ebook img

Science and Convention. Essays on Henri Poincaré's Philosophy of Science and the Conventionalist Tradition PDF

243 Pages·1982·11.23 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Science and Convention. Essays on Henri Poincaré's Philosophy of Science and the Conventionalist Tradition

FOUNDATIONS Sc PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Sc TECHNOLOGY SERIES General Editor: MARIO BUNGE, McGill University, Montreal, Canada Some Titles in the Series AGASSI, J. The Philosophy of Technology ALCOCK, J. Parapsychology: Science or Magic? ANGEL, R. Relativity: The Theory and its Philosophy BUNGE, Μ. The Mind-Body Problem HATCHER, W. The Logical Foundations of Mathematics SIMPSON, G. Why and How: Some Problems and Methods in Historical Biology WILDER, R. L. Mathematics as a Cultural System Pergamon Journals of Related Interest STUDIES IN HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE* Editor: Prof. Gerd Buchdahl, Department of History and Philosophy of Science, University of Cambridge, England This journal is designed to encourage complementary approaches to history of science and philosophy of science. Developments in history and philosophy of science have amply illustrated that philosophical discussion requires reference to its historical dimensions and relevant discussions of historical issues can obviously not proceed very far without consideration of critical problems in philosophy. Studies publishes detailed philosophical analyses of material in history of the philosophy of science, in methods of historiography and also in philosophy of science treated in developmental dimensions. *Free specimen copies available on request Science and Convention Essays on Henri Po/ncaré's Philosophy of Science and The Conventionalist Tradition by JERZY GIEDYMIN University of Sussex, Brighton PERGAMON PRESS OXFORD · NEW YORK · TORONTO · SYDNEY · PARIS · FRANKFURT U.K. Pergamon Press Ltd., Headington Hill Hall, Oxford OX3 OBW, England U.S.A. Pergamon Press Inc., Maxwell House, Fairview Park, Elmsford, New York 10523, U.S.A. CANADA Pergamon Press Canada Ltd., Suite 104, 150 Consumers Road, Willowdale, Ontario M2J 1P9, Canada AUSTRALIA Pergamon Press (Aust.) Pty. Ltd., P.O. Box 544, Potts Point, N.S.W. 2011, Australia FRANCE Pergamon Press SARL, 24 rue des Ecoles, 75240 Paris, Cedex 05, France FEDERAL REPUBLIC Pergamon Press GmbH, 6242 Kronberg-Taunus, OF GERMANY Hammerweg 6, Federal Republic of Germany Copyright © 1982 Jerzy S. Giedymin All Rights Reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means; electronic, electrostatic, mag- netic tape, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without permission in writing from the publishers. First edition 1982 Library of Congress Catalog Card no: 81-81334 British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Giedymin, Jerzy Science and convention. - (Foundations & philosophy of science & technology) 1. Science - Philosophy I. Title 501 Q175 ISBN 0-08-025790-9 Printed in Great Britain by A. Wheaton & Co. Ltd., Exeter To the memory of my parents Preface ESSAYS in this volume are concerned with Henri Poincaré's philoso- phy of science—physics in particular—and with the conventionalist tradition in philosophy which he revived and reshaped at the turn of the century, simultaneously with, but independently of, Pierre Duhem. My aim was to make explicit the main ideas of that philosophy (Essays 1 and 5), to trace at least some of its historical background (Essays 1, 2 and 3) and to follow some of its later developments (Essays 2 and 4). Since the ideas in question are, for the most part, epistemological in nature and are discussed here in their historical context, the essays may perhaps be characterised as belonging to comparative epistemology. The main reason for writing these essays was this. On the basis of my research I came to the conclusion that the philosophy of Poin- caré and of his fellow-conventionalists had been perceived in too narrow a fashion, misunderstood and, consequently, under- estimated. It is my belief that in Poincaré's philosophical writings one of the leading traditions in 19th century mathematics found its epistemological and ontological expression, viz. the tradition, represented in the writings of Galois, Poncelet, Plücker, Cayley, Hermite, Darboux, Klein and many others, for which the concepts of transformations, groups and invariants were fundamental and characteristic. It penetrated not only many branches of pure mathematics but also kinematics, analytic dynamics, optics and elec- trodynamics. It provided the foundation for the mathematical shape of much of the new 20th century physics of relativity and of the quanta. As regards Poincaré's own research, discontinuous groups were essential for the theory of automorphic functions (of one complex variable) which he discovered, stimulated by Hermite's work on modular functions; Lie's theory of transformation groups was the basis for his analysis of the foundations of geometry vii viii Preface and—as Hadamard put it (1914, 1921, p. 220)—"in his guiding the nascent theory of relativity". Not surprisingly, the general ideas of transformations, groups and their structures as well as of a theory of invariants with respect to a group, which may be identified with the relativity theory of the group, became fundamental for Poincaré's epistemology (Essays 1, 2 and 5). However, the outlined perception of Poincaré's philosophy is not the one shared by the majority of his commentators, nor is it reflected in the name "conventionalism" (geometrical or physical) now usually