Teleology, First Principles, and fi ’ Scienti c Method in Aristotle s Biology OXFORD ARISTOTLE STUDIES GeneralEditors JuliaAnnasandLindsayJudson PUBLISHEDINTHESERIES Teleology,FirstPrinciples,andScientific MethodinAristotle’sBiology AllanGotthelf PriorityinAristotle’sMetaphysics MichailPeramatzis DoingandBeing AnInterpretationofAristotle’sMetaphysicsTheta JonathanBeere Space,Time,Matter,andForm EssaysonAristotle’sPhysics DavidBostock AristotleonMeaningandEssence DavidCharles TimeforAristotle UrsulaCoope AristotleonTeleology MonteRansomeJohnson OnLocation Aristotle’sConceptsofPlace BenjaminMorison OrderinMultiplicity HomonymyinthePhilosophyofAristotle ChristopherShields Aristotle’sTheoryofSubstance TheCategoriesandMetaphysicsZeta MichaelV.Wedin Aristotle’sDeInterpretatione ContradictionandDialectic C.W.A.Whitaker Teleology, First Principles, and fi Scienti c Method ’ in Aristotle s Biology Allan Gotthelf 1 3 GreatClarendonStreet,OxfordOX26DP OxfordUniversityPressisadepartmentoftheUniversityofOxford. ItfurtherstheUniversity’sobjectiveofexcellenceinresearch,scholarship, andeducationbypublishingworldwidein Oxford NewYork Auckland CapeTown DaresSalaam HongKong Karachi KualaLumpur Madrid Melbourne MexicoCity Nairobi NewDelhi Shanghai Taipei Toronto Withofficesin Argentina Austria Brazil Chile CzechRepublic France Greece Guatemala Hungary Italy Japan Poland Portugal Singapore SouthKorea Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam OxfordisaregisteredtrademarkofOxfordUniversityPress intheUKandincertainothercountries PublishedintheUnitedStates byOxfordUniversityPressInc.,NewYork #inthisvolumeAllanGotthelf 2012 Themoralrightsoftheauthorhavebeenasserted DatabaserightOxfordUniversityPress(maker) Firstpublished2012 Allrightsreserved.Nopartofthispublicationmaybereproduced, storedinaretrievalsystem,ortransmitted,inanyformorbyanymeans, withoutthepriorpermissioninwritingofOxfordUniversityPress, orasexpresslypermittedbylaw,orundertermsagreedwiththeappropriate reprographicsrightsorganization.Enquiriesconcerningreproduction outsidethescopeoftheaboveshouldbesenttotheRightsDepartment, OxfordUniversityPress,attheaddressabove Youmustnotcirculatethisbookinanyotherbindingorcover andyoumustimposethissameconditiononanyacquirer BritishLibraryCataloguinginPublicationData Dataavailable LibraryofCongressCataloginginPublicationData Dataavailable TypesetbySPIPublisherServices,Pondichery,India PrintedinGreatBritain onacid-freepaperby MPGBooksGroup,BodminandKing’sLynn ISBN978–0–19–928795–6 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 To the memory of Ayn Rand and David Balme For Aristotle, life is not an inexplicable, supernatural mystery, but a fact of nature.Andconsciousnessisanaturalattributeofcertainlivingentities,their naturalpower,theirspecificmodeofaction—notanunaccountableelementin amechanisticuniverse,tobeexplainedawaysomehowintermsofinanimate matter,noramysticmiracleincompatiblewithphysicalreality,tobeattributed tosomeoccultsourceinanotherdimension.ForAristotle,‘living’and‘know- ing’arefactsofreality;man’smindisneitherunnaturalnorsupernatural,but natural—and this is the root of Aristotle’s greatness, of the immeasurable distancethatseparateshimfromotherthinkers. Life—anditshighestform,man’slife—isthecentralfactinAristotle’sview of reality. The best way to describe it is to say that Aristotle’s philosophy is ‘biocentric’. This is the source of Aristotle’s intense concern with the study of living entities, the source of the enormously ‘pro-life’ attitude that dominates his thinking. AynRand,‘ReviewofRandall’sAristotle’(1963) Butteleologyneverthelessistheprimarysubjectof[thePartsofAnimals],and the other [biological] treatises likewise have primarily theoretical purposes. Theyarenotjustempiricalstudiesinwhichsomephilosophicalconceptsare puttouse.Wegolessfarwrongifweregardthemasstudiesoftheseconcepts madethroughempiricaldata. Thissuggeststhepossibilitythatwemightgainlightupontheseconcepts— suchassubstance,form,species,essence,logos—byexaminingtheirreference inbiology,togetherwiththeargumentsaroundthem. D.M.Balme,‘ThePlaceofBiologyinAristotle’sPhilosophy’(1987a) Preface In 1961, midway through my undergraduate studies, I read Ayn