ebook img

Simplicius : on Aristotle physics 1.5-9 PDF

176 Pages·2012·0.98 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Simplicius : on Aristotle physics 1.5-9

SIMPLICIUS On Aristotle Physics 1.5-9 This page intentionally left blank SIMPLICIUS On Aristotle Physics 1.5-9 Translated by Han Baltussen, Michael Share, Michael Atkinson and Ian Mueller with an Introduction by Richard Sorabji LONDON • NEW DELHI • NEW YORK • SYDNEY Bloomsbury Academic An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc 50 Bedford Square 1385 Broadway London New York WC1B 3DP NY 10018 UK USA www.bloomsbury.com Bloomsbury is a registered trade mark of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc First published in 2012 Paperback edition (cid:192) rst published 2014 Translation © 2012 by Han Bultussen, Michael Share, Michael Atkinson and Ian Mueller Introduction © 2012 by Richard Sorabji Han Bultussen, Michael Snare, Michael Atkinson, Ian Mueller and Richard Sorabji have asserted their rights under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identi(cid:192) ed as Authors of this work. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or any information storage or retrieval system, without prior permission in writing from the publishers. No responsibility for loss caused to any individual or organization acting on or refraining from action as a result of the material in this publication can be accepted by Bloomsbury Academic or the author. British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library. ISBN HB: 978-0-7156-3857-6 PB: 978-1-4725-5786-5 ePDF: 978-1-4725-0173-8 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data A catalog record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. Acknowledgements The present translations have been made possible by generous and imaginative funding from the following sources: the National Endowment for the Humanities, Division of Research Programs, an independent federal agency of the USA; the Leverhulme Trust; the British Academy; the Jowett Copyright Trustees; the Royal Society (UK); Centro Internazionale A. Beltrame di Storia dello Spazio e del Tempo (Padua); Mario Mignucci; Liverpool University; the Leventis Foundation; the Arts and Humanities Research Council; Gresham College; the Esmée Fairbairn Charitable Trust; the Henry Brown Trust; Mr and Mrs N. Egon; the Netherlands Organisation for Scienti(cid:192) c Research (NWO/GW); the Ashdown Trust; Dr Victoria Solomonides, the Cultural Attaché of the Greek Embassy in London. The editor is grateful for comments on early drafts to Myrto Hatzimichali, Robert Wardy, Eleni Kechagia, Giannis Stammatellos and Fiona Leigh, and for especially full comments to Pamela Huby, Stephen Menn, Rachel Barney, Harold Tarrant and Carlos Steel. The translation of 1.6 bene(cid:192) ted from the comments of Carlos Steel, Dirk Baltzly, and Robbert van den Berg. Ian Mueller died before he was able to revise 1.7-9 in the light of valuable comments from Donald Russell and James Wilberding. The editor implemented revisions on 1.7-9 with the aid of those comments. He thanks Michael Atkinson for (cid:192) nal comments on 1.5 and 1.7-9, as well as for preparing the Greek-English indexes and subject indexes for 1.5 and 1.7-9, and collaborating with Michael Share on the indexes for 1.6. He would also like to thank Sebastian Gertz for compiling the English-Greek indexes and preparing the volume for press, and Deborah Blake, the publisher responsible for every volume in the series. The editor also wishes to thank Janel Mueller and Lucas Siorvanes for their help with proofreading. Typeset by Ray Davies. Printed and bound in Great Britain Contents Introduction Richard Sorabji 1 Conventions 13 Abbreviations 14 Translation: 1.5-6 15 1.5 Han Baltussen 17 1.6 Michael Share and Michael Atkinson 30 Departures from Diels’ Text and Bibliography 50 Notes 53 English-Greek Glossary 65 Greek-English Index 71 Subject Index 79 Memorial notice 85 Translation: 1.7-9 Ian Mueller 87 Notes 145 English-Greek Glossary 157 Greek-English Index 161 Subject Index 166 This page intentionally left blank Introduction Richard Sorabji 1.5 What is meant by principle? Aristotle (384-322 BC) here uses his survey of earlier natural philosophy in Physics 1.1-4 in order to establish what the principles (arkhai: origins or sources) are of natural change. But what is a principle? He seems to use interchangeably the terms ‘principle’, ‘element’ (stoikheion: liter- ally: letter of the alphabet) and ‘cause’ (aition: explanatory factor). But the ancient commentators did not agree at all that they were seen as interchangeable, as Simplicius (writing after 529 AD) explained in an opening discussion at 6,31-7,19 and 10,7-12,3. Plato, we there learn, was said by Aristotle’s pupil Eudemus to have been the first to distinguish elementary principles or elements, giving the name to the matter and form (as his pupil Aristotle would call them) of natural things. According to Simplicius in a later passage (233,10-14), Plato called matter and inherent form the two elementary principles, and Simplicius comments that they are elements in the strict sense because they inhere per se in what comes to be from them. But Simplicius’ opening passage contrasts Plato’s divine intellect (the demiurge or craftsman of the universe) and his goodness as being (again in Aristotle’s terms) the efficient and final causes of natural things, and, since they are above nature, as being principles of a non-elementary sort. Eudemus agreed in requiring an element, like letters of the alphabet, to be inherent or present in (enhuparkhein) that of which it was an element, but he is said to have differed from Plato by counting only matter as an element, not inherent form. From this Simplicius dissented, but five hundred years after Eudemus, his great fellow-Aristotelian, Alexander of Aphrodisias (fl. c. 205 AD), agreed that what inheres, being matter, is especially called ‘element’. This restriction of the name ‘element’ to lower principles was not universal. Proclus, for example, Simplicius’ Neoplatonist predeces- sor in Athens (c. 411-485 AD), used the term ‘element’ for some of the highest principles above nature in his work called Elements of Theology (stoikheiôsis theologikê). Conversely, Plato considered that some mate- rial constituents were too lowly to count as elements or principles. He said this of the set of elements that became most famous of all, after being introduced by Empedocles and accepted by Plato, Aristotle, the 2 Introduction Stoics and Neoplatonists and much of the Middle Ages: earth, air, fire and water. According to Plato’s Timaeus, however, they deserve to be called neither elements nor principles, since, being corpuscles, they have as principles the triangles that make up their sides and these have further principles in their turn, 48B-C; 53C-D. To return to Aristotle’s inquiry, there seem to be two restrictions on the kind of principle he is looking for here. First, for the time being, he accepted the restriction of naming only principles that inhered in what came into being from them. This is not surprising, because Physics is literally the study of nature (phusis), and Aristotle defines nature as an internal cause of change, because natural things are distinguished from artefacts by their changing size, shape, quality, and (in the case of animals) place through internal causes, unlike artefacts which have to be acted on from without, Physics 2.1; 8.4. Aristotle postponed, as Simplicius points out, 8,6-9, till the last chapter of the Physics, 8.10, a discussion of the ultimate external cause of all motion, God, the un- moved mover. The second restriction that Aristotle seems to be accepting, as Sim- plicius indicates at 1.6, 208,18-19, 1.7, 216,32 and 222,13-16, 1.9, 246,12, is that he is looking not just for constituents, but for principles of change in natural bodies. His definition of ‘principle’, much stressed by Simplicius, is given at 1.5, 188a27-30. The principles must come not from each other nor from other things, and all things must come from them. The requirement that they must not come from each other is later qualified. In a sense, two of Aristotle’s principles, form and privation, do come from each other, in that one replaces the other during the course of a change. For example at 1.7, 190a21-31, Aristotle allows that cultured comes from uncultured. Simplicius at 183,32-5 takes the ban at 188a27-30 to mean only that contraries like form and privation are on the same footing, so one is not a source for the other. At 221,21ff., commenting on Aristotle’s further remark at 191a6-7, Simplicius takes his point there to be that the contrary from which the opposite contrary comes facilitates the trans- formation only by its absence. This is not the robust sense in which, for example, a statue comes from bronze, in which the bronze is not replaced, but remains a component of the statue. Aristotle does not go so far as to claim that a contrary’s coming to be is only accidentally from a contrary, though he does later argue for the different claim in 1.8, 191a34-b26, taken up by Simplicius from 236,14-238,5, that coming to be is only accidentally from being or from non-being. At 181,10-30, Simplicius reports the ascription by Eudorus, a Platon- ist of the first century BC, to Pythagoreans of certain views about principles. On one account, the Supreme One is a principle for them, whereas the lower One and the Indefinite Dyad (sometimes called the great and the small) are contraries and only elements. This is further clarified in a report on Moderatus, a Neopythagorean of the next cen- Introduction 3 tury, in the commentary on ch. 7, at 230,34, who says that the second One is the Platonic Forms. 1.6 The exact number of principles non-empirically determined In 1.6, Aristotle attempts to establish by ratiocination the exact number of principles. This would seem crazy if one thinks of modern determina- tions of the constituents or forces constituting matter, which have to be empirically determined. Moreover, his predecessors were often trying to determine, on the basis of explanatory conjecture, what those constitu- ents might be. Earth, air, fire and water commended themselves as constituents only insofar as they seemed to explain empirical experi- ence. But here it is relevant that Aristotle was attempting something slightly different: the analysis of natural change in natural bodies. This was more a philosophical analysis than an empirical investigation. Aristotle first appeals to the history of philosophy, pointing out that most of his predecessors had cited contraries among their principles. He then claims rather boldly that there cannot be more than one primary pair of contraries. He reaches the conclusion that all natural change involves the passage from one contrary, the privation of form, to an- other, the form or its possession. But something must underlie privation and form in order to be acted on by them and in order to provide a subject that will possess in turn the contrary attributes. We need only one such underlying thing, matter, if there is only one pair of contraries. Thus (190b29-191a7, discussed in 221,20-222,28) we may seem to need three principles, matter, form and privation. But a case might be made for saying that we need only two, for form is sufficient to produce change by its presence or absence, and this discussion is continued into 1.7 and later. It turns out in the commentary on 1.9, at 245,26-30, that Simplicius considers the reduction to two principles to be Plato’s view. But already at 7,34-8,1, Simplicius, in the course of praising Aristotle as surpassing even Plato in the philosophy of nature, credits Aristotle for distinguishing matter from privation. Simplicius follows Aristotle 1.7, 190a15-17; 190b23-7; 191a1-3 and the Aristotelian Alexander in saying that matter and privation need to be distinguished in being (einai), form (eidos) and defining character (logos), even if not in num- ber, 244,29-245,9; 247,20-1. Moreover, Aristotle is concerned at 1.9, 191b35-192a1, that the distinction of privation from matter is needed for getting clear about the merely accidental sense in which things come to be from what per se is not. This had been explained in terms of privation at 1.8, 191a34-b26. Aristotle went on to warn at 1.9, 192a1-2 that those who regard matter and privation as one in number may make the mistake of thinking them one in potentiality. Aristotle finally plumps for three principles at the end of 1.8, at 191a20.

Description:
Simplicius' greatest contribution in his commentary on Aristotle on Physics 1.5-9 lies in his treatment of matter. This is its first translation into English. The sixth-century philosopher starts with a valuable elucidation of what Aristotle means by 'principle' and 'element' in Physics. Simplicius'
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.