcliffe Seminar at Harvard University, the Rhode Island Philosophical Society, the International Nietzsche Tagung in Naumburg, and the Nietzsche Kolleg at the Goethe-Schiller Stiftung at Weimar, and at various meetings of the North American Nietzsche Society. Contents Abbreviations Xi Introduction 1 1 Nihilism 21 2 Overcoming Disorientation 54 3 The Will to Power 103 4 Overcoming Despair 148 5 The Eternal Recurrence 201 6 Dionysian Wisdom 228 Notes 271 Bibliography 301 Index 309 Abbreviations Primary sources from Nietzsche, Schopenhauer, and Kant are cited in the text by abbreviation and according to prevalent conventions. WORKS BY NIETZSCHE Nietzsche's works are cited by section number and, when applicable, by chapter as well: for example, On the Genealogy of Morals, chapter III, section 11 is cited as GM, III 11. In the case of Thus Spoke Zarathustra, I will also include within brackets the number of a subsection when applicable: for example, Z, III 12 [16]. Finally, I cite fragments from the posthumous notes in accordance to their classification in the Kritische Studienausgabe: for example, KSA 14 [453]. And I cite published texts from that edition by volume and page numbers: for example, KSA, I, pp. 783-792. WORKS BY SCHOPENHAUER Schopenhauer's works are cited by section number and, when applicable, by volume as well. Since the sections can be quite lengthy, I have also mentioned the translation's page number of the quotation: for example, The World as Will and Representation, volume I, section 57, p. 312 is cited as WWR, I 57, p. 312. Note that the chapters of the second volume of that work are numbered with roman numerals. WORKS BY KANT Kant's works are cited by page numbers from the so-called Akademie edition. For example, the Groundwork for a Metaphysics of Morals, Ak. p. 412 is cited as GW p. 412. -WALLACE STEVENS, SUNDAY MORNING Introduction 1. The Systematicity of Nietzsche's Thought On November 13, 1888, a mere few weeks before his final collapse into insanity, Nietzsche makes the following announcement, in a letter to his friend Franz Overbeck: "The printing of Twilight of the Idols, or How to Philosophize with a Hammer is finished; the manuscript of Ecce Homo: How One Becomes What One Is is already at the printer's. The latter, an absolutely important book, gives some psychological and even biographical details about me and my writings; people will at last suddenly see me. The tone of the work, one of gay detachment fraught with a sense of destiny, as is everything I write. Then at the end of next year the first book of the revaluation will appear. It is finished."' Ecce Homo, the last original work Nietzsche was ever to complete,2 has all the trappings of an intellectual testament, from its title-"Ecce Homo" is an invitation to "behold the man" who is here presenting himself-to its content-Nietzsche reviews the nature and the significance of his intellectual contribution in a series of provocatively titled chapters ("Why I Am So Wise," "Why I Am So Clever," "Why I Write Such Good Books," and "Why I Am a Destiny"). This "absolutely important book" closes with a last, anxious plea for understanding: "Have I been understood?-Dionysus versus the Crucified.-" (EH, IV 9). By that time, the figure of Dionysus has fully assumed the role of symbol for an ideal Nietzsche calls the "affirmation of life," whereas "the Crucified," an expression that traditionally refers to the Pauli nian conception of Christ, represents the opposite ideal of negation of life. The strategically significant location of these words unequivocally suggests, in my view, that Nietzsche regards the affirmation of life as his defining philosophical achievement. We truly "understand" him, he warns us, only insofar as we understand what the affirmation of life amounts to. Yet, in spite of the formidable literature on Nietzsche's work, we still lack an adequate and compelling account of both the nature and the significance of this notion in his philosophy. Moreover, the project of a "revaluation of all values," to which the letter also refers, and which will prove to be an essential requirement of the affirmation of life, has generated hardly less puzzlement and controversy. The ambition of the present book is to articulate a systematic interpretation of Nietzsche's philosophical project that delivers a plausible and compelling account of the nature and significance of the affirmation of life and of the attendant project of a revaluation of values. To fulfill this ambition, the interpretation I will develop here differs from most existing interpretations both in its broad outline and in its details. Since the differences in details are best revealed in the examination of specific issues, I will focus here on the distinctive traits of the broad structure of my interpretation. Existing interpretations of Nietzsche's philosophy fall roughly within two categories. Some take the studied disorderliness of his writings to signal the lack of a central, systematizing thought and adopt a piecemeal thematic approach: they pull scattered texts together to determine what his views are in metaphysics, epistemology, ethics, and so on.3 Since Nietzsche does develop views in all these areas, such interpretations can be very helpful. But this approach also invites worries about contrivance and anachronism. Moreover, if Nietzsche's particular views are animated by a fundamental philosophical motivation, as I believe they are, this approach runs the risk of missing it, and therefore of misunderstanding them. Other interpretations favor a more global systematic approach, which consists in identifying a central doctrine in Nietzsche's philosophy and understanding everything else in relation to it.4 Existing systematic interpretations have often managed to account for many of those themes Nietzsche himself saw as his most important philosophical contributions-namely, nihilism, the revaluation of values (which includes the critique of morality), perspectivism, the will to power, the eternal recurrence, and the affirmation of life. But they have not succeeded in accounting for all of them or, at any rate, in explaining their importance in Nietzsche's eyes. And they have also overlooked themes that are no less important for being more implicit, such as, for example, Nietzsche's ubiquitous concern with the problem of suffering. One shortcoming, in particular, is common to all existing interpretations: none has yet been able to explain adequately why Nietzsche regards the affirmation of life as his defining philosophical achievement. The systematic approach I adopt in this book will, at the outset, encounter resistance, for it does not sit well with Nietzsche's famous quip against systematization: "I mistrust all systematizers. The will to a system is a lack of

Description:
Among all the great thinkers of the past two hundred years, Nietzsche continues to occupy a special place--not only for a broad range of academics but also for members of a wider public, who find some of their most pressing existential concerns addressed in his works. Central among these concerns is
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.