Rand’s Atlas Shrugged.Ilovedthenovel.Itglowedwithrespectforthemind,andformuchelse that I valued or came to value. Rand loved Aristotle, and that love permeated especiallyherlaterwritings,fromAtlasShruggedon.Shecreditedhimwithdefining ‘thebasicprinciplesofarationalviewofexistenceandofman’sconsciousness’,with rejecting Plato’s otherworldly metaphysics, and with showing (in outline at least) how reason can come to understand this world based on sense-perception. Rand thus saw Aristotle as the father of science, and attributed the Renaissance and Enlightenment(andalloftheirproducts)tohisinfluence: If we consider the fact that to this day everything that makes us civilized beings, every rationalvaluethatwepossess—includingthebirthofscience,theindustrialrevolution,the creationoftheUnitedStates,eventhestructureofourlanguage—istheresultofAristotle’s influence,ofthedegreetowhich,explicitlyorimplicitly,menacceptedhisepistemological principles,wewouldhavetosay:neverhavesomanyowedsomuchtooneman.1 IstartedreadingAristotlemyselfandfoundmuchofprofoundvaluephilosoph- ically,certainlymorethanIhadfoundinthecontemporaryphilosophymaterialsI studied for my regular courses. I had been fortunate to meet and get to know Rand, and I talked with her about Aristotle (and much else) on and off over the nextfifteenorsoyears.TwoideasIwouldliketohighlightherethatattractedme to Aristotle from the beginning (in the first case, with the help of Rand’s own discussionof the issues) were: (i) an understanding of causality and explanation in termsnotofeventsandlawsbutofthingswithnaturesandpotentials;and(ii)theidea that developed human knowledge takes the form of axiomatically structured bodiesofunderstanding,whichreflectagraspoftheessentialnaturesandpotentials oftherelevantthings(includingtheirattributes),agraspacquiredthroughsystem- aticsensoryobservationandabroadlyinductivemethodology. Andsobegananadventure,whichhasnotabatedtothisdayandisreflectedin the chapters of the volume before you. I set out to master what I could of Aristotle’s philosophic and scientific thinking, of his understanding of human nature and psychology, and of his view of the life and actions proper to human beingsasrationalanimals.IchoseColumbiaastheplacetodomygraduatework, inpartsoIcouldbeinNewYorkandstudywithRand,andinpartbecauseJohn HermanRandall,Jr.wasatColumbia;Iknewthatwhateverthelimitationsofhis Aristotle(1960),thebookandthemanhadmuchtoteachme. 1 Rand1961,20(2005,17-18). viii PREFACE InmyearlyworkonAristotleduringthatfirstyearatColumbia,1964-65,Iwas caughtupinAristotle’sinsistencethatlivingorganismscometobe,arestructured, and function for the sake of something. Acorns and embryos are goal-directed in their development, as are mature organisms even in their vegetative functioning, even thoughthereisnoconsciousnesswithintodirectthatdevelopmentandfunction- ing.Howisthisthesistobeunderstood? Istruggledwiththatissueforsomeyearsandeventuallydecidedtomakeitmy dissertationtopic.WhatItookfromRand,andwhatIthinkintheendmadeallthe difference to my ‘irreducible potential for form’ interpretation, was the insistence thatweposetheproblemintermsofnaturesandpotentials.ReadersofPartIofthis volume—thechapterson‘Teleology,Irreducibility,andtheGenerationofAnimals (GA)’—will find this insistence a pervasive theme, on which I draw in many differentcontexts.(See,firstofall,chapter1,sec.IV.) Although I had worked out the heart of my interpretation of the teleology before I came across David Balme’s work, reading his 1972 Clarendon Aristotle volume—Aristotle’s De Partibus Animalium I and De Generatione Animalium I (with excerpts from II.1-3)—was a revelation. Randall had introduced me to Aris- totle’s biological treatises and their underlying naturalism, but Balme taught me howtostudythem;andespeciallyasIreadon inhiswritings, hetaughtmetheir value—thevalueofthewholeofthebiologicalcorpus—foradeeperunderstanding of Aristotle’s philosophy. I met Balme in 1973 and we stayed in close touch as colleaguesandthenasfriendsuntilhisdeathinearly1989;Iwasproudtoedithis Festschriftin1985.Itellsomethingsaboutthemanandhisworkinmyintroduc- tiontothatvolume(Gotthelf1985a),anddiscusshisworkinsomedetailinsome