GROVE CITY COLLEGE The Abolition of Man Through Intellectual Property Kevin Rahbar Kevin Rahbar 1/29/2012 This paper explores the concept of owning ideas, intellectual property, the problems it causes in the market place, the place for intellectual property in Christendom, and the connection between intellectual property, liberty, and the human personality. 1 Introduction ―He who receives an idea from me, receives instruction himself without lessening mine; as he who lights his taper at mine, receives light without darkening me. Inventions then cannot, in nature, be a subject of property,‖ spoke Thomas Jefferson. It appears as though Jefferson was an advocate for the free exchange of ideas. Ideas can be spread but often there are barriers to the free use of an idea. Information, while readily available, can sometimes not be readily used. The institution of intellectual property has a long history and development, but the present author questions the legitimacy of the present system and will join the conversation surrounding this controversial subject matter. Intellectual property has been a subject of immense debate in politics, economics, history, ethics, philosophy, and legal studies. This paper will discuss the nature of ideas, the nature of property and intellectual property. We will also discuss the effects of intellectual property, the compatibility of intellectual property with a Christian world view, and defend the importance of the free spread of ideas. Intellectual property gives ownership over non-scarce intangible goods resulting in the implicit ownership of information in the minds of people which damages the extent of the market; this damage obfuscates the development of the human person because it stymies the creativity that is essential to man being an image-bearer of God. What are ideas? The most fundamental question that must be answered in our inquiry into intellectual property rights is: What are ideas? On both an ideological level and on a metaphysical level we need to determine the nature of ideas. Are ideas ends? Are ideas means? Are ideas in their own category? 2 Any definition of an idea that can or is used for an‖ idea‖ does not permit it to be ownable. An idea could most simply be defined as whatever is before the mind as one thinks. Ideas can represent images, concepts or a variety of other things. To possess an ideas is to be engaged in thinking which has been argued to be a fundamental category of being. Humans have the ability to create worlds, structures, images, literature, and solutions all in our minds. It is a direct reflection of the imago dei to be able to engage in a thinking process. In some ways we are even able to re-create and re-live events that have happened in the past. In other senses we are able to prepare in advance for what may happen. Plato was the father of discussing the nature of an idea, and opened up the discussion for the importance of ideas as it relates to metaphysics and epistemology. For Plato believed ideas are immutable, eternal, and perfect. Descartes believed ideas were an image or representation, but he did not think that these necessarily needed to exist ―in the mind.‖ Descartes said that, ―Some of my thoughts are like images of things, and it is to these alone that the name 'idea' properly belongs." He sometimes maintained that ideas were innate‖ (Descartes 1993, pp. 196-198). Locke differed from Plato in his conception of an idea. In Locke‘s Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Locke defines an idea as: [T]hat term which, I think, serves best to stand for whatsoever is the object of the understanding when a man thinks, I have used it to express whatever is meant by phantasm, notion, species, or whatever it is which the mind can be employed about in thinking; and I could not avoid frequently using it. Following Locke, Hume and Kant continued the discussion. Hume limited an idea to ambiguous mental constructions of perceptions, which he called ―impressions‖ (The Encyclopedia of Philosophy 1973, pp. 74-90). Kant defined an idea against a concept 3 (ibid. 973, pp. 74-90). ―Regulator ideas" are ideals that we move toward, but never fully accomplish. For example, liberty is an idea, and not a concept. G.F. Stout and J.M. Baldwin, in the Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology1, define idea as "the reproduction with a more or less adequate image, of an object not actually present to the senses." It is clear to see that none of these definitions implicitly or explicitly imply that an idea is ownable Are ideas means? In order for an idea to be a means, it must first be a good. Carl Menger provides us with four conditions that make a good. Let us examine if Menger‘s conditions line up with an idea being a mean. Menger (2007, p. 52) lists his four conditions for a good obtaining good-character: 1. A human need. 2. Such properties as render the thing capable of being brought into a causal connection with the satisfaction of this need. 3. Human knowledge of this causal connection. 