ebook img

Symbol and Interpretation PDF

106 Pages·1975·2.399 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Symbol and Interpretation

SYMBOL AND INTERPRETATION SYMBOL AND INTERPRETATION by DAVID M. RASMUSSEN m ~ MAR TINUS NIJHOFF / THE HAGUE / 1974 © 1974 by Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, Netherlands All rights reserved, including the right to translate or to reproduce this book or parts thereof in any form lSBN-13: 978-90-247-1579-4 e-1SBN-13: 978-94-010-1594-3 DOT: 10.1007/978-94-010-1594-3 TABLE OF CONTENTS Introduction 1 Chapter I: SYMBOL AND LANGUAGE 7 Introduction 7 On Multiple Realities 7 Potentiality, Givenness, Heritage, Memory 7 Actualization and Meaning 10 Multiple Realities 12 Language and the Symbol 17 Language and Consciousness 17 Language as Isomorphic to Consciousness 19 Conclusion 24 Chapter II: MIRCEA ELIADE: STRUCTURAL HERMENEUTICS AND PHILOSOPHY 25 Introduction 25 The Symbol as a Dimension of Consciousness 25 The Method for Establishing the Symbol as a Valid Form 33 Conclusion 37 Chapter III: PAUL RICOEUR: THE ANTHROPOLOGICAL NECESSITY OF A SPECIAL LANGUAGE 38 Introduction 38 The Question 38 Philosophy of the will 39 Freedom and Nature 41 Fallible Man 42 The Symbolism of Evil 45 An Answer 47 Conclusion 50 Chapter IV: MYTH, STRUCTURE AND INTERPRETATION 52 Introduction 52 VI TABLE OF CONTENTS From Evolution to Structure 52 Structural Hermeneutics 55 Archaic Ontology 64 Conclusion 68 Chapter V: TOWARD A THEORETICAL FOUNDATION FOR A CORRELATION BETWEEN LITERARY AND RELIGIOUS DISCOURSE 70 Introduction 70 Background 70 Theory of Language: The Possibility of a Phenomenological Model 71 Hermeneutics: the Interpretation of Special Languages 76 Conclusion 79 Chapter VI: SOCIQ-POLITICAL SYMBOLISM AND THE TRANSFORMATION OF CONSCIOUSNESS 80 Introduction 80 The Conflict of Rationality: Operational and Dialectical 81 Utopian Symbolism 85 Symbol, Seriality, and the Group Resolve 89 Symbol, Structure and Philosophical Anthropology 92 Conclusion .96 Index 99 INTRODUCTION For the past four or five years much of my thinking has centered up on the relationship of symbolic forms to philosophic imagination and interpretation. As one whose own philosophic speculations began at. the end of a cultural epoch under methodologies dominated either by neo-Kantianism or schools of logical empiricism the symbol as a prod uct of a cultural imagination has been diminished; it has been neces sary for those who wanted to preserve the symbol to find appropriate philosophical methodologies to do so. In the following chapters we shall attempt to show, through a consideration of a series of recent interpretations of the symbol, as well as through constructive argu ment, that the symbol ought to be considered as a linguistic form in the sense that it constitutes a special language with its own rubrics and properties. There are two special considerations to be taken ac count of in this argument; first, the definition of the symbol, and sec ond, the interpretation of the symbol. Although we shall refrain from defining the symbol explicitly at this point let it suffice to state that our definition of the symbol is more aesthetic than logical (in the technical sense of formal logic ), more cultural than individual, more imaginative than scientific. The symbol in our view is somewhere at the center of culture, the well-spring which testifies to the human imagination in its poetic, psychic, religious, social and political forms. Yet we shall attempt to avoid the tendency of the early phenomenol ogists and neo-Kantians to see the symbol as constituted by an act of consciousness. Rather our tendency is to conceive the symbol as a given, something to be interpreted. To be sure, the symbol is a rather curious phenomenon. It literally abolishes clarity and it confounds one's common sense understanding of self and world. Neither the positive nor the negative meaning of a flag can be contained in the material that allows for us to have a visu- 2 INTRODUCTION al perception of it, nor can the meaning of a cross be explicated in terms of the pieces of wood that make it up. The symbols that are visualized in a dream are never clear, for the price for the disclosure of the story they tell is in one sense the understanding of the mean ing of one's life. Equally, the poet transforms the ordinary words of our common sense world into a symbolic haven which is both opaque and rich, beyond the ordinary sense of clarity. The symbol is indeed a curious phenomenon and that is why it continues to baffle its interpreters. In one sense we may say that the most obvious error associated with the interpretation of the symbol has been the identification of it with the ordinary linguistic sign. Our common sense world is a world of assumptions which although they are inherited and perhaps unproven, we take to be true and real. Hence the words we have for the objects we perceive are taken to designate precisely those objects. Trees are trees, tables are tables, lamps are lamps, automobiles are automobiles and a street light on red desig nates literally that the pedestrian should stop. We may say that in our ordinary common sense world of meaning the sign signifies but it signifies literally. Strangely, the tendency of some modern inter pretation of the symbol has been to take the common sense view of the world as primary with the consequence that the symbol is taken to be false. The argument may be stated like this: those who have used symbols, pre-modern peoples for example, really didn't understand the world they sought to communicate with so they resorted to a se ries of symbolic transformations which, although false, gave a func tional interpretation of the world. Hence, myths and symbols, to fol low the argument, were created by those peoples primarily for pur poses of social organization, or for purposes of primitive scientific in vestigation and analysis. On the same basis it is possible to argue for the falsity of the poetic symbol on the ground that it communicates only emotively and not cognitively. In such