Social Morphogenesis Margaret S. Archer Editor Social Morphogenesis 123 Editor Margaret S. Archer Collège desHumanités EPFL Ecole PolytechniqueFédérale deLausanne Lausanne Switzerland ISBN 978-94-007-6127-8 ISBN 978-94-007-6128-5 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-007-6128-5 SpringerDordrechtHeidelbergNewYorkLondon LibraryofCongressControlNumber:2013931201 (cid:2)SpringerScience?BusinessMediaDordrecht2013 Thisworkissubjecttocopyright.AllrightsarereservedbythePublisher,whetherthewholeorpartof the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation,broadcasting,reproductiononmicrofilmsorinanyotherphysicalway,andtransmissionor informationstorageandretrieval,electronicadaptation,computersoftware,orbysimilarordissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed. Exempted from this legal reservation are brief excerpts in connection with reviews or scholarly analysis or material supplied specifically for the purposeofbeingenteredandexecutedonacomputersystem,forexclusiveusebythepurchaserofthe work. Duplication of this publication or parts thereof is permitted only under the provisions of theCopyrightLawofthePublisher’slocation,initscurrentversion,andpermissionforusemustalways beobtainedfromSpringer.PermissionsforusemaybeobtainedthroughRightsLinkattheCopyright ClearanceCenter.ViolationsareliabletoprosecutionundertherespectiveCopyrightLaw. The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publicationdoesnotimply,evenintheabsenceofaspecificstatement,thatsuchnamesareexempt fromtherelevantprotectivelawsandregulationsandthereforefreeforgeneraluse. While the advice and information in this book are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication,neithertheauthorsnortheeditorsnorthepublishercanacceptanylegalresponsibilityfor anyerrorsoromissionsthatmaybemade.Thepublishermakesnowarranty,expressorimplied,with respecttothematerialcontainedherein. Printedonacid-freepaper SpringerispartofSpringerScience?BusinessMedia(www.springer.com) Contents 1 Social Morphogenesis and the Prospects of Morphogenic Society. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1 Margaret S. Archer Part I Social Morphogenesis and Societal Transformation? 2 Morphogenesis and Social Change . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 25 Douglas V. Porpora 3 The Morphogenetic Approach and the Idea of a Morphogenetic Society: The Role of Regularities . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 39 Andrea M. Maccarini 4 Emergence and Morphogenesis: Causal Reduction and Downward Causation?. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 61 Tony Lawson 5 Morphogenesis, Continuity and Change in the International Political System . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 85 Colin Wight Part II Social Formations and Their Re-formation 6 Self-Organization: What Is It, What Isn’t It and What’s It Got to Do with Morphogenesis? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 105 Kate Forbes-Pitt v vi Contents 7 Self-Organisation as the Mechanism of Development and Evolution in Social Systems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 125 Wolfgang Hofkirchner 8 Morphogenic Society: Self-Government and Self-Organization as Misleading Metaphors . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 145 Margaret S. Archer Part III Social Networks: Linkages or Bonds? 9 Network Analysis and Morphogenesis: A Neo-Structural Exploration and Illustration . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 167 Emmanuel Lazega 10 Authority’s Hidden Network: Obligations, Roles and the Morphogenesis of Authority. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 187 Ismael Al-Amoudi 11 Morphogenesis and Social Networks: Relational Steering Not Mechanical Feedback. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 205 Pierpaolo Donati Chapter 1 Social Morphogenesis and the Prospects of Morphogenic Society Margaret S. Archer This book is about theorising a possible transition from the social order of late modernity. What we examine is the generative mechanism of ‘social morpho- genesis’, held to account for the increasing rapidity of social change. In itself, rapidsocialchangedoesnotnecessarilysignal,muchlessconstitute,anewtypeof social formation. What intrigues us is whether or not this increasingly important process could be responsible for generating a different kind of social formation— MorphogenicSociety—albeitonewiththepotentialforassumingamultiplicityof specific forms. None of us is committed to announcing the advent of the Mor- phogenic Society, but regard it as worth exploring. All of us are wary about the array of social forms that have hastily been advanced as superseding modernity. Thus, we do not precipitously announce a new ‘Beyond’. Instead, the book deals with ‘social morphogenesis’ as a process rather than an end product. Clearly, this processdoesnotnecessarilygeneratemacroscopicsocialtransformationbecauseit hasbeenwithusforcenturies,althoughalways,untilnow,incounterbalancewith morphostatic mechanisms. Whilst we will certainly question the justifiability of thinking and theorising about Morphogenic Society, nevertheless, the question mark remains throughout. M.S.Archer(&) Centred’OntologieSociale,EcolePolytechniqueFédéraledeLausanne, Station10,Lausanne1015,Switzerland e-mail:margaret.archer@epfl.ch M.S.Archer(ed.),SocialMorphogenesis,DOI:10.1007/978-94-007-6128-5_1, 1 (cid:2)SpringerScience+BusinessMediaDordrecht2013 2 M.S.Archer 1.1 Part 1. Social Morphogenesis and Societal Transformation? The ten contributors to this volume are working together in an unusual way: addressing this question mark collaboratively, exploring rather than proclaiming and voicing our own reservations, hesitations, objections and differences in interpretation and conviction. In other words, we reverse the usual sequence of ‘publication’followedbycriticalreview.Noonehasyetadvancedorismarriedto atheoryofthecomingofMorphogenicSociety.Instead,throughauto-critique,we try to anticipate the criteria such a theory would have to meet; the objections and alternativesitwouldhavetoovercome.Atmost,explicitspeculationsareventured aboutthepossibilityofthissocialformation.However,westillliveinthecrisisof late modernity, a formation that appears to be gasping without any guarantee that this is its last gasp. Rather, we concentrate on the process of ‘social morpho- genesis’becauseonlyifwecanarticulateagenerativemechanismofsocialchange is there any convincing basis for beginning to theorise about radical social transformation. Our focus upon ‘social morphogenesis’ has two implications. First, in con- centrating upon morphogenesis we have elected to deal with ‘those processes which tend to elaborate or change a system’s given form, structure, or state’ in preferencetomorphostaticprocesses‘thattendtopreserveormaintainasystem’s form,organization,orstate’(Buckey1967,58).Whataccountsforthisconsensus, especially given that none of us would hold that morphostasis has yet been dis- placed? (As Wight properly maintains in Chap. 5, that which is unchanged is the benchmark for what has changed). Part of the answer lies in a shared conviction about the growing rapidity of social change over the last quarter of a century, although the proposition that change is speeding up is remarkably difficult to demonstrate empirically. Partly too, we are all—though not in the same way—in quest of a generative mechanism accounting for it. In other words, we agree that satisfactory explanation cannot be at the level of experience (the empirical level) or at the level of events (the actual level) but needs to identify a real mechanism whoseexercise,evenintheopensystemthatisthesocialorder,isresponsiblefor theintensificationofsocialchange.Inotherwords,weshareacollectiveantipathy towards empiricist explanations and we hold that the vast literature on globali- sation—an outcome broadly coterminous with the tendencies upon which we focus—has been incurably ‘actualist’. These two points will be examined in turn. First,beforeexaminingwhetherornotsuchchangeandthemechanismgenerating itjustifyconsideringMorphogenicSocietyasasocialformationinstatunascendi, it is necessary to probe the reasons for such rapidity of change. 1 SocialMorphogenesisandtheProspectsofMorphogenicSociety 3 The Rapidity of Social Change and Empiricism’s Shortcomings Most lay people in the developed world will agree that change has speeded up in their lifetimes, but what reasons do they give for their assertion? Technological innovations are favourite markers, especially for grandparents: flights for all, mobile phones, the Internet (their own parents probably favoured inventions: the car, the phone, the plane, television). Impressionistically, any marker will do and today’s young people might cite the rise and fall of music groups, the arrival of social interactionsites ortherapidsuccessionofnewapps. Nobodyiswrong,but everybody is exercising selective perception. The selectivity of folk wisdom is matched by academic approaches that are equally selective. This is the source of the conundrum—and it is rooted in empiricism. In brief, there seem to be four intractable problems attaching to any empirical estimation of the rapidity of social change. First, what is included is necessarily incompletebecausecertainchangeswillhaveoccurredwithoutyetproducingtheir fullmanifestations,especiallygiventhelackofproportionalitybetweencauseand effect. In other words, that legendary butterfly may just have flapped its wings in Tokyo. That is the ontological problem. Epistemologically we may also be inca- pableofknowingit.AsKarlPopperonceremarked,wecannotevenknowallthe implications of any single proposition. Second, what we do know about recent social change is a series of incommensurables, literally a list without common measure,preventinganycomparisonorweightingoftheitemslisted.Forexample, inEurope,proportionatelymorepeoplecame