4. Command of the thing sufficient to direct it to the satisfaction of the need. Menger goes on to explain that only if all four prerequisites are present can a thing become a good. Most helpful for our discussion of the issue of intellectual property rights is his fourth condition. Granted, Menger explicitly communicates that all four conditions must be present at the same time, the fourth condition is adequate to remove the possibility of an idea being a means; ideas are not directly serviceable. Under any of the definitions we have discussed so far of an idea, would any of them imply direct satisfaction of the end desired? For example, does having the idea of a new cell phone 1 See http://psychclassics.yorku.ca/Baldwin/Dictionary/ 4 design give one the ability to make phone calls? Does an idea of a new type of screen enable the viewing of images on that screen? Clearly, the answers are no.2 Mises (1998, p. 93) argues in the beginning of his well-regarded work, Human Action, the issue of ends and means stating, A thing becomes a means when human reason plans to employ it for the attainment of some end and human action really employs it for this purpose. Thinking man sees the serviceableness of things, i.e., their ability to minister to his ends, and acting man makes them means. It is of primary importance to realize that parts of the external world become means only through the operation of the human mind and is offshoot, human action… It is human meaning and action which transform them into means. Ideas are not sufficient to be means because the existence of the idea does not de facto mean that the end can be satisfied. Means can only become means through human action, and we will later see that the possession of an idea is not labor. Goods must be directly serviceable and means are only able to satisfy ends indirectly, but the prerequisites for human action are ideas, means, and ends. An idea alone will never satisfy an end. More could be said on the issue of an idea being an end, but we will refrain from further argumentation and simply posit that ideas are not means. Property, Intellectual Property, and Property Rights The next issue we must address is the question of what is intellectual property? However, in order to address the issue of intellectual property we need to determine what property is. To answer this question simply: property is anything that we can come to own.3 However, what can be property is a subject of debate. Locke contributed most notably to the creation argument that makes something property by stating it is done by 2 It might be objected that the idea could be an end. In that case you would have to have an idea about an idea and then means to apply your idea about your idea to arrive at your end. This leads to some fairly obvious logical issues. Additionally, Mises deal with creative acts of genius not being products of labor which is discussed later in this paper. 3See Boudewijn Bouckaert, ―What is Property?‖ in ―Symposium: Intellectual Property,‖ Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy 13, no. 3 (Summer 1990) for a more detailed discussion on what property is. 5 ―mixing your labor with an object, or clearing and cultivating virgin land‖ (Locke 1690). Locke also saw right of self-ownership as necessary for liberty. Ownership in ourselves is the foundation for ownership of alienable objects because they become assimilated to our bodies.4 There is not a large debate about the ownership of one‘s own body because ―self- ownership‖ has not been a problematic or controversial issue in the history of economic thought. The ownership of tangible goods has not historically been an issue is Christian thought or libertarian convention, but there has been and continues to be a discussion on the eligibility of ownership of intangible goods.5 Advocates for intellectual property law often use a Lockean-style natural law argument which states that creations of the mind are due equal protection under the law as tangible property (Kinsella 1998, p. 3). This argument does not see that intangible property is not naturally ―scarce‖ like tangible property.6 In Locke‘s view the state of nature contains natural property and therefore natural property which is economically scarce. Ownership is allocated to the first person that ―mixes his labor‖ with resources and property to solve the potential conflict that could happen from two people trying to use something. However, ―since use of another's idea does not deprive him of its use, no conflict over its use is possible, which undermines the natural-law justification for property rights in IP.‖7, 8 As Professor Tom Bell (Torremans 2007, p.54) writes, Locke‘s 4 See (Wheeler 1980, p. 171) 5 See (Khan 2008) and (Boldrin and Levine 2008, pp.48-67) for additional discussion on the history of intellecual property 6 See (Rothbard 2004, p. 173) for a discussion on radio waves. Rothbard was a head of his time but the discussion needs to be updated 7http://web.archive.org/web/20061213004018/ and http:/www.fedsoc.org/Publications/practicegroupnewsletters/intellectualproperty/legitimate-ipv3i3.htm 6 …labor-desert justification of property gives an author clear title only to the particular tangible copy in which she fixes her expression–not to some intangible plat in the noumenal realm of ideas. Locke himself did not try to justify intangible property. He appears, in fact, to have viewed copyright as merely a policy tool for promoting the public good. Modern commentators who would venture so far beyond the boundaries of Locke‘s thought and into the abstractions of intellectual property thus ought to leave his name behind. More succinctly, copyright contradicts Locke‘s justification of property.9 Copyright violates the very rights that Locke defended by silencing our voices, shackling our hands, and furthering ignorance. Locke did not consider his theory of property extending to copyrights and patents, stating in his Second Treatise of Civil Government, ―The labour that was mine, removing them out of that common state they were in, hath fixed my property in them.‖ The purpose of borders of owned things is to distinguish them from things one does not own. Labor does this by establishing a causal connection between the homesteader and the thing. In addition to answering the question of property, we must answer the issue of what a property right is. The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics defines property rights as a ―socially enforced right to select use of an economic good.‖10 As Hoppe notes in The Economics and Ethics of Private Property, ―According to this understanding of private property, property ownership means the exclusive control of a particular person over specific physical objects and spaces‖ (Hoppe n.d., p. 6). Is intellectual property be a socially enforceable right? 8 Ideas can be infinitely instantiated and therefore the use of one‘s idea never interferes with another‘s instantiation of an idea. 9 Locke described legislation authorizing the Stationers‘ Company monopoly on printing—the nearest thing to a Copyright Act in his day—as a ―manifest . . . invasion of the trade, liberty, and property of the subject.‖ Even today, by invoking government power a copyright holder can impose prior restraint, fines, imprisonment, and confiscation on those engaged in peaceful expression and the quiet enjoyment of physical property. 10 See Property rights in The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics 7 To begin, we must define what intellectual property is and come to an understanding of our terms. The scope of this paper will only deal with intellectual property in so far as it is used to refer to copyrights and patents. There are various definitions for intellectual property rights. Some have called it the construction of a scarce resource from knowledge or information (May and Sell 2006, p. 5). Other have called it the intangible items that typically produce or creates products, processes, expressions, marks or nonpublic information (Sun and Baez 2009, p. 1). It has also been expressed as rights in ideal objects, which are distinguished from the material substrata in which they are instantiated (Kinsella 2008, p. 9). Yet others claim it is a government issued monopoly (Boldrin and Levine 2008). A copyright is a right given to authors of ―original works,‖11 such as books articles, movies and computer programs. Copyrights give exclusive right to perform or present the work publicly; it protects form or expression, not the underlying ideas themselves (Kinsella, 2008, p. 10). Copyrights have been used for literary works and for media, including music and movies (Boldrin & Levine, 2008, p. 22). Copyrights deals with the written expression of ideas once they are reduced to a tangible form (Peloso, 2003, p. 35). A patent is a property right in inventions that performs a useful function. It grants the inventor a limited monopoly on manufacture, use or sale of the invention (Kinsella, 2008, pp. 10-11). Patents12 protect inventions and the laws are designed to 11 We will later explore the nonsensical nature of this distinction. 12 Patents, by definition are aimed to clock competition (Boldrin and Levine 2008, p. 77). A myriad of patents are created to keep competitors from creating anything that even remotely resembles their product or service. Patents come about for defensive reasons resulting in patent lawyer salaries and patent office fees. The large overhead would not be needed if there were no patents (Kinsella 2008). For a list of ridiculous patents see (Kinsella 2008) appendix. The defensive patent situation is very similar to the cold war where weapons were created for ―defensive‖ purposes, but never used. In other words defensive patents are a creation of the legislation (Boldrin and Levine 2008, p. 74). 8 encourage technology advances and new ideas (Peloso 2003, p. 35). The laws gives the inventor a monopoly on his invention for a limited period of time in the exchange for sharing the technology when the patent expires. One cannot get very far in the intellectual property literature without encountering Ayn Rand‘s advocacy for intellectual property rights. For Rand (1986, p. 141), The government does not grant a patent or copyright, in the sense of a gift, privilege, or favor; the government merely secures it that is the government certifies the origination of an idea and protects its owner‘s exclusive right of use and disposal. Exclusive right and disposal are very powerful terms if we are going to take Rand‘s conjecture to its logical extent. We will explore the ramifications of this type of proposition as we proceed with our discussion. However, we need to address where rights are derived from. Natural rights were pioneered by philosophers and political scientists13 and are argued to be universal and inalienable. These rights do not depend on any religious, ideological, cultural or traditional understanding. As a result these rights can be adopted by all people. The Stoics pioneered natural law, followed by the Catholic thinkers, the Reformers14, and most recently the Enlightenment. Most notably and widely recognized has been John Locke‘s additions to the historical dialogue on natural rights. Locke 13 John Locke, Thomas Hobbes, Thomas Jefferson, Thomas Paine, Samuel P. Huntington, G.E. Moore, Hugh Gibbons, Ayn Rand, Murray Rothbard, and Robert Nozick. 14 The reformer, Luther (1523), declared: Furthermore, every man is responsible for his own faith, and he must see it for himself that he believes rightly. As little as another can go to hell or heaven for me, so little can he believe or disbelieve for me; and as little as he can open or shut heaven or hell for me, so little can he drive me to faith or unbelief. Since, then, belief or unbelief is a matter of every one's conscience, and since this is no lessening of the secular power, the latter should be content and attend to its own affairs and permit men to believe one thing or another, as they are able and willing, and constrain no one by force. In other words, the state should coerce beliefs systems like religious faith. 9 claimed that natural rights were, ―life, liberty, and estate (property).‖ Lock believed that the right to life15 means that everyone is entitled to live once they are created. Liberty means that people are free to do what-so-ever they please, provided it does not conflict with the right to life, and the estate or property right means that people are entitled to own what they homestead or gain though exchange provided that it does not conflict with the right of life or liberty. We will later explore if Locke‘s claims line up with intellectual property rights. In the libertarian tradition the liberal tradition of natural rights has been continued by most recently by Rand16and Rothbard.17 and Natural rights proponents have claimed that man has ownership over this life and ergo his property because of the use of the individuals time, which is an extension of his life, that he has put into the property. 15 Rothbard (2001, p. 1311) Egalitarianism is, therefore, a literally senseless social philosophy. Its only meaningful formulation is the goal of ―equality of liberty‖—formulated by Herbert Spencer in his famous Law of Equal Freedom: ―Every man has freedom to do all he wills, provided he infringes not the equal freedom of any other man.‖ This goal does not attempt to make every individual‘s total condition equal— an absolutely impossible task; instead, it advocates liberty—a condition of absence of coercion over person and property for every man. This goal has sometimes been phrased as ―equality before the law,‖ or ―equality of rights.‖ Yet both formulations are ambiguous and misleading. The former could be taken to mean equality of slavery as well as liberty and has, in fact, been so narrowed down in recent years as to be Yet even this formulation of equality has many flaws and could profitably be discarded. In the first place, it opens the door for ambiguity and for egalitarianism. In the second place, the term ―equality‖ connotes measurable identity with a fixed, extensive unit. ―Equal length‖ means identity of measurement with an objectively determinable unit. In the study of human action, whether in praxeology or social philosophy, there is no such quantitative unit, and hence there can be no such ―equality.‖ Far better to say that ―each man should have X‖ than to say that ―all men should be equal in X.‖ If someone wants to urge every man to buy a car, he formulates his goal in that way—―Every man should buy a car‖—rather than in such terms as: ―All men should have equality in car buying.‖ The use of the term ―equality‖ is awkward as well as misleading. And finally, as Clara Dixon Davidson pointed out so cogently many years ago, Spencer‘s Law of Equal Freedom is redundant. For if every man has freedom to do all that he wills, it follows from this very premise that no man‘s freedom has been infringed or invaded. The whole second clause of the law after ―wills‖ is redundant and unnecessary. Since the formulation of Spencer‘s Law, opponents of Spencer have used the qualifying clause to drive holes into the libertarian philosophy. Yet all this time they were hitting at an encumbrance, not at the essence of the law. The concept of ―equality‖ has no rightful place in the ―Law of Equal Freedom,‖ being replaceable by the logical quantifier ―every.‖ The ―Law of Equal Freedom‖ could well be renamed ―The Law of Total Freedom.‖ 16 See http://aynrandlexicon.com/lexicon/individual_rights.html 17 See (Rothbard 1998)
Description: