ebook img

The Abolition of Slavery and the End of International War PDF

36 Pages·2008·4.28 MB·English
by  
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview The Abolition of Slavery and the End of International War

The Abolition of Slavery and the End of International War Author(s): James Lee Ray Source: International Organization, Vol. 43, No. 3 (Summer, 1989), pp. 405-439 Published by: The MIT Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2706653 . Accessed: 15/10/2011 23:39 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. The MIT Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to International Organization. http://www.jstor.org The abolition of slavery and the end of international war James Lee Ray In A Study of War,Q uincy Wrighto bserves that "war ... is found in nearly all existing groups, however primitive."'IT he origins of slavery may well have involved a combinationo f warfarea nd economic incentives, as noted by Will Durant: "The rise of agriculture . . . led to the employment of the socially weak by the socially strong; not till then did it occur to the victor in war that the only good prisoner is a live one. Butchery and cannibalism lessened, slavery grew.... Warh elped to make slavery, and slavery helped to make war."2 In additiont o this hypothesized connection between their origins, slavery and war have also shared an assumed common base in "human nature." That is, for thousands of years even many of those with the best minds assumed that war and slavery were naturala nd thereforei nevitable. In this view, accordingt o KennethW altz, "Ourm iseriesa re ineluctablyt he product of our natures. The root of all evil is man, and thus he is himself the root of the specific evil, war. This estimate of cause . . . has been immensely influential.I t is the conviction of St. Augustine and Luther, of Malthusa nd An earlier version of this article was presented at the annual meeting of the International Studies Association, St. Louis, 29 Marcht o 2 April 1988. EimadH oury, Allen Joseph, Mihali Krassacopoulos,P atriciaM orris,a nd Mi Yung Yoon made helpfulc ommentso n that version. I am especially gratefulf or the criticismsa nd suggestionso f GilbertA bcarian,D ale L. Smith, Stephen D. Krasner,a nd anonymousr eviewers for InternationalO rganization. 1. Quincy Wright,A Study of War, 2d ed. (Chicago:U niversityo f ChicagoP ress, 1965),p . 36. 2. Will Durant,O ur OrientalH eritage (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1951),p . 20. See also L. T. Hobhouse, Morals in Evolution,4 th ed. (London:C hapman& Hall, 1923),p . 272. "Two conditions," asserts Hobhouse, "suffice to insure the growth of slavery ... in the savage world. The first conditioni s a certaind evelopmento f industrialization."(B y this he means, it is obvious from the context, agriculture.)" In a huntingt ribe, which lives from handt o mouth, there is little occasion for the services of a slave." Hobhouse then explains that the second condition is "warlike prowess," thus also pointingt o war as the interveningv ariable, so to speak, between the rise of agriculturea nd the appearanceo f slavery. International Organization 43, 3, Summer 1989 ?) 1989b y the WorldP eace Foundationa nd the MassachusettsI nstituteo f Technology 406 InternationalO rganization JonathanS wift, of Dean Inge and ReinholdN iebuhr". 93 Aristotle, the "great- est philosopher and scientist of the ancient world,"4 believed that some "'people are slaves by nature.... For a man who is able to belong to another person is by nature a slave (for that is why he belongs to someone else Almost two thousand years later, John Locke was still de- . . . )."15 fendingt he enslavement of foreign captives, and "no realistic leader" in the 1700s considered the abolition of slavery a reasonable possibility in the foreseeable future.6 Nevertheless, slavery was effectively abolishedi n the nineteenthc entury.7 Its disappearancer enders plausible the possibility that within decades both slavery and internationalw ar will seem quainta nd unthinkablei n the modern age. Skepticism about such a proposition may be almost universal, but as Samuel Kim points out, "For centuries slavery was 'imagined' as an im- mutable part of the natural social order. Hence it was utopian to advocate its abolition."8 In a similar vein, Robert Axelrod observes that "'a major goal of investigatingh ow cooperative norms in societal settings have been established is a better understandingo f how to promote cooperative norms in internationals ettings. This is not as utopian as it might seem because international norms against slavery . . . are already strong."9 The main implication (at least from the perspective of this article) of Axelrod's ar- gumenti s clear. Slavery has disappearedb ecause internationanl ormsa gainst 3. KennethW altz, Man, the State, and War( New York:C olumbiaU niversityP ress, 1959), p. 3. 