cases of interpretation the symbol is taken, as the ordinary sign, to signify literally. The sym bol may make exorbitant claims about the sky, about vegetation, about the self, etc., but if we are to understand it, so the argument goes, then it is necessary to translate symbols back into signs in order to get at their common sense meaning, or at a minimum, that which the interpreter may think the meaning is. We wish to point out simply that interpretation has become a prob lem in a twofold sense. On the one hand it is impossible to divorce oneself from the common sense world of ordinary meaning. Strange- INTRODUCTION 3 ly, there is no uninterpreted point from which interpretation may begin. In most cases interpretation involves typing or categorizing in the sense that that which is perceived is thematized in terms of types which are familiar to us. The world which is meaningful to us is a world which we can re-cognize in terms of a certain stock of knowl edge which is the content of our experience. That which is unfamiliar to us we tend either to dismiss or to thematize in terms of the stock of knowledge we already possess. Hence, when one turns to the inter pretation of symbols whose temporal (historical) location is prior to our own, our tendency is to typify in terms of our own experience. The case is the same when one interprets data from a culture other than one's own. Sadly, one lives in a world of probabilities and it is always possible that the dual hiatus created by history and culture is sufficient to create a chasm in interpretation which allows for the possibility that the interpreter has missed the point. This is particu larly true when we allow that finite world of meaning which we call our common-sense world to dictate our definition of meaning, or if we allow for ordinary usages of language to predominate over symbol ic usages. The second problem which interpretation points to is that of veri fication. How does one determine whether or not one's interpretation of the symbol is valid? In the natural sciences modes of verification are, in general, standardized. One constructs an hypothesis, conducts experiments on the basis of the hypothesis, and verifies the hypothe sis on the basis of the successful or unsuccessful completion of the experiments. But in the human sciences, the sciences which rely on the interpretation of human activity and the products of that activity, the problems presented by verification are quite different and in some ways more difficult primarily because one is forced to deal with what can be called the anthropological factor. Although a symbol is sim ply a given for interpretation, in order to account for its presence it is necessary to account for the peculiar set of meanings and inten tions which went into its production. The process would be greatly simplified if it was possible to interrogate the producers of the sym bol. For several reasons this is almost universally impossible. First, symbols are generally the products of cultures and only indirectly can they be said to be products of individual minds existing within cultures. There are ways of interrogating individual minds within a culture but it is almost impossible to question the culture as a whole. Second, in the case of archaic symbolism, the cultures which pro- 4 INTRODUCTION duced the symbols have disintegrated to such an extent that one is left with a few scraps of information which, when put together, do little to give one evidence of the culture that once existed. Even so phisticated techniques of historiography are of little avail in those situations. Third, the possibilities for interrogation of the producers of symbols is severely limited, even discounting the other factors, by their availability. Since most authors refrain from interpreting their works, and because in many cases the producers and users of symbols are dead, the ideal of interrogation is impossible. Inasmuch as, in the case of the interpretation of the symbol, direct methods of empirical investigation are excluded, it will be necessary, if interpretation is to be exercised at all, to develop a theoretical foun dation sufficient to account for not only the definition of the sym bol and its interpretation, but for ways of establishing its validity. Instead of empirical verification the requirement of the symbol is for an anthropological verification. In other words human intentionali ties must be correlated with symbolic forms. The construction of philosophical foundations for interpretation becomes critical at this juncture initially because the theoretical foundations for interpreta tion will influence the manner in which interpretation occurs. One can find no better negative example of this than the late nineteenth and early twentieth century interpretations of the symbol which ten ded to eliminate the symbol on the basis of a philosophical commit ment to an evolutionary scheme. Such interpreters directly or indi rectly were influenced by the overwhelming success of the natural sciences in the modern world,and they were willing to apply to the data of the human sciences conclusions that had been successfully applied in the natural sciences. They were also committed to a view of man which envisioned the emergence of a total scientific rational ity which would no longer require non-scientific expressions. Our own commitments are somewhat different. We wish to con struct a philosophical foundation which will grant authenticity to the symbol conceiving of it as a legitimate and necessary expression of human consciousness. Indeed, our initial judgment is somewhat dif ferent than that cited above. We wish to work out a philosophical framework which will capture the intentionality of the symbol at its own level. In order to do this, to refer to comments made a moment ~go, it is necessary to consider the symbol as a linguistic form. There are those who would object to this position. First, there is the argu ment that the symbolic form is something other than a linguistic mo-

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.