ebook img

Space, Time and Causality: Royal Institute of Philosophy Conferences Volume 1981 PDF

212 Pages·1983·10.182 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Space, Time and Causality: Royal Institute of Philosophy Conferences Volume 1981

SPACE, TIME AND CAUSALITY SYNTHESE LIBRARY STUDIES IN EPISTEMOLOGY, LOGIC, METHODOLOGY, AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Managing Editor: JAAKKO HINTlKKA, Florida State University Editors: DON ALD DAVIDSON, University of Chicago GABRIEL NUCHELMANS, University of Leyden WESLEY C. SALMON, University ofP ittsburgh VOLUME 157 ROYAL INSTITUTE OF PHILOSOPHY CONFERENCES VOLUME 1981 SPACE, TIME AND CAUSALITY Edited by RICHARD SWINBURNE Department of Philosophy, University of Keele, Keele, Staffordshire D. REIDEL PUBLISHING COMPANY DORDRECHT : HOLLAND / BOSTON: U.S.A. LONDON: ENGLAND library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Main entry under title: Space, time, and causality. (Synthese library; v. 157) 'The papers in this volume are revised versions of papers read to a conference at the University of Keele in September 1981, sponsored by the Royal Institute of Philosophy'-Pref. Bibliography: p. Includes index. 1. Space and time-Congresses. 2. Causation-Congresses. I. Swinburne, Richard. II. Royal Institute of Philosophy. BD632.S63 1982 110 82-18123 ISBN-13: 978-94-009-6968-1 e-ISBN-13: 978-94-009-6966-7 DO I: 10.1007/978-94-009-6966-7 Published by D. Reidel Publishing Company, P.O. Box 17, 3300 AA Dordrecht, Holland. Sold and distributed in the U.S.A. and Canada by Kluwer Boston Inc., 190 Old Derby Street, Hingham, MA 02043, U.S.A. In all other countries, sold and distributed by Kluwer Academic Publishers Group, P.O. Box 322, 3300 AH Dordrecht, Holland. D. Reidel Publishing Company is a member of the Kluwer Group. All Rights Reserved Copyright © 1983 by D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland Softcover reprint of the hardcover 15t edition 1983 No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording or by any infonnational storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner TABLE OF CONTENTS FOREWORD vii PREFACE ix INTRODUCTION xi ABSOLUTE VERSUS RELATIVE SPACE AND TIME J. L. MACKIE I Three Steps Towards Absolutism 3 JON DORLING I Reply to Mackie 23 ELiE ZAHAR I Absoluteness and Conspiracy 37 TIME AND CAUSAL CONNECTIBILITY LA WRENCE SKLAR I Prospects for a Causal Theory of Space-Time 45 RICHARD SWINBURNE I Verificationism and Theories of Space-Time 63 TEMPORAL AND CAUSAL ASYMMETRY RICHARD A. HEALEY I Temporal and Causal Asymmetry 79 W. H. NEWTON-SMITH I Temporal and Causal Asymmetry 105 CAUSALITY AND QUANTUM MECHANICS NANCY CARTWRIGHT I How the Measurement Problem Is an Arti- fact of the Mathematics 125 JEREMY BUTTERFIELD I Measurement, Unitarity, and Laws 135 vi TABLE OF CONTENTS CAUSALITY, RELATIVITY, AND THE EINSTEIN-PODOLSKY-ROSEN PARADOX MICHAEL REDHEAD I Nonlocality and Peaceful Coexistence 151 PETER GIBBINS I Quantum Logic and Ensembles 191 NOTES ON CONTRIBUTORS 207 INDEX OF NAMES 209 FOREWORD The Royal Institute of Philosophy has been sponsoring conferences in alter nate years since 1969. These have from the start been intended to be of interest to persons who are not philosophers by profession. They have mainly focused on interdisciplinary areas such as the philosophies of psychology, education and the social sciences. The volumes arising from these conferences have included discussions between philosophers and distinguished practitioners of other disciplines relevant to the chosen topic. Beginning with the 1979 conference on 'Law, Morality and Rights' and the 1981 conference on 'Space, Time and Causality' these volumes are now constituted as a series. It is hoped that this series will contribute to advancing philosophical understanding at the frontiers of philosophy and areas of interest to non-philosophers. It is hoped that it will do so by writing which reduces technicalities as much as the subject-matter permits. In this way the series is intended to demonstrate that philosophy can be clear and worthwhile in itself and at the same time relevant to the interests of lay people. STUART BROWN Honorary Assistant Director Royal Institute ofP hilosophy vii PREFACE The papers in this volume are revised versions of papers read 'to a conference at the University of Keele in September 1981, sponsored by the Royal Institute of Philosophy. The general theme ofthe conference was the implica tions for our understanding of space, time and causation of the developments of modern physics, and especially of those two great theories of modern physics - Relativity Theory and Quantum Theory. It is very sad to have to record that after participating in the conference with his usual vigour, but before he could complete the final revisions to his paper, J. L. Mackie died on December 12th 1981. I should like to dedicate this volume to his memory. John Mackie believed that philosophical argu ment, applied to knowledge provided by other disciplines and above all by science, could lead to a clear and unified world-view. He has contributed in a major way to debates about most areas of philosophy. His enthusiasm for the subject showed in his readiness to argue about it with almost any opponent, however humble or awkward. He always did so with great courtesy; as one who argued with him about many philosophical matters from a dia metrically opposed position over many years can certainly testify. Oddly enough, the issue discussed in our two contributions to the present volume was one of