ofthechaptersbelow. ThankstoRandall’sinfluence,asI’vementioned,Ihadstartedreadinginthelate 1960sthemainexplanatorytreatisesinthebiologicalcorpus:GenerationofAnimals, fortheteleology,andPartsofAnimals,inpartfortheteleology,butinparttoseeto what extent my earlier-mentioned suspicion that Aristotelian explanatory science has a demonstrative structure was sound. In that first substantial read of PA, I thought I could detect glimmers: Aristotle seemed at times to move in his explanations from features which he clearly took to be more fundamental or essential to the animals in question to features of those animals that were less fundamental or essential. But in the limited time I had for that issue, I couldn’t graspthewholeofAristotle’sprojectinPA.Itwasn’tuntil1985thatItookonthe problemdirectly,inapaperIdevelopedforaconferenceG.E.R.LloydandIhad organizedatCambridge.Chapter7ofthepresentvolume,whichgrewoutofthat conferencepaper,remainsmystatementofmyviewonthistopic(especiallywhen readinlightoftheelaborationsprovidedinthechapterthatfollowsit). Although I am perhaps best known for my work on Aristotle’s biology and naturalphilosophy,IhavehadstrongintereststhroughoutmycareerinAristotle’s PREFACE ix metaphysics and ethics. The two chapters constituting Part III of this volume addressmetaphysicalthemesonwhichthebiologyshedslightandtouchonaspects of my interpretation of the theory of substance in the central books of the Metaphysics,onwhichIhopetowritemorefullysomeday. Personally, I view my interpretation of Aristotle’s natural teleology, and my account of the broadly axiomatic structure of biological explanation, as my most important work. Third on that list are the various ways in which my work on particularphilosophicaltopicsmayhave contributedtotheopeningup,forother admirers of Aristotle, of the three main biological treatises for subsequent study. ThisincludesespeciallytheworkIhavedone—muchofitjointlywithmylong- timefriendandcolleagueinsomanyAristotelianendeavors,JimLennox—tohelp make the History of Animals, the largest and still least studied treatise in the Aristotelian corpus, more accessible to scholars. That work is presented in the three chapters of Part IV, ‘Starting a Science: Theoretical Aims of the History of Animals(HA)’. Part V, ‘Aristotle as Theoretical Biologist’, contains two chapters that are personalfavoritesofmine.‘DarwinonAristotle’wasmotivatedbyastrongstreak of hero-worship: I love the famous 1882 letter praising Aristotle that Charles Darwinwroteduringthecourseofhis first readingof Aristotle’s biologicalwork, andIwasirritatedbeyondbeliefbyanessayIreadintheearly1980sthattriedto debunk the letter. ‘Debunk the debunker’ was my motto, and I am confident I succeeded. I also had great fun doing some straight historical detective work, on detailssuchaswhen,exactly,so-and-sodied(see,forinstance,chapter15,n.4). Thelastchapter ofPartV, whichIconsider alsoa ‘coda’totheentirevolume, for its synoptic character, is a lecture that I have delivered many times to general audiences. I was prompted to write it by an experience I had during my annual visitstoClareHall,Cambridgeinthe1980s,whenIwoulddescribemyinterestin Aristotle’s scientific work to the other (often natural-science-oriented) visiting fellows. ‘Oh, but he’s not a real scientist’, they would say, or ‘Oh, but his work heldbackthecourseofsciencefor2,000years’.Myresponse,whichIdeliveredfor thefirsttimeatClareHallin1987,is‘AristotleasScientist:AProperVerdict(with emphasisonhisbiologicalworks)’. I have added to each chapter an opening unnumbered footnote in which I indicate the chapter’s origin and/or its role in my thinking about Aristotle. With theseintroductoryfootnotes,withthegroupingofthechaptersintoParts,andwith the extensive cross-references among chapters, I have not thought it necessary to addsubstantiveintroductionseithertothefivePartsortothevolumeasawhole. IhavementionedmyinterestinintroducingscholarsandstudentsofAristotleto the main biological treatises, not just as sources of philosophical insight, but as whole works in their own right. As indication that I think the chapters in this volumecandothat,especiallyinPartsI,II,andIV,Ihaveincludedinthetitlesof
Description: