ebook img

Socially Enforced Nepotism: How Norms and Reputation Can Amplify Kin Altruism PDF

13 Pages·2016·1.83 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Socially Enforced Nepotism: How Norms and Reputation Can Amplify Kin Altruism

RESEARCHARTICLE Socially Enforced Nepotism: How Norms and Reputation Can Amplify Kin Altruism DougJones* DepartmentofAnthropology,UniversityofUtah,SaltLakeCity,Utah,UnitedStatesofAmerica *[email protected] Abstract Kinselection,whichcanleadorganismstobehavealtruisticallytotheirgeneticrelatives, worksdifferentlywhen—asisoftenthecaseinhumansocieties—altruismcanbeboosted bysocialpressure.HereIpresentamodelofsocialnormsenforcedbyindirectreciprocity. a11111 Inthemodeltherearemanyalternativestableallocationsofrewards(“distributional norms”);astablenormisstableinthesensethateachplayerisbestofffollowingthenormif otherplayersdothesame.Stablenormsvarywidelyinhowequallytheyrewardplayers withunequalabilities.Inapopulationofmixedgroups(somegroupmembersfollowone norm,somefollowanother,andsomecompromise)withmodestwithin-groupcoefficientsof relatedness,selectionwithingroupsfavorsthosewhocompromise,andselectionbetween OPENACCESS groupsfavorsgenerousgeneralizedreciprocityratherthanbalancedreciprocity.Thus Citation:JonesD(2016)SociallyEnforced evolvedsocialnormscanamplifykinaltruism,givingrisetoauniquelyhumanmodeofkin- Nepotism:HowNormsandReputationCanAmplify basedsocialitydistinctfromspontaneousaltruismamongclosekin,orcooperationamong KinAltruism.PLoSONE11(6):e0155596. non-kin. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0155596 Editor:Cheng-YiXia,TianjinUniversityof Technology,CHINA Received:November10,2015 Introduction:BeatingHamilton’sRule Accepted:May2,2016 Thisarticlepresentsasouped-upversionofthetheoryofkinselection.Inthestandardversion, Published:June15,2016 anorganismhasachancetoprovidebenefitbtooneofherkinatcostctoherself.Natural Copyright:©2016DougJones.Thisisanopen selectionfavorsthisaltruisticactaslongasHamilton’sRuleissatisfied,r(cid:1)b>c,whereristhe accessarticledistributedunderthetermsofthe coefficientofrelatednessofrecipienttodonor[1].Butinthetheorypresentedhere,altruism CreativeCommonsAttributionLicense,whichpermits towardkinisinfluencedbyawidersocialcontext,asmembersofagroupplayagameinwhich unrestricteduse,distribution,andreproductioninany medium,providedtheoriginalauthorandsourceare eachplayercanrewardothersforbehavinggenerouslytowardtheirmutualkin.Ishowthat credited. thiscanfavortheevolutionofhighlevelsofaltruism,intheformofunbalancedgeneralized reciprocityamongkin,evenwhenrissmall. DataAvailabilityStatement:Code(Mathematica)is availableattheOpenScienceFramework(osf.io) Thetheoryofsociallyenforcednepotismshouldbeofinteresttoscholarsinseveraldisci- repositorywithidentifiersDOI10.17605/OSF.IO/ plines[2,3].Itbearsonargumentsamongevolutionarytheoristsabouthowusefulinclusivefit- MXZ8H/ARKc7605/osf.io/mxz8h. nesstheoryisinaccountingforsocialbehavior,amongsocialscientistsabouttherelationship Funding:Theauthorhasnosupportorfundingto betweenrationalchoiceandsocialnorms,andamongculturalanthropologistsabouthowfar report. theirtheoriesofkinshipcanbereconciledwithevolutionarytheories. Intherestofthisintroduction,Isummarizetheoreticalandempiricalreasonsforwanting CompetingInterests:Theauthorhasdeclaredthat nocompetinginterestsexist. toaddamodelofsocialnormsandtheirenforcementtothetheoryofkinselection.Onthe PLOSONE|DOI:10.1371/journal.pone.0155596 June15,2016 1/13 SociallyEnforcedNepotism theoreticalside:Kinselectiontheoryissometimesequatedwiththepropositionthatorganisms areshapedbynaturalselectiontomaximizetheirinclusivefitness.Butthisresultrestsonthe assumptionthatforeachactorinagroup,wecanseparateoutanindependentcontribution thatshemakestothewell-beingofherkin[4].Thisamountstotreatingkinselectionasacol- lectionofone-persongames. Howeverkinselectiongetsmorecomplicatedwhenthereismoreinthewayofstrategic interactionamongactors.Considerasimplemodelwhichcombinesgametheoryandpopula- tiongenetics,theBrothersKaramazovGame[5].Thegameisplayedamongthreebrothers, withacoefficientofrelatednessr=1/2foreachpair.Onebrotherisapotentialrecipientof altruism,andtheothertwoarepotentialdonors,sowearelookingatatwo-persongame betweenthetwodonorsregardinghowtheytreatthethird.Toestablishabenchmarkfor comparison,webeginwitheachofthetwopotentialhelpersdecidingindependentlyofthe otheronewhethertohelptheirneedysibling.Inthiscase,theevolutionofaltruismisgov- ernedbyHamilton’sRule.Eachbrothershouldhelpaslongashiscostcandtheneedybroth- er’sbenefitbsatisfy1/2(cid:1)b>c.Butnowconsiderthecasewherethetwopotentialhelpers adoptastrategyofconditionalnepotism:eachwillprovideextrahelpaslongastheotherdoes thesame.Itistemptingtoanalyzethispackagedealusinginclusivefitnesstheory,withcosts andbenefitstoone’ssiblingscountingforhalfasmuchascoststooneself.Bythisaccounting, withtwobrotherstakingturns,eachonhisturnpayingcostcandprovidingbenefitbtothe third,theruleforaltruismis2/3(cid:1)b>c.Butamorecarefulanalysisusinggeneandgenotype frequenciesgivesadifferentanswer:theconditionfortheevolutionofaltruismisrC(cid:1)b>c, whererC=(1+6p)/(2+8p),withpbeingthefrequencyofthealleleforconditionalaltruism. TheconditionalcoefficientofrelatednessrCincreasesfrom1/2to7/10aspincreasesfrom0 to1.Aconditionalnepotismgenecannotinvadeapopulationwhenveryrare,butcanspread onceitgainsafoothold. TheBrothersKaramazovGamedemonstratesseveralthings.First,itshowsthelimitations ofinclusivefitnessaccounting.Thecalculationbasedonthegenealogicalcoefficientofrelated- nessof1/2betweensiblingsdoesn’twork,becausetheprobabilitythatthetwohelpersareiden- tical-by-descentfortheconditionalnepotismalleleisrelatedinacomplicatedwaytothe strategieseachchooses.Whileinclusivefitnesstheorycanofferqualitativeinsights,ittakesan explicitpopulationgeneticcalculationtogetthecorrectanswer.Second,themodelprovidesa proof-of-conceptthatasociallyenforcedrulecanamplifykinaltruism.Theconditionalstrat- egycanleadeachdonorbrothertobehaveasifhewerecloserkinthanabrother.Onewayto understandthisistonotethataltruismtowardkinisapublicgood.Whenonebrotherprovides help,heisalsogivingafreeboosttotheinclusivefitnessoftheotherpotentialhelper,andvice versa.Aswithotherpublicgoods,moreisprovidedwhenplayersreducefree-ridingbyenforc- ingagreed-uponrules.Inthiscase,ifwegaugekinaltruismbyc/b,thenconditionalnepotism beatsindividualnepotismfollowingHamilton’sRulebyupto40percent. TheBrothersKaramazovGameisperhapsthesimplestpossiblemodelofsociallyenforced nepotism.Thebulkofthisarticleexploresamoregeneralmodelofann-persongamethat differsfromtheBrothersKaramazovGameinseveralrespects.First,themodelhereisnot builtaroundasimpletwo-folddivisionofplayersintothosewhohelpandthosewhoare helped.Insteaditincludesplayerswitharangeofhelpingabilities.Second,playersinthe modeldonotrelyonasimpleconditionalstrategytoboostaltruismtokin.Suchastrategy (“I’llhelpifyoudotoo”)worksfortwohelpers.Butthen-personconditionalstrategy(“I’ll helpifeveryoneelsedoestoo”)breaksdownfornmuchgreaterthantwo,becauseitimposes animpossiblystringentunanimityrequirement[6].Instead,playersrelyonindirectreciproc- ityandhonestadvertisingofabilitytoenforcenormsofsharing.Themodelletsusexplore thecontrast,andtheevolutionarycontest,betweennormsofbalancedreciprocity(where PLOSONE|DOI:10.1371/journal.pone.0155596 June15,2016 2/13 SociallyEnforcedNepotism playerjhelpsplayeriasmuchasihelpsj)andgeneralizedreciprocity(wherej,concerned withherreputationamongotherplayers,helpsievenificannotreciprocate).Manyanthro- pologistsregardgeneralizedreciprocity,orcommunalsharing[7],asahallmarkofrelations amongkin. Thisbringsustotheempiricalmotivationforthepresentwork.Longbeforeevolutionary biologistsdevisedthetheoryofkinselection,culturalanthropologistsdevelopedtheirown theoryofkinship—perhapsthediscipline’ssinglegreatestcontributiontothehumansci- ences.Thestudyofkinshipisimportantbecause,asonescholarwrites,“Inmanysocieties, bothprimitiveandsophisticated,relationshipstoancestorsandkinhavebeenthekeyrela- tionshipsinthesocialstructure;theyhavebeenthepivotsonwhichmostinteraction,most claimsandobligations,mostloyaltiesandsentiments,turned”[8].Thestudyofkinshiphas resultedinanumberofimportantfindings;ofspecialinteresthereisageneralizationregard- ingtheconnectionbetweenkinshipandaltruism:“Kindredandkindnessgotogether—two wordswhosecommonderivationexpresses...oneofthemainprinciplesofsociallife”[9]. Inotherwords, thecentralvaluepremiseassociatedwith[thenotionofkinship]isuniform.Kinshippredi- catestheaxiomofamity,theprescriptivealtruismexhibitedintheethicofgenerosity.... [T]heruleposits...that“kinsfolk”haveirresistibleclaimsononeanother’ssupportand consideration...simplybyreasonofthefactthattheyarekin.Kinsfolkmustideallyshare ...andtheymust,ideally,dosowithoutputtingapriceonwhattheygive.[10] Theobservationthatpeopleactaltruisticallytowardtheirkinevenwhentheycanexpect nothinginreturnsoundslikewhatthetheoryofkinselectionpredicts.Butthereisacrucial complication:humankinshiphasanormativeside,asimpliedbythewords“prescriptive,” “ethic,”“rule,”and“ideally”above.Howonepersontreatsothers,includingherkin,ispartly guidedbyherpersonalfeelingstowardthembutalsopartlydictatedbysocialconventions. Thismeans,accordingtomanyanthropologists,thathumankinaltruismcomesintwovarie- ties.(Muchoftheevidenceregardingthetwovarietiesofnepotismcomesfromalargebodyof qualitativeethnographicstudies,butthedistinctionhasalsobeenupheldbyrecentquantitative research[11,12].)Onevariety(callitindividualnepotism)ismotivatedbybenefactors’feelings ofattachmenttotheirbeneficiaries.Itislargelydirectedtoclosekin(consistentwithinclusive fitnesstheory,sincecoefficientsofrelatednessfalloffrapidlywithgenealogicaldistance).The secondvariety(callitsociallyenforcednepotism)isgovernedbyconventionsabouthowkin oughttobetreated,andismotivatedbysocialpressureandconcernforone’sstandingina moralcommunity.Itcanextendeventodistantkin.“[T]hemostconvincingevidence...of kinshipamity[isfoundin]situationswherekinshipissotenuousastobeonlynominal,as whenpersonsseekoutremoteclansfolk...andwithoutfurtheradoclaimandreceivehospital- ityandprotection.”[10]Itissociallyimposednepotismthathelpsmakekinshipimportantnot justforfamilylife,butforsocialorganizationonalargerscale. Individualnepotismlooksalotlikekinaltruisminotherspecies[13].Sociallyenforcednep- otismisdifferent.Itdependsonthemoralregulationofbehavioraccordingtosociallytrans- mittednorms—somethingregardedbymanysocialscientists,includingsomeevolution- mindedones,asadistinguishingfeatureofourspecies[14–16].Hencethemodelbelow,com- bininggametheoryandpopulationgenetics,inwhichthestartingpointisnotanindividual decidingonherownhowmuchtohelpherkin,butagroupofunequalindividualssettlingon andenforcinganormdeterminingwhogetshowmuch. PLOSONE|DOI:10.1371/journal.pone.0155596 June15,2016 3/13 SociallyEnforcedNepotism Results Distributionalnorms,reputation,andincentives Imaginesociallifeasadrama[17].Eachindividualplaystherole(s)appropriatetoherstatus, treatingotherplayersasdirectedbyherroleandtheirs,withallplayersactingfromashared script.Aspartofthedrama,realcostsarepaidandbenefitsreceived,soaplayerhasanextrin- sicmotivetosticktothescript:ifshebreakscharacter,otherplayersreactsoastoleaveher withlowernetbenefits.HereItranslatethisdramaturgicalmetaphorintoagame-theoretical modelinwhichplayersuseindirectreciprocityandreputationtogetoneanothertoplaytheir parts.Inthemodel,playersdifferintheirabilitytohelpothers(=status);theyhelpandare helpedbasedontheiradvertisedabilities(=assumedroles);andeachhasanincentivetohon- estlyadvertiseherabilitybyfollowingadistributionalnorm(=sharedscript). Consideragameamongagroupofnplayers.Ineachroundofplay,eachplayerhasthe opportunitytohelpsomerandomlyselectedtargetplayers.Costsandbenefitsofhelpingare relatedbytheproductionfunction b ¼a1(cid:3)tct ð1Þ ij j ji wherebijisthebenefitthatireceivesfromj,cjiisthecostthatjincursinhelpingi(bothaver- agedoveralongspanofplay),αjisameasureofj’sproductiveability,andτgeneratesdimin- ishingmarginalreturnstohelping,withbij,cji,andαj(cid:4)0,and0<τ<1. Weareinterestedinindirectreciprocity,whereplayerjproducesbenefitsforplayeribased onthebenefitsihasproducedforotherplayersinearlierroundsofplay[18–25].Whopro- duceshowmuchforwhom—thevalueofbij—dependsondistributionalnormsandreputa- tions.Let’sassumeinitiallythatmembersofagroupagreeonasingledistributionalnorm,call itA,definedbyafunctionbA[x,y]overx(cid:4)0,y(cid:4)0.Thisfunctiondictateshowmuchbenefita playerwithabilityxoughttogetfromaplayerwithabilityy.Ifiandjhaveabilitiesαiandαj, andjfollowsthenorm,thenbij=bA[αi,αj].Supposehoweverthatjcannotassessi’sability directly,butmustactaccordingtoanascribedability,orreputation,fori.Toachievethis,the functionbAmustmadetooperateintwodirections,determiningboththebenefitsjproduces forotherplayersandthereputationothersassignher.First,ifjknowsherownability,αj,and ascribesabilitysitoplayeri,shecanrewardiaccordingtobij=bA[si,αj].Second,ifsomeplayer kknowswhatbenefitsjhasproducedforotherplayers,andhasascribedabilitiesforthem,she canworkbackwardtoassignanewreputation,sj,toj,wheresjisimplicitlygivenbybA(as spelledoutbelow).Thismeansthatreputationisdefinedrecursively:thereputationofeach playerdependsonthebenefitsshebestowsonothersandontheirreputations.Theresult,at equilibrium,isthatreputationequalsability(sj=αj)andplayersreceivebenefitsaccordingto bij=bA[αi,αj]andpaycostsaccordingtocji ¼a(cid:3)j 1(cid:3)ttbA½ai;aj(cid:5)1=t,foralliandj. Inprinciple,anynormwithnon-negativebA[x,y]isallowed,includinganormofpure altruism,“fromeachaccordingtohisability,toeachaccordingtohisneed”(Fig1A).Buthere weareespeciallyinterestedintheclassofincentive-compatiblestablenorms,whichmotivate eachself-interestedplayertohonestlyadvertiseherabilitybyfollowingthenorm,provided othersdolikewise.Astablenormandassociatedreputationfunctionmustsatisfyseveral conditions. (i)Positivenetbenefits.Foreachactiveplayerj,summedbenefitsminussummedcostsaver- agedovermanyroundsofplaymustbegreaterthanzero. X X bA½a;a (cid:5)(cid:3)a(cid:3)1(cid:3)tt bA½a;a(cid:5)1=t >0 ð2Þ j k j i j k i PLOSONE|DOI:10.1371/journal.pone.0155596 June15,2016 4/13 SociallyEnforcedNepotism Fig1.Threedistributionalnorms.Howbenefitsshouldbedistributedasafunctionofrecipient(x)anddonor(y)ability,according tonormsof(A)PureAltruism,(B)AlmostBalancedReciprocity,and(C)GeneralizedReciprocity.Onleft,benefits,b[x,y];onright, recipientnetbenefits,b[x,y]−c[x,y].Colorsscalewithbenefitsornetbenefits,1.0isred,0.0islightblue.Blacklinesshowwhere netbenefitsequalzero. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0155596.g001 (ii)Penaltyforimpersonation.Foreachactiveplayerj,hersummednetbenefitsmustbe greaterifshehonestlyadvertisesherability,αj,thanifshe“impersonates”aplayeroflesseror greaterability,y: X X bA½a;a (cid:5)(cid:3)a(cid:3)1(cid:3)tt bA½a;a(cid:5)1=t j k j i j Xk Xi ð3Þ > bA½y;a (cid:5)(cid:3)a(cid:3)1(cid:3)tt bA½a;y(cid:5)1=t k j i k i fory6¼αj.Sosummednetbenefitsmustincrease,neithertooslowlynortooquickly,with donorability. (iii)Penaltyforinconsistency.Playerjmightbelessgeneroustosomeplayersandmoregen- eroustoothersthanisconsistentwithhonestlyadvertisingherabilityajorimpersonatinga playerwithabilityy:theremightnotbeanyoneysuchthatbij=bA[si,y]foralli.Inthiscase,j isassignedanintermediateweightedaveragereputation,sj,chosensothatbij<bA[si,sj]for PLOSONE|DOI:10.1371/journal.pone.0155596 June15,2016 5/13 SociallyEnforcedNepotism someiandbij>bA[si,sj]forotheri.Theaimisnottomakesjanaccurateestimateofαj,butto penalizejforbehavinginconsistently.Forexample,let X(cid:2) (cid:3) 0¼ b1=t(cid:3)bA½s;s(cid:5)1=t oðb1ij=t(cid:3)bA½si;sj(cid:5)1=tÞ ð4Þ ij i j i Thisgivessjasanimplicitfunctionofthebenefitsjproduces,bij,andthereputationsofher P beneficiaries,si.Supposeω=1.Thentheωtermdropsout,andj’sactualcost,a(cid:3)j 1(cid:3)tt ibi1j=t,is P equaltothecost,a(cid:3)1(cid:3)tt bA½s;s(cid:5)1=t,shewouldpayifsheconsistentlyimpersonatedaplayer j i i j withabilitysj.Soinconsistentplaygetsherthesamereputation,forthesamecost,asconsistent play.Butsupposeinsteadthat0<ω<1.Thenjpaysthesamecostasbefore,butherreputa- tionisnowlower,becausesubparbij’saremoreheavilyweighted,andreducesjmorethan excessivebij’sincreaseit.Sowemake0<ω<1:eitherjisconsistent,andgetstheappropriate sjforhonestadvertisingorconsistentimpersonation,orjisinconsistent,andpaysareputa- tionalpenalty. Withadistributionalnormandareputationfunctionthatsatisfytheseconditions,consis- tenthonestadvertisingisthebeststrategyforeachplayer,aslongasothersfollowthenorm.So thehonestadvertisingconstraintssetlimitsonwhatdistributionalnormsarestableamong self-interestedplayers—forexample,thenormmatchingthepayoffsunderpurealtruismisnot stable.Butwithintheselimits,thereisawiderangeofstablenorms,includingthetwobelow, whichdifferinhowwelltheytreatweakplayers,andaremeanttocapturetheanthropologist’s distinctionbetweenbalancedandgeneralizedreciprocity. AlmostBalancedReciprocity Onefamilyofdistributionalnormsassignsequalpayoffsinbothdirections,bA[x,y]=bA[y,x] forallxandy.Playersgetonlyasmuchtheygive,and“thereain’tnosuchthingasafree lunch.”Wecanpickonememberofthisfamilybyallowingtheweakerplayertoset bA[x,y]=bA[y,x]toherpreferredvalue,t(cid:3)1(cid:3)ttxforx(cid:6)y.Thisnormisstableunderdirectrec- iprocity,andalsounderindirectreciprocitywhereplayersestimatereputationsaccordingto Condition4. There’sahitch,however.Exactbalancedreciprocity,directorindirect,isnotdynamically stable.Ifplayersstartsomewhereotherthanatequilibrium,andestimateoneanother’sabilities basedonpastplay,thenreputationsandbenefitsproduceddon’tconvergeontheequilibrium. Evensmallperturbationsaredestabilizing.TheunderlyingproblemisfamiliarfromtheIter- atedPrisoner’sDilemmagame:twotit-for-tatplayersdon’tgettothecooperativeequilibrium iftheyaren’talreadythere.Intheprisoner’sdilemmacase,thiscanbefixedwithaforgiving amendmenttothetit-for-tatstrategy[26].Inthepresentcase,theanalogousfixistoset bA[x,y]slightlyhigherthanbA[y,x]forx<y,withthedifferenceadjustedtosatisfyCondition 3.WecalltheresultingstabledistributionalnormAlmostBalancedReciprocity,orB,with definingfunctionbB(Figs1Band2). GeneralizedReciprocity WithAlmostBalancedReciprocity,astrongplayercouldprovideaweakplayerwithgreater benefitsatlittleaddedcosttoherself,butdoesn’tdosobecauseitwouldbetoocostlyforthe weakplayerto(almost)matchtheextrabenefits.Discardingtheprinciplethatexchangesmust balanceallowsforamoreevendistributionofbenefitsandgreatertotalnetbenefits.Consider thenormthatmaximizesgroupnetbenefits,subjecttothehonestadvertisingconstraints. Withthisnorm,astrongplayergivessubstantialhelptoweakplayers,evenentirelyhelpless PLOSONE|DOI:10.1371/journal.pone.0155596 June15,2016 6/13 SociallyEnforcedNepotism Fig2.ReachingequilibriumwithAlmostBalancedReciprocity.Inagroupof40players,eachplayerj producesbenefitsforarandom5playersiineachround,followingbBandbeginninginround1usingrandom privateestimatesofsi.Foreachj,everyotherplayerkcalculatesarevisedsjofherown,afterobservinga random3ofj’s5randomactsofkindness,bypluggingthe3bij’sandher3unrevisedsi’sintotheimplicit functiongivenbyCondition4.Foreachj,playerkthenaveragesherrevisedandunrevisedsj’stogeneratenew sj’sthatwilldeterminehowmuchshehelpsarandom5playersinthenextround.Chartshowsatypicalresult forarandomplayer’sprivateestimatesofsj’sfor10otherrandomplayersj:hersj’sconvergeonαj’s. (GeneralizedReciprocitygivessimilarresults.) doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0155596.g002 playerswithα=0,inordertoupholdherreputationandberewardedbyotherstrongplayers. Thisissociallyenforcedaltruism.Itislessgenerousthanpurealtruism,becausestrongplayers needtodobetterthanweakplayerstoencouragehonestadvertising,butmoregenerousthan AlmostBalancedReciprocity. Anevenmoregenerousdistributionispossibleifwemaximizetotalnetbenefits,butallowj someknowledge,notjustofthebenefitsiproduces,butofthecostsipays.Inthiscase,aweaki helpingothersatsomecosttoherselfcanreceivemorecreditthanastrongerplayerproviding thesamebenefitsatlesscost[27],makingitpossibletoenforcemoregenerositytowardweak playerswithoutmotivatingshirkingamongstrongplayers.Hereweuseaversionofadistribu- tionalnormwithsomeknowledgeofcosts,callingitGeneralizedReciprocity,orG,withdefin- ingfunctionbG(Fig1C). Mixedgroups,compromise,andkinselection Eithernorm,AlmostBalancedReciprocity(B)orGeneralizedReciprocity(G),isstableif everyoneagreestoit.Butwhathappensifplayersdon’tagree?Evolutionaryconsiderationscan helpanswerthisquestion. Consideramixedgroup,inwhichsomeplayersfollownormBandsomefollowG.Insuch agroup,eachplayerjcanbeassignedtworeputations,sBandsG,dependingonthebenefitsshe j j producesandthereputations,sBandsG,ofherbeneficiaries.Wecannumericallycalculatean i i equilibrium,atwhichtypeBplayersrewardotherplayersaccordingtotheirsBreputationsand typeGplayersrewardaccordingtosG(Table1).Wecanfurthercalculatethemeannetbenefits accruingtoeachtype.SimulationsshowthatingroupswithagivenfrequencyoftypesBand G,themorecommontypeusuallygetsgreatermeannetbenefits;butinacollectionofgroups withdifferentfrequenciesofBandG,bothtypesusuallygetgreatermeannetbenefitsinthose groupswhereBislessfrequentandGmorefrequent(Fig3,lowerportion). PLOSONE|DOI:10.1371/journal.pone.0155596 June15,2016 7/13 SociallyEnforcedNepotism Table1.Reputationinamixedgroup.Equilibriumreputations,sBandsG,calculatedforamixedgroupof 40playersofvaryingability(α).Arandom20playersfollownormBand20followG;resultsaregivenfor threerepresentativeplayersofeachtype.Playersaccuratelyassessabilitiesofthoseoftheirowntype,but under-oroverestimateabilitiesofthoseofunliketype.) Type α sB sG B 1.925 1.925 1.156 B 1.025 1.025 .934 B .325 .325 .229 G 1.725 1.958 1.725 G .925 .968 .925 G .125 .178 .125 doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0155596.t001 Nowconsideralargepopulationofgroups,eachofsizenandaveragewithin-grouprelated- nessr,wheretheoverallfrequencyoftypeBinthepopulationispB.Onaverage,aBplayer findsherselfinagroupwheretypeBnumbers1+(n−1)(r+pB−r(cid:1)pB),andaGplayerfinds herselfinagroupwheretypeBnumbers(n−1)(pB−r(cid:1)pB)(lowerarrowsinFig3).Ifnisnot verysmall,andrisnotverylarge,eithernumberiscloseton(cid:1)pB.Ifnetbenefitsarepropor- tionaltoincrementsinfitness,thenthecommontype(awayfromtheequalpayoffcrossover point)isexpectedtohavehigherfitnessinmostgroups.Selectionwithingroups,favoringthe commontype,isstrongerthanselectionbetweengroups,favoringG.Whicheverdistributional normstartsoutathighfrequencygoestofixation. Yetthesurvivalofthecommonestisnottheendoftheevolutionarystory.Theequilibrium wheresomegroupmembersplayBandothersGisnotaNashequilibrium.Individualsof Fig3.Mixedgroups.Averagenetbenefitsinmixedgroupsof40players,withnBplayingAlmostBalanced ReciprocityandnGplayingGeneralizedReciprocity—orwiththetwotypescompromisingonanintermediate norm—basedonrandomsamplingofplayerswithdifferingabilities.Linesshowquadraticbestfitstopoints. Arrowsshowthatwithamodestcoefficientofrelatedness(r=.06,suggestedby[5,28])andnocompromise, araretypeGdoesworsethanacommontypeB,butwithcompromise,araretypeGdoesbetter. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0155596.g003 PLOSONE|DOI:10.1371/journal.pone.0155596 June15,2016 8/13 SociallyEnforcedNepotism eithertypecandobetteriftheydon’tsticktotheirpreferredstrategy,butadapttothepresence oftheothertype.Suchaccommodationwithinamixedgroupcantakevariousforms. First,allplayerscancompromiseonanintermediatestrategy.Acompromisedistributional norm(callitW)canbedefinedbyaparameterw ,with0<w <1,suchthatthesummednet 0 0 benefitreceivedbyaplayerwithabilityyisaweightedmeanofthesummednetbenefits receivedbyayplayerundernormsBandG,withweightsw and1−w .Foragivenw ,abene- 0 0 0 fitfunctionbWcanbedefinedsuchthatthecorrespondingnormWisstable,givingeachplayer anincentivetohonestlyadvertiseherabilitiesaslongasothersfollowthenorm.Hereweallow eachgrouptosettleonthew forwhichbW1/τgivesaleast-squaresbestfittob1=tfortypeBand 0 ij typeGplayers. Whenplayerscompromiselikethis,simulationsgivedifferentresultsthanwhentheydon’t (Fig3).BothtypesdobetterwhentheysettleonanintermediatenormW.Furthermore, amongcompromisinggroupswithagivenfrequencyoftypesBandG,Busuallydoesslightly betterthanG.Thisisbecausestrongplayershavemoreinfluenceonthevalueofw thanweak 0 players.IngroupswheremoreofthestrongplayersaretypeB,theB’s“vote”greaternetbene- fitsforthestrongestplayers,themselves;wheremoreofthestrongplayersaretypeG,theG’s “vote”greaternetbenefitsfortheaverageplayer.ButGcanstillprevail:withpositivewithin- grouprelatedness,typeGplayersaremorelikelytofindthemselvesingroupswithextratype Gplayers(upperarrowsinFig3).StrongGplayers’supportforhighermeannetbenefitsin thesegroupscangiveGagreateraveragefitness. Inanalternativeformofcompromise,typeBandGplayerspersistinplayingtheirrespec- tivestrategies,whileathirdtypeofplayer,typeW,adoptsthecompromisestrategycorre- spondingtothegroup’sleast-squaresw .Experimentationwitharangeofparametervalues 0 showsthatingroupswhereBandGplayersrefusetocompromise,typeW—amoralchame- leonwhotakesontheaveragecolorofhersurroundings—generallydoesbetter(Fig4).Once typeWreacheshighfrequency,selectionchanges,andtheraresttypeisnolongeratsuchadis- advantage.InapopulationwithaverycommontypeW,raretypeG,lessraretypeB,andmod- eratewithin-grouprelatedness,atypeGplayermayoftenfindherselfinagroupcontaining manytypeW’s,severaltypeGkin,andfewertypeB’s.Suchagroupwillleantowardenforcing agenerous,G-weightednorm,totheadvantageoftypeG. Socombiningasmallmeasureofprincipledrule-followingwithalargemeasureofself- interestedcompromiseopensupnewspaceforkinselection.WhentypesBandGcompromise onnormW,variancewithingroupsdecreases.WhenBandGdon’tcompromiseandthe compromisingtypeWbecomesmorefrequent,variancebetweengroupsincreases.Eitherway, compromisestrengthensselectionbetweengroupsrelativetoselectionwithinthem.With sociallyenforcedaltruism,alittlerelatednesscangoalongway. Discussion Abigmotivefordevelopingthetheoryofkinselectionwastheproblemofaltruism:Whydoes oneorganismsometimeshelpanotherwhenthathelpwillnotbereciprocated?Theanalogous motivefordevelopingatheoryofsociallyenforcednepotismistheproblemofdistribution: Howarethegainsfromcooperationdistributed?[29]Whydoessocialexchangesometimes shadeintouni-directionalgenerosity—balancedreciprocityintogeneralizedreciprocity? Previoustheory[19]andevidence[30,31]showthatindirectreciprocitycanmotivatecoop- erationintheformofcontributionstopublicgoods.Themodeldevelopedheregoesfurther.It issimultaneouslyaboutmotivatingcooperationandaboutdistributingthegainsfromcoopera- tionamongplayersofunequalabilities.Kinshipispartofthestorybecauseevenmodestcoeffi- cientsofrelatedness—toolowtomotivatemuchindividualnepotism—canturntheproblemof PLOSONE|DOI:10.1371/journal.pone.0155596 June15,2016 9/13 SociallyEnforcedNepotism Fig4.Threetypes.StreamplotofselectionvectorsforpopulationswithfractionspB,pG,andpWplaying AlmostBalancedReciprocity,GeneralizedReciprocity,andaWeightedCompromise.Fitnessesare proportionaltonetbenefits,averagedoverrandomsamplesofmixedgroupsof40playerswithcoefficientof relatednessr=.06.BluelineshowsaneutrallystablemixofBandWplayers,greenlineaneutrallystable mixofGandWplayers.Atswitchpoint,themixtureofBandWisunstable:populationleavesB/Wequilibrium forG/W,nevertoreturn.Group1:TypicalgroupcompositionexperiencedbyarareGplayerandherrelatives whentypeWisabsent.TypeG(greencircles;sizestandsforability)isoutnumberedbytypeB(bluecircles). Group2:TypicalgroupcompositionexperiencedbyarareGplayerandherrelativeswhentypeWis common.GplayerandherGrelativesoutnumbertypeB;typeWplayers(whitecircles)skewtheirplay towardGeneralizedReciprocity,amplifyingsmallr. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0155596.g004 distributionfromaconstantsumgameintoapublicgoodsgame:allarebetteroffevolution- arilyifstrongplayersgiveuppotentialnetbenefitstohelpweakplayers.(Aruleofthumb:if r(cid:7)1/n,thenaplayercanexpectthatothergroupmemberscarrymorecopiesofhergenes thanshedoes,andsheshould“vote”forthenormthatisbestfortheaverageplayer,evenifit’s notbestforher.[5]) Theworkhereextendsearlierfindingsthatindirectreciprocitydependsonreputationand reputationmustbedefinedrecursively,sothateachplayer’sreputationdependsbothonthe benefitssheprovidesandonthereputationsofthebeneficiaries.Inthemodelhere,reputation isanindexofability,and,likeability,canvarycontinuously.Sothemodelfacestheproblemof assigninganumericalreputationtoeachplayerbasedonthereputationsofotherplayers.This ismorecomplicatedthansimplychoosingtocooperateornotbasedonwhethertheother playerisingoodorbadstanding.Itisclosetotheproblemofdesigningapage-rankingalgo- rithmthatranksacollectionofwebpagesbyassigningascoretoeachpagebasedonthescores ofthepagesthatlinktoit[32].Someofthesameissuesariseinbothcases:forexample, whetheragivendistributionalnormorpage-rankingalgorithmisdynamicallystableandcon- vergesonaconsistentresult. Themodelmustsatisfyafurthersetofconditions.Werequirethatadistributionalnormbe enforceable(orincentivecompatible):aplayerofwhateverabilityshoulddobetterstickingto thenorm,ratherthanimpersonatingastrongerorweakerplayerorplayinginconsistently,as PLOSONE|DOI:10.1371/journal.pone.0155596 June15,2016 10/13

Description:
Here I present a model of social norms enforced by indirect reciprocity. In the rest of this introduction, I summarize theoretical and empirical . biologists devised the theory of kin selection, cultural anthropologists . In principle, any norm with non-negative bA[x, y] is allowed, including a no
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.