very few about which we had a small measure of agreement. January 1982 RICHARD SWINBURNE INTRODUCTION A major role of the philosopher of science is to put major scientific theories under the philosophical microscope. Once the scientist has constructed his theory, given it precise mathematical form, used it to make predictions, and found that these confirm the theory, the philosopher comes and examines the theory. He asks first what does the theory mean, what is it telling us about the world. Some philosophers and scientists (variously called instru mentalists, operationalists, or anti-realists) have held that the whole meaning of the theory is contained in its predictions about what can be observed - e.g. that the atomic theory of chemistry, as put forward in the nineteenth century, was simply a shorthand summary of observable data, of which chemical substances combine with other chemical substances in what pro portions by mass and volume to form other substances; of the viscosity, boiling points and melting points of substances. But most philosophers and scientists these days are realists. They think of scientific theories not just as predicting devices, but as devices which tell us about the unobservable entities and properties which lie behind and cause the phenomena which we observe. They understand talk about 'molecules', 'atoms', 'protons', 'photons', 'electrons' and 'neutrinos' as talk about very small things which possess properties such as mass and charge, not just as terms in a scientific theory which is a successful predicting device. Yet even if you adopt this realist attitude to science, it is not always clear just what the scientific theory is claiming - are electrons supposed to be small round material objects, like billiard balls but very much smaller; or are they supposed to be rather dif ferent from anything observable on the large scale? If the world about which the scientist tries to tell us is very different from the world which we can observe with the naked eye, he will have a problem in describing it - for our ordinary language is designed for talk about the observable world. The scientist will therefore need to use words in slightly different senses from their normal senses. The role of the philosopher is to show when and how this is happening, and so to make clear just what the scientific theory is claiming. The physicist may tell us that electrons may be regarded either as waves or as particles. But if he is claiming that they are both waves and particles, the philosopher needs to clarify this claim. For superficially it is hard to make xi xii INTRODUCTION sense of this - how can something be both the propagation of a disturbance in a medium (which is what a wave is) and a material object? A second task for the philosopher when he has spelled out what the theory means is to show why the scientist's evidence is in fact evidence for that interpretation of the theory. The theory tells us about things unobservable. Why should we take particular observations as evidence in favour of the existence of just those things? Relativity Theory and Quantum Theory present abundant scope for philosophical investigation. They are both theories of great mathematical sophistication which have proved very successful predictors of observations. But the descriptions in words which physicists give of the meaning of these theories are highly paradoxical. Ordinarily we suppose that an event occurs at a defmite time and place - i.e. at a defmite interval after some other specified event and at a definite distance from it. But the Special and General Theories of Relativity, at any rate as they are normally expounded, challenge this understanding. We are told that the distance in space and the interval in time between events depends on the frame of reference in which rulers and clocks used for measurement are situated - the Earth, say, or a spaceship moving across the Earth's surface. There is no true distance in space or interval in time between events; there is just 'distance in F', and 'distance in F", 'temporal interval in F', and 'temporal interval in F' '. Again, we ordinarily wish to distinguish between real motion (e.g. the motion of a train across the countryside) and apparent motion (e.g. the motion of the countryside as seen from the train). But relativity theory seems to tell us that in reality there is no such thing as absolute motion. Indeed it seems to go even further and say that space and time are not separate things in which there are separate intervals. The real entity is space-time, intervals in which really exist - any division of these intervals into spatial and temporal components is an arbitrary one. We need to elucidate and make sense of these claims, if we can; and clarify precisely whether the evidence of observation supports these claims. Similar problems arise with Quantum Theory. Ordinarily we suppose that physical objects are at defmite places at definite times moving with definite velocities and momenta. Yet Quantum Theory, at any rate on some inter pretations, seem to suggest not merely that we cannot know the exact position and momentum of a particle, such as an electron or photon, but that it does not have these. It only has the probability of being in a certain place and having a certain momentum - until it is 'observed' (i.e. interacts with some measuring apparatus which gives a reading which we can observe). Then if its position is measured, this acquires a definite value, while its momentum

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.