4. Michael H. Hart, The 100: A Ranking of the Most Influential Persons in History (New York: A & W Publishing,1 978),p . 105. 5. Quote from Aristotle's Politics, cited in David Brion Davis, Slavery and Human Progress (New York:O xfordU niversityP ress, 1984),p . 3. See also WayneA mbler," Aristotleo n Nature and Politics:T he Case of Slavery," Political Theory1 5 (August 1987),p p. 390-410; and Wylie Sypher, "Hutchesona nd the 'Classical'T heory of Slavery," TheJ ournalo f Negro Slavery2 4 (July 1939),p . 264. Ambleri nsists that Aristotleh as been misinterpretedo n this point and that Aristotle's standardsf or "natural"s lavery were so demandingt hat in effect he was speaking out againsts lavery as it was actuallyp racticed.I f Ambleri s correct, the followingo bservation by Sypheri s especially ironic:" For generationsb efore Europeb ecame awareo f the barbarous treatmento f Negro slaves in the New Worldc olonies, jurists and philosophersa ccepted as a mattero f course the 'classical' theory of slavery expoundedi n Aristotle'sP olitics." 6. Davis, Slavery and Human Progress, pp. 107-8. In anotherw ork, Davis notes that Ben- jamin Franklino wned Negro slaves as late as 1750,a nd "it would appeart hat his desire to get rid of them was more a producto f racial prejudicet han humanitarianism."S ee David Brion Davis, The Problem of Slavery in Western Culture (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1966), p. 426. 7. Admittedly,s lavery has not been completelye radicatedi n moderno r even contemporary times. "The institutionw as finally outlawed by Saudi Arabiai n 1962a nd by the Sultanateo f Muscat and Oman in 1970," accordingt o Davis, Slavery and Human Progress, p. 379. Fur- thermore, Stalin and Hitler both made massive use of slave labor, and even today there is a controversya bout slavery in the Sudan. See UshariA hmadM ahmuda nd SuleymanA li Baldo, Al Diein Massacre: Slavery in the Sudan (Khartoum: University of Khartoum, 1987). 8. Samuel Kim, The Questf or a Just WorldO rder( Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press, 1984), p. 81. 9. Robert Axelrod, "An EvolutionaryA pproacht o Norms," American Political Science Review 80 (December 1986),p . 1110. Internationalw ar 407 it are strong; presumably, additionale vils such as internationalw ar might also disappear, and for similarr easons. In this article, I address the validity of an argumentb ased on an analogy between the abolitiono f slavery and the demise of internationalw ar. I begin with a discussion of the rise and fall of slavery, placing special emphasis on the contending explanations of slavery's disappearance. Next, I analyze competing theoretical approachest o the role of ethical constraintsi n inter- national politics. This discussion of slavery's demise and the theoretical considerationo f the role of ethics in internationalp olitics then serves as the basis for an evaluation of the assertion that the fate of slavery portends the coming end of internationalw ar. Explaining slavery's demise: moral progress or declining profitability? Slavery was common in ancient Egypt, Babylonia, Assyria, Greece, Rome, India, and China. The extent to which ancient Greece relied on slaves plays an importantr ole in two controversies relevant to the focus of this article, possibly because the practice became prominenti n Greece.'0 One contro- versy, cited by Moses Finley, involves the juxtaposition of the emergence of important" Western" or liberal values and the concomitant prevalence of slavery: "The cities in which individual freedom reached its highest expression-most obviously Athens-were cities in which chattel slavery flourished."" That the Greeks could formulate and espouse the values of individualf reedom and democracy and simultaneouslye nslave so many in their midst suggests that moralv alues do not have a powerfuld eterrente ffect on slavery as a social practice. The extent to which ancient Greece dependedo n slavery is also important to an evaluation of a standardM arxist interpretationo f history, which fo- cuses on "conflicts of economic classes correspondingt o specific modes of production, such as slavery, feudalism, or capitalism."1 2 Ancient Greece, in the view of FriedrichE ngels, was cruciallyd ependento n slavery: "With- out slavery, no Greek state, no Greek art and science; without slavery, no Roman empire . . . no modern Europe . . . no modern socialism."1 3 Just 10. "Though actual slaves never formed a significant percentage of the population of China, or ancient Egypt, in Greece . . . the number kept increasing from the Persian Wars to the time of Alexander," according to Davis, The Problem of Slavery, p. 75. 11. See Moses I. Finley, "Was Greek Civilization Based on Slave Labor?" in Moses I. Finley, ed., Slavery in Classical Antiquity: Views and Controversies (Cambridge: W. Heffer, 1960), p. 3; cited in Davis, The Problem of Slavery. 12. Albert Fried and Ronald Sanders, eds., Socialist Thought (Garden City, N.Y.: Anchor Books, 1964), p. 278. 