online andlessofthem gotmarried in the last quarter of the century. However, we can neither say that these two changes made equally important contributions to change in general, nor can we assert the opposite. Third, change often involves displacement. As the average hours spent watching television per capita have risen, those for listening to radio have fallen; as the sale of machine made knitted goods increased, those with the ability to knit has diminished. However, it cannot be concluded that a (hypo- thetical)rateofdisplacementwouldbeabettermeasureoftherapidityofchange. This is because we also know that ‘displacement’ is often artificial (planned obsolescence) and may involve no significant change at all (cosmetics). Finally and most importantly, what is deemed ‘a change’, that is an element contributing to the judgement that there has been ‘rapid change’ overall, is inescapably value- laden. It will be theory-laded too because to focus upon any kind of substantive change(economic,political,demographic,culturaletc.)wouldinvolvetheoretical assumptions about its ‘centrality’—alone or in some combination—that may be challenged as unjustified or unjustifiable. In sum, the rapidity or otherwise of social change remains an inherently contested concept in the empirical domain. The point is not merely that everyone knows whatever they do know about social change from a particular perspective (their job, their gender, the various positions that they occupy). It is that if we accept that each perspective is ‘news from somewhere’, we must also agree that there is, indeed, no ‘news from 4 M.S.Archer nowhere’. Since reports are always expressed from a perspectival vantage point, this means that empirical and experiential access to the real state of affairs is necessarily incomplete. Were it possible to combine every existing perspective that would not be to combine every perspective possible. This is not a methodo- logicalproblemaboutrepresentativeness.Itwouldremainifeveryoneintheworld contributed their perspectives, because their composite would not be a readers’ digest of unvarnished news but merely ‘global perspectivism’. ‘Global perspectivism’ necessarily means that the same defects also dog the empirical indices or metrics, which are intended to capture indirectly that which cannot be obtained directly from the sense data people supply from different vantage points. The various metrics that are used in reporting the news and on whose basis national governments and supranational agencies take decisions— such as indicators of ‘economic growth’, ‘unemployment’, service delivery in health or education—suffer from the same empiricist defects of necessary incompleteness and consequent bias. These indices are simply crunched-up ver- sions of observations, but they are nonetheless perspectival and this cannot be rectified by eliminating deliberate manipulation or distortion, despite their fre- quency in politics and economics. This is one of the main reasons why we turn, instead, to examine generative mechanisms, rather than directly inducing them from manifest outcomes as is the empiricist practice. Although not all contributors would describe themselves as critical realists, we accept that the nature of social reality is such that its expla- nation requires the identification of the distinctive causal powers exercised at any given place or date. This is the case for those processes that account for its contoursatanyparticulartime,thosethatmaintainaparticularsocialconfiguration inbeingforsometime,andthosethattransformitsparticularkindovertime.The differencebetweenthesemechanismsandthosefoundinthenaturalorderderives from the nature of the fundamental constituents of these two orders of reality. Their difference also explains why ‘morphogenesis’ means something very different in biology (Davies 2005)—being an entirely non-conscious process— thanitdoesinsocialscience.(Theonlythingtheyshareisacommonetymology). Social reality—any section of it—is intrinsically, inherently and ineluctably ‘peopled’.Itsontologicalconstitutionisutterlyactivity-dependent,despitethefact that people’s thoughts and actions give rise to factors that are ‘not people’—the most important of these being culture and structure. Becauseofthisthereseemstobegeneralagreementthatforanyprocesstomerit considerationasageneratorofsocialchangeitmustnecessarilyincorporatestructured human relations (context-dependence), human actions (activity-dependence) and human ideas (concept-dependence). Necessarily, the three make social theorising non-naturalistic. A more familiar way of putting the above is that every theory about the social order necessarily has to incorporate SAC: structure, agency and culture. The probleminhandwillgovernwhichofthethreeisaccordedmostattentionandthe acronym SAC is thus not a rank ordering of priority between the three elements.
Description: