ebook img

Shapes of Forms: From Gestalt Psychology and Phenomenology to Ontology and Mathematics PDF

380 Pages·1999·8.948 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Shapes of Forms: From Gestalt Psychology and Phenomenology to Ontology and Mathematics

SHAPES OF FORMS SYNTHESE LIBRARY STUDIES IN EPISTEMOLOGY, LOGIC, METHODOLOGY, AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Managing Editor: JAAKKO HINTIKKA, Boston University Editors: DIRK VAN DALEN, University of Utrecht, The Netherlands DONALD DAVIDSON, University of California, Berkeley THEO A.F. KUIPERS, University ofGroningen, The Netherlands PATRICK SUPPES, Stanford University, California JAN WOLEN-SKI, lagiellonian University, KrakOw, Poland VOLUME 275 SHAPES OF FORMS From Gestalt Psychology and Phenomenology to Ontology and Mathematics Edited by LILIANA ALBERTAZZI Department of Sociology and Social Research, University of Trento, Trento, Italy SPRINGER-SCIENCE+BUSINESS MEDIA, B.V. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data is available. ISBN 978-90-481-5098-4 ISBN 978-94-017-2990-1 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-017-2990-1 Prmted an acid-free paper Ali Rights Reserved © 1999 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht Origina1ly published by Kluwer Academic Publishers in 1999 Softcover reprint of the hardcover 1s t edition 1999 No part of this publication may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, inciuding photocopying, recording or by any information storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner. TABLE OF CONTENTS 1. LILIANA ALBERTAZZI / Form Aesthetics: Introduction 2. PAOLO BOZZI/Experimental Phenomenology: A Historical Profile 19 3. ALF ZIMMER / What is Form? The Contributions of Psychology to an Old Epistemological Problem 51 4. GIOVANNI BRUNO VICARIO / Forms and Events 89 5. MICHAEL STADLER, SABINE PFAFF, PETER KRUSE / Towards a Theory of Figural Form 107 6. RICCARDO LUCCIO / On Pragnanz 123 7. MANFREDO MASSIRONI, MARIA CHIARA LEVORATO / Formal Characteristics in Verbal Description and Spatial Representation 149 8. IVOR GRATTAN-GUINNESS / Forms in Algebras and their Interpretations: Some Historical and Philosophical Features 177 9. ALBERTO PERUZZI/An Essay on the Notion of Schema 191 10. ROBERTO POLl / Qua-Theories 245 11. LILIANA ALBERTAZZI / Form Metaphysics 257 12. JOHN F. SOWA / Ontological Categories 307 13. JACEK JADACKI / On Forms of Objects 341 Index of Names 361 Subject Index 365 v ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS The first idea for this volume arose out of the International Summer School in Philosophy and Artificial Intelligence on the topic of Form, organized in Bolzano, Italy, 1-5 July 1993, by the Central European Institute of Culture. My thanks go to the former President of the Institute, Professor Claudio Nolet, for his constant and valuable support. The Editor VI LILIANA ALBERTAZZI FORM AESTHETICS: INTRODUCTION 1 WHAT IS A FORM? The concept of form has been of central importance in philosophical and scientific reflection since its beginnings. One thinks, for example, of the Ionian physicists and their hypothesis that many aspects of the world depend on the form of atoms. Similarly, innumerable variations on Plato's world of ideas/ forms and Aristotle's dialectic of matter/form have characterized Western thought throughout its history. Of universal currency is Galileo's thesis that the book of nature is written in the language of the geometric forms, and that it is only necessary to learn how to read it. The various theories of form that have been developed in the twenty-five centuries of Western civilization instruct us that there is no single or fundamental theory of forms. The problem thus becomes one of those theoretical cruxes that enable us to understand the meaning and deeper-lying characteristics of a theory. A book about form, therefore, may pursue the purely theoretical purpose of developing an aesthetics of knowledge, in the sense of analysis of the forms that emerge qualitatively from the physicallevel. Moreover, the development of research connected with artificial intelligence and the cognitive sciences obliges us to confront further components of the traditional problem of form and to ask ourselves once again: 'What is a form?' Among the answers now forthcoming to this question, some seem irritatingly traditional: for example, that there exists a world of experience which displays the features of an intuitive physics, more Aristotelian than Galilean, and that the procedures of semantic categorization employed by natural language are more closely connected to perception than we would have been willing to admit even only a few years ago. These answers refer to concepts of form which assume a perceptive and phenomenological nature, and they thus recover the original meaning of scientific traditions that had grown outmoded or had been radically distorted. Indeed, it was Gardner himself, when tracing the history of cognitivism, who asked whether we have truly moved forward from Gestalt psychology and the Wiirzburg school, or whether in fact we are merely rediscovering what they already knew. 1 I shall examine two cognitive theories that are today generally assumed to be irreconcilable: that of Gibson and that of Gregory. L. Albertazzi (ed.), Shapes of Forms, 1-17. © 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers. 2 LILIANA ALBERTAZZI The supporters of an ecological theory ofp erception maintain that the same laws of organization operate in both thought and perception, an example being the Gestalt law of field, which would exclude the perception of phases. By contrast, the proponents of a constructivist theory claim that perceptive processes and the processes of thought follow the same inferential logic. In brief, Gibson's theory rejects the constructivist point of view and affirms that perception is a direct organization of the available information.2 Con versely, Gregory argues that perception is the result of our brain's processing data about a world and that it can be explained in terms of stored mental representations.3 For Gregory, perception is hypothesis, with the correlated idea that the mind must translate sensory information into a language of the mind.4 Both conceptions share the idea that perception proceeds in a single direction from stimuli to meaning, and that massive transformations in sequence are required to break these structures down for analysis. Nevertheless, although the two positions have a large amount of experimental evidence in common, they are apparently incompatible. And yet, at least in part, the polemic that divides the two theories on the cognitive processes involved in the phases between distal and proximal stimulation could profitably draw on theories developed prior to the 1930s. The theory ofp roduction developed by the Graz school, for example, assumed that perceptive aspects and cognitive integrations are connected in the various phases of the presentation. In modern terms, this suggests that the difference between 'bottom up' and 'top down' in cognitive processes is more a difference of degree than of kind internally to a form - that is, a structure consisting several layers. At issue are the differences between a theory of perception founded on eventualities ofp resentation and one founded on eventualities ofj udgement, or in modern terms, between theories of representation that place more or less emphasis on its 'inner' or 'outer' aspects, as well as the directions taken by information input and output. Moreover, between the presentation and the hypothesis lies the assumption (Annahme), which is a type of act which is not yet a judgement - in the sense of a comparison among several and successive presentations (hypotheses) - but contains a form of immediate conviction deriving from the apprehension of the mode of being (So-sein) of a physical object.5 This is an aspect of Meinongian theory which sank into oblivion but which in the last fifteen years has been revived only with regard to logico linguistic aspects of Meinong's semantics, whereas it would be much more relevant to the theory of perception in which it originated. An assumption, in simple terms, is a type of intermediate act between presentation and judgement which enables apprehension of an object through awareness of its existence or presence (Vorgegebenheit) and its ordering or structuring into an 'objective,.6 The 'hypotheses' referred to by Gregory's theory, and of which it is accused by the Gibsonians - this in effect being the term most frequently used by Gregory himself - are not always hypotheses; on occasion they are outright 'assump tions' in Meinong's sense of the term. For example, in the case of Penrose's FORM AESTHETICS: INTRODUCTION 3 impossible triangle, after apprehension of the perceptively given mode ofb eing of that 'object', the visual system assumes that all three sides touch on all three sides, whereas this happens on only one side. In fact, the sides touch only optically, because they are separate in depth. In Meinong's words, Penrose's triangle has been inserted in an 'objective', or in what we would today call a "cognitive schema". Re-examination of the Graz school's theory, as said, sheds light on several problems concerning the theory of perception, and, as Luccio points out in his contribution to this book, it helps to eliminate a number of over-simplistic commonplaces, such as the identification of the cognitivist notion of 'top down' with Wertheimer's 'von oben unten', and of 'bottom up' with his 'von unten nach oben'. In fact, neither Hochberg's and Gregory's 'concept-driven' perception nor Gibson's 'data-driven' perception coincide with the original conception of the Gestalt. In a Gestaltist configuration, in fact, 'top down' and 'bottom up' processes act simultaneously, because perception is viewed as a set of numerous processes with differing degrees of complexity. However, as Zimmer's article in this book shows, these processes are not hierarchically ordered but interact as forces of a field which tend towards stability according to a 'principle of minimum'. Necker's cube is a paradigmatic example of this phenomenon. Since competing processes are at work, constantly new spatial structurings and restructurings are generated. Other examples are provided by the phenomenon of spatial multi-stability, the perception of space from two-dimensional dis plays, and the role of symmetry in the history of science. A categorization of this kind - which broadly speaking we may call phenom enological - has nothing to do with hermeneutic phenomenology. Nor does it belong to the mainstream of analytic philosophy, although it shares a certain expository simplicity and a number of themes with the latter, as evidenced by several similarities between Husserl and Wittgenstein.7 Moreover, since its original formulation by the School of Brentano, phenomenological inquiry has always had an experimental aspect to it, as a discipline whose experimental variables are mental contents ofd irect experience rather than physical stimuli or physiological processes. 8 Experimental phenomenology, then, is not only a theory ofc onsciousness, it is also a science which could be called a descriptive psychology of perception. 9 This type of inquiry, which lies midway between metaphysics and psychology, and which draws on laboratory experiments, displays a number of variations in its base conception. By way of simplification, it was more 'cognitivist' among the Meinongians and more 'realist' in various branches of Husserlian phenomenology. Nevertheless, it invariably addressed issues that are still central to ongoing debate in the cognitive sciences - from the perception of form to the transfer of a modified image over another. Frequently, moreover, it obtained results that are today in the process of being re-discovered, as Gardner observes, and to do so used refined conceptual tools which enabled the integration of these results into a more general theory. 4 LILIANA ALBERTAZZI An intuitive example is provided by research into perceptive illusions, distortions, ambiguous objects like Rubin's vase, and paradoxical objects like Penrose's already-mentioned impossible triangle. Such inquiry had already been amply developed by Brentanist psychologists, both experimentally and theoretically, given that the theory available to them (in this particular case Meinong's theory of objects) was able to ascribe an ontological status even to entities of this kind. One thinks, in fact, of the polemic between Benussi and Koffka on ideal objects, and the dispute concerning presentations of a-sensory provenance that set Graz and Berlin against each other - with Meinong, Ameseder, Hofler and Benussi on one side, and Koffka and Buhler on the other, to cite only the best-known names.lO This, however, is an ontological problem that has broader implications than a mere dispute between schools. As shown by Grattan-Guinness's article in this volume on the objects of algebra, or by Jadacki's contribution on the objects of logic, it traverses the whole of mathematics, starting from discussion on the nature of the complex, irrational or negative numbers variously defined false, impossible or chimerical. As for phenomena of temporal inversion, like the acoustic tunnel, or those involved in the perception of causality that Michotte analysed, these are entirely coherent with Brentano's metaphysical analyses of the velocity and direction of perceptive continua. Indeed, many of these phenomena were already being investigated by experimental psychology at the beginning of this century. Curiously, current debate in the cognitive sciences displays the same conflict over the theoretical interpretation of experimental debate that split the exponents of descriptive psychology: I refer in particular to the conflict between Graz and Berlin. All these themes centred, and still centre today, on the concept of representa tion (or better, the inner stratification of the morphogenesis of the representative modules), beginning with the first stages of concrete presentations, visual and auditory presentations in particular. One of the starting-points of the contemporary cognitive sciences is, in fact, the assumption that knowledge essentially consists of the manipulation of inner representations variously defined as neurophysiological states, mental images or symbolic codifications. From these premises, also on the promptings of researchers working in the field of artificial intelligence, various theories have been developed, for example Fodor's connectionism, Johnson-Laird's mental models, and Fauconnier's mental spaces.11 In general, therefore, a Brentanian or phenomenological programme is required not only in philosophy but also in various areas of psychophysical research, examples being the theory of vision and the temporary structure of spatial representation; the recognition ofform: the analysis of the structure and formation of mental images and experimental studies of memory; the ecology of perception, phenomenologically-based structuralism and naive physics; and finally cognitive semantics as a natural approach to semantics on a representa tional basisY

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.