13. Quote from Friedrich Engels' essay, "Herr Eugen Duhring's Revolution in Science (Anti- Duhring)," cited in M. M. Bober, Karl Marx's Interpretation of History (New York: Norton, 1965), p. 50. 408 InternationalO rganization how important slavery was in the Roman Empire is a question that has generateda controversym uch like that concerningG reece. Marxists cholars agree that it was quite importanta nd that a fundamentalc ause of Roman imperialismw as the economy's need for slaves. But David Brion Davis, in a mannert ypical of critics of Marxista nalyses, asserts that the Romans did not in fact establish an empire for the purpose of acquiring slaves, even though he does acknowledge that "the Roman empire . . . bequeathed to Christian Europe the juridical and philosophical foundations for modern slavery." 14 The practice of slavery became distinctly less prevalent as the Roman Empire declined, and for Marxists the reasons are clear. When slavery disappears,i t does so because it is replacedb y a more efficienta nd therefore more progressive mode of production.B ut Davis points out that "the prob- lem of the decline of slavery in later Romanh istory is so entangledw ith the question of the decline of the Empire itself that one must be suspicious of any simple explanation."5' One can surmise that the "simple" explanation evoking the most suspicion in Davis's mind is the Marxist model, which suggests that slavery gave way to feudalismi n a naturalp rogressionb ecause of internalc ontradictionsi n the slave system. The details of this process are clearly debatable. "What are the productivef orces liberatedb y slavery that unavoidably create a higher order . . . ? Does a slave mode of production inevitably produce circumstances which must result in feudalism?" asks M. M. Bober in Karl Marx's Interpretation of History. In Bober's opinion, at least, there is "no answer" to these questions.'6N evertheless, it is quite clear that in Western Europe "slavery declined and then virtually disap- peared with the emergence of the feudal system." 17 Moral progress may have had something to do with this development. John Nef points out that "before Dante's time [1215-1321A .D.], slavery had almost entirelyd isappeareda mongt he Christianp eoples of WesternE urope, partly, as Montesquieul ater assumed, 'because the law of the church made it inadmissablet o reduce to servitude a brother in Christ.' "18 But slavery did not entirely disappear from Europe in the Middle Ages; slavery-like serfdomt hrivedi n Europef or centuries;a nd most important,m any powerful European states were on the verge of inauguratingt he great transatlantic slave trade in the following centuries. It is therefore difficultt o sustain an argumentt hat the decline of slavery in medieval Europe was primarilyt he result of an emerging moral consensus that slavery was wrong. The reluc- tance of Christianst o enslave other Christiansc an be seen as an important step in the direction of forming that consensus, but it seems that where 14. Davis, Slavery and Human Progress, p. 27. 15. Davis, The Problem of Slavery, p. 37. 16. Bober, Karl Marx's Interpretation of History, p. 54. 17. Davis, The Problem of Slavery, p. 37. 18. John U. Nef, War and Human Progress (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1950), p. 232. Internationalw ar 409 slavery did disappeari n Europe, it was largely because economic processes made it outmoded and less profitable." The decline of slavery was not due to moral progress," asserts Durant in The Age of Faith (focusing on the Middle Ages), "but to economic change. Productionu nder direct physical compulsion proved less profitableo r convenient than productionu nder the stimulus of acquisitive desire."19 Slavery in the New World The discovery of the New World created powerful economic incentives that led to a resurgence of slavery on a grand scale-probably, in fact, the grandest of all time.20I n the period from 1502 to almost 1900, slaves were brought from Africa to the Americas by the millions. (Native Americans were used as slaves in the earlier years, but they proved "unsuitable" in several ways, one of which was a stubbornt endency to die.) Great Britain officially prohibitedt he slave trade in 1807 and played a role in bringingi t to a virtualh alt by the latter half of the nineteenthc entury. The Britisha lso legally ended slavery in territories under their control in 1833, while the Civil Warb roughti t to an end in the United States by 1865.C uba and Brazil were the last holdouts in the Western hemisphere;s lavery was abolished in Cuba in 1886, while Brazil officially terminatedi t in 1888. Many of the most influentiali nterpretationso f the demise of slavery in the Western hemisphere have been "economistic,"s21 whether devised by classical or liberal theorists on the one hand or by Marxist, radical scholars on the other. As Davis indicates, both schools of thought convey "the comfortablea ssurance that slavery was doomed by impersonall aws of his- torical progress and that economic development ensured . . . social and moral betterment."22I n short, both liberals and radicals, in their analyses of slavery, typically exhibit a common faith in the rationality or utility- maximizingb ehavioro f those involved in exploitings lave labor. When slav- ery disappears,i n this view, it must have been forced out by a more efficient system of production.23 Classical analyses of the demise of slavery that focus on market forces date directly back to Adam Smith. In The Wealtho f Nations, Smith argued 19. Will Durant, The Age of Faith (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1950), p. 524. 20. Howard Temperley, "Capitalism, Slavery, and Ideology," Past and Present 75 (May 1977), p. 94. 21. Richard K. Ashley, "Three Modes of Economism," International Studies Quarterly 24 (December 1983), pp. 463-96. 22. Davis, Slavery and Human Progress, p. xiv. 23. This similarity in the views of classicists and Marxists is arguably less anomalous than it might appear at first glance. See George Soule, Ideas of Great Economists (New York: Mentor, 1952), p. 63. Soule points out that "the economic theory developed in Capital is almost wholly classical, much though the discovery may surprise both orthodox followers of Smith and Ricardo as well as orthodox socialists. Marx used no assumption not outlined by some writer of the classical school, and his method of reasoning was, like theirs, deduction from a few relatively simple postulates." 410 InternationalO rganization that slaves can have no interest but "to eat as much as possible and to labour as little as possible" and that work done by slaves is inevitablyt he "dearest of any" (that is, grossly inefficient)a nd thus bound to disappeari f market forces are allowed to operate.24D avis states that "Smith was certain," for example, "that economic causes explainedt he abolitiono f bondagei n West- ern Europe. Landowners simply came to realize that their profits would increase by giving labor a share of the produce.' '25 If slave labor is in principle so relatively unproductive,w hy did it appear in the first place? Smith explained this anomaly for his theory with a rather obviously ad hoc modification:h e asserted that slave owners engaged in the dominationo f inferiorso ut of a love of power, even to the detrimento f their economic self-interest.26 Marxista nalystsa re usuallym ore theoreticallyc onsistent. Slaverya ppears and disappears, in their view, as the result of marketf orces. Slavery must have been "rational"; otherwise the practice would not have been devel- oped. Likewise, when it disappears,i t does so because the dialecticalp rocess has reached the point at which a new mode of productionh as become more efficient. One of the most noted contemporarya nalyses of the disappearanceo f slavery in the Western hemisphere is that of Eric Williams in Capitalism and Slavery, which focuses on the history of slavery in the British West Indies. Williams' thesis is straightforward:" When British capitalism de- pended on the West Indies, they ignored or defended it. When British cap- italism found the West Indian monopoly a nuisance, they destroyed West Indian slavery as a first step in the destructiono f the West Indian monop- oly. " 27 The thesis most cleary in contrast to the "economistic" arguments of Williams and others emphasizes the importance of moral progress in the process that broughta bout the eliminationo f slavery in the Western hemi- sphere. CraneB rinton,i n A History of WesternM orals, succinctly describes the heart of this debate: The prize exhibit of those who can still believe in moral progress is the Western achievement of abolishing chattel slavery.... The Marxists, and not only the Marxists, never tire of insisting that slavery has al- ways prevailed where it was economically profitablea nd has only been abolished after it has been demonstratedt o at least most slave-owners ... that slavery is unprofitable.... The honest materialistw ould have to admit that the completeness of abolition can be explained only by 24. Adam Smith, The Wealth of Nations (New York: Norton, 1937), p. 63. 25. Davis, The Problem of Slavery, p. 434. 26. Ibid. 27. Eric Williams, Capitalism and Slavery (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1944), p. 169. Internationalw ar 411 the fact that the overwhelmingm ajorityo f Westernersc ame in a few generations to feel that slavery is wrong.28 Economism versus idealism The British, abolition in the West Indies, and the end of the Atlantic slave trade. The debate between adherentst o economistic models on the one hand and defenders of moral progress on the other focuses on the motives of policymakersa nd other political and economic agents involved in the abo- lition of slavery, motives that were invisible and perhaps even obscured intentionally. Who knows what evil (or virtue) lurks in the hearts of men (or persons)? Nevertheless, there are differences in the empiricali mplica- tions of these competing models which may allow at least a tentative eval- uation of their relative validity. The economistic models, but not their com- petitors, suggest that at some point slave owners realized that slave labor had become relatively unprofitablea nd then more or less voluntarilyg ave up their slaves in order to move on to some more profitablem ode of pro- duction. But, as HowardT emperleyp oints out, "Virtuallyw ithoute xception the principald efenders of slavery were, in fact, the slaveholderst hemselves [and] . . . by contrast, those who spearheaded the attack on slavery were almost invariablym en with no direct economic stake in the institution.'' 29 Economistic models also suggest that once slave owners had done the rightt hingf rom an "expected utility" point of view, they reapedt he benefits of their wisdom. Models emphasizingi dealism and moral progress, in con- trast, imply that abolitiono ccurs even in the absence of an economic payoff and perhaps even in the face of economic costs, since profit and loss cal- culations have not been central, in this view, to the process that eliminated slavery. In the key case of the West Indies, the economistic implicationt hat ab- olition was profitablet urns out ratherc learly to be wrong. Sugarp roduction in the wake of abolition dropped precipitously-by a third overall and by as much as 50 percent in specific cases, such as Jamaica.30T his hurt not only the formers lave owners but also those who marketeda nd bought sugar in Great Britain. Partly as a result of the abolition of slavery in the West Indies, sugarg rowersi n Cubaa nd Brazil steppedu p the importationo f slaves and the export of sugart o GreatB ritain.H avinge ffectively abolisheds lavery in their own colonial holdings, the British stepped up the pressure against the traffic in slaves to Cuba and Brazil. The economistic interpretationo f this British policy is that it was a rationala ttempt by the British to prevent competitorsf romo btainings lave labori n ordert o protectt he sugarp roducers 28. Crane Brinton, A History of Western Morals (New York: Harcourt, Brace, 1959), pp. 435-36. 29. Temperley, "Capitalism, Slavery, and Ideology," p. 97. 30. Ibid., p. 103. 412 InternationalO rganization in their own colonies.31 But denying the Brazilians,f or example, free access to slaves deprived the British of access to the cheap sugar and other com- modities those newly imported slaves would have produced, and it also depressedt he marketf or Britishe xports that could have been created among slave owners and others in Brazil who might have reaped the economic benefits of selling those slave-producedc ommodities.32 The abolition of slavery and of slave trade, then, was not clearly an economically rational move by the British. Admittedly, the argumentt hat abolition was based primarilyo n ethical considerationsi s weakened by the fact that abolitionists as well as their opponents made consistent attempts to conceal theirm otives.33F urthermoreT, emperleym akes a convincingc ase for his assertion that abolitionistsi n Britaini n the 1830sb elieved that ending slavery would bringe conomic benefits to Britain,t hus creatingd oubts about the relative importance of the contributions of economic incentives and ethical constraintst o the success of that movement.34N evertheless, evidence regardingt he economically damaging effects of the abolition of both the slave trade and slavery is sufficient to underminet o an importantd egree economistic explanationso f Great Britain's role in slavery's demise. Tem- perley, for example, concludes that Eric Williams' "own evidence fails to supporth is conclusions . .. [and]f urthere vidence shows that the dominant economic interests in Britain,f ar from being impelled to weaken or destroy slavery, would have profitedf rom strengtheninga nd extending it."35 Simi- larly, David Eltis asserts that the slave trade in the Americas was "killed when its significance ... was greater than at any point in its history.... For [the] British, . . . there was profoundi ncompatibilityb etween economic 31. See, for example, Thomas E. Skidmore and Peter H. Smith, Modern Latin America (New York: Oxford University Press, 1984), p. 148. These authors point out that in 1826 "Britain got from Brazil a treaty commitment to end the slave trade by 1830. The British wanted this commitment for several reasons. One, usually stressed by modern day economic historians, is that Britain feared that slave-produced sugar from Brazil would prove cheaper in the world market than sugar from the British West Indies, where slavery had recently been abolished." Skidmore and Smith unwittingly undermine the economistic argument here, since slavery was not in fact abolished in the British West Indies until 1833, which was seven years after the date (1826) they obtained the commitment from Brazil to end the slave trade by 1830. They also explicitly support the "idealistic" or "moral progress" model, asserting that another reason for British action against the slave trade to Brazil was "pressure on the British government generated by British abolitionists" (p. 148). 32. David Eltis, Economic Growth and the Ending of the Transatlantic Slave Trade (New York: Oxford University Press, 1987), p. 12. 33. Davis, Slavery and Human Progress, p. 170. See also Roger Anstey, The Atlantic Slave Trade and British Abolition, 1760-1810 (Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press, 1975); and Seymour Drescher, Econocide: British Slavery in the Era of Abolition (Pittsburgh: Uni- versity of Pittsburgh Press, 1977). 34. Temperley, "Capitalism, Slavery, and Ideology," p. 118. 35. Howard Temperley, "Anti-Slavery as Cultural Imperialism," in Christine Bolt and Sey- mour Drescher, eds., Anti-Slavery, Religion, and Reform (Hamden, Conn.: Anchor Books, 1980), p. 339. Temperley cites Drescher, Econocide, in support of his assertion. In a later volume, Capitalism and Antislavery (New York: Macmillan, 1986), Drescher maintains that 'most of the specifics of Williams' economic argument have ... been undermined" (p. 2). Internationalw ar 413 self-interesta nd antislaveryp olicy." Furthermore,E ltis has no doubt about why the antislavery policy was adopted: "The set of beliefs that branded slavery and the slave trade as evil prevented the continuedi ncorporationo f the slave trade and slavery into the British and indeed the world economic system at a time when the British economy had the greatest need of such institutions."36D avis concurs: "Britain's dogged pursuit of foreign slavers was . . . contraryt o the nation's immediatep oliticala nd economic interests. The impetus behind British anti-slaveryp olicies was mainly religious. 37 The American Civil War and abolitionism. Slavery in the United States was abolished as a result of the Union's victory over the Confederacy in the Civil War. The impact of that war on the practice of slavery can be integratedi nto quite disparatee xplanatoryt hemes. One argues that slavery was not an importanti ssue in that struggle, and so its disappearancea fter the war was a side effect that cannot be convincinglya ttributedt o the ethical concerns of abolitionists in the North. Another interpretst he Civil War as a competition between one system based on "wage slavery" and another based on chattel slavery, with the victory of the former representingt he ascendance of a more efficient mode of production.38 But vital economic interests in the North, up to the time of the Civil War, profitedh andsomelyf rom the toil of slaves in the South. Accordingt o Tem- perley, "Northernc otton manufacturersw ere dependento n Southernp lan- tation agriculturef or their raw materials.N ew York financeh ouses provided Southernersw ith much of their capital and reaped their reward in interest. New Englands hippersc arriedt he South's cotton to the factories of Europe and the North."39 Granted, the clash of economic interests in the rapidly industrializing North and the primarilya griculturalS outh created several issues, such as the focus on tariffs, to cite a prominente xample, which made victory for the Union beneficial to the pocketbooks of many in the North. However, the predominante conomic classes in the North were not necessarily well served by the abolition of slavery in the South. The antislaveryp osition of the Union did bringc lear politicalb enefits, some of which were international in scope, and those benefits, arguably,f lowed ultimatelyf romt he widespread feeling that slavery was indefensibleo n ethical grounds. Even the South was responsive to such considerations, as Eltis makes clear: "One of the first actions of the Montgomery (Alabama)C onstitutionalC onvention of 1861, 36. Eltis, Economic Growth, pp. 15 and 28. 37. Davis, Slaverya nd HumanP rogress,p p. xxviii and2 36. See also IrvingK ristol," 'Human Rights':T he Hidden Agenda," The National Interest 6 (Winter1 986-87), p. 10. In this recent article on ethical issues in contemporaryi nternationapl olitics, Kristol asserts that "probably the 'purest'-most moral, least self-interested-foreign policy action ever taken on behalf of 'humanr ights'w as the Britishn avy's suppressiono f the slave tradei n the nineteenthc entury." 38. Arguments et forth by A. M. Simons in Class Struggle in America, a 1903p ublication cited in Temperley, "Capitalism,S lavery, and Ideology," pp. 101-2. 39. Temperley, "Capitalism,S lavery, and Ideology," pp. 101-2.

Description:
have involved a combination of warfare and economic incentives, as noted . Quote from Friedrich Engels' essay, "Herr Eugen Duhring's Revolution in Science (Anti- lem of the decline of slavery in later Roman history is so entangled with the .. Hans J. Morgenthau, Politics Among Nations, 4th ed.
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.