attached to it. For some reason, those whose pronouncements were to set the trend over roughly sixty years in defining and assessing Poincaré's contribution to the philosophy of physics, have restricted their attention to only one of its two inter- related features, viz. the one expressed in the claims such as that the axioms of geometry are conventions, that the choice of one of metric geometries is (empirically) arbitrary, that scientists often elevate empirical generalisations to the status of conventional prin- ciples, that some hypotheses (indifferent ones) are conventions freely invented by the mind, etc. This feature, undoubtedly important, became henceforth enshrined in the name conventionalism, never used by Poincaré himself. So, for example, as early as April 1922 Albert Einstein is reported as saying—at a discussion in Paris where he attended a reception in his honour—that there existed two opposite views concerning physical theories between which he felt unable to decide: Kant's apriorism and Poincarés conventionalism. Both were in agreement on the point that to construct science we need arbitrary concepts; but according to Kant these were given in α priori intuition whereas according to Poincaré they were conventions (Bulletin de Ια Société Française de Philosophie, Juillet 1922; reported in Nature, August 18, 1923, p. 253). Through a kind of "harmony of illusions" (to use L. Fleck's terms) this line of exegesis became firmly established in the German-speaking countries where, in all prob- ability, the term "conventionalism" was coined. Roughly between 1918 and 1960 it permeated the logical empiricist perception of Poincaré's philosophy through the writings of Schlick, Reichenbach and Frank. It also dominated the view of the critics of logical empiricism under the influence of Popper, Frank and Holton, the Preface ix first of whom saw instrumentalism (theories are nothing but mathematical contrivances) as an essential part of conventionalism. And yet, any attentive reader of Science and Hypothesis—not to mention other writings of Poincaré, especially the (1898) paper— should have noticed the other side of Poincaré's philosophy, the side concerned with the cognitive role of groups and their invariants in mathematics and physics. This can be illustrated by the following claims: the object of geometry is to study a particular group; in our minds the latent idea of a number of groups pre-exists (these are groups with which Lie's theory is concerned); from all possible groups we choose one to which to refer natural phenomena; there is no absolute space, there is no absolute time, we have no direct intuition of the simultaneity of distant events; the principle of relative motion is impressed upon us because the commonest experiments confirm it and because the consideration of the contrary hypothesis is singularly repugnant to the mind, etc. The concept of invariance (invariantism) or of relativity would be much more appropriate than "con- ventionalism", to refer to this feature of Poincaré's epistemology. If now one inquires how the two aspects of Poincaré's epis- temology, viz. conventionalism and invariantism came to be asso- ciated, then my answer is roughly this: Poincaré's main epistemological problem was the question how objective knowledge and continuous progress were possible in spite of apparently disruptive changes in mathematics and in science. It is in his solution of this epistemological problem that he combined the ideas of convention and conventionality with the ideas of invariance, groups, transformations, etc. From such developments as the discovery of non-Euclidean geometries and of higher spaces, from the criticism of the assump- tions of absolute space and time in Newtonian mechanics and from the philosophy of the physics of the principles, Poincaré drew the conclusion that many elements of science which had appeared as ultimate truths about the world turned out, on closer analysis, to be conventional contrivances: though undoubtedly serving a purpose, they were substitutable by different conventions without change in the cognitive content of relevant theories. Consequently, not all problems and disputes in the history of science which had appeared χ Preface as substantive and empirical were indeed such. What one did not see properly was that these disputes resulted from the existence of observationally equivalent (or, at least, experimentally indistinguish- able) theories based on different conventions. Having discovered the non-empirical nature of some of the time-honoured problems con- cerned, for example, with the nature of space, time, light, etc., some philosophers, viz. nominalists, have concluded that "anything goes", that science is purely conventional. In fact it is such only if one adopts the nominalist attitude, otherwise it is not. However, in order to avoid the Scylla of naïve empiricism and the Charybdis of nominalism, one has to be clear about what constitutes the cognitive content of scientific theories and in effect where the limits of know- ledge are. One way of doing this is to adopt the view, known as instrumentalism, according to which only the observational but not the abstract part of a scientific theory contributes to the cognitive (descriptive) content. This is Ramsey's view and, perhaps, Duhem's, but—despite all appearances—not Poincaré's. For, according to Poincaré, mathematics is not concerned with the production of purely formal games. It is a study of structures and mappings which, in its progress, reveals previously unsuspected connections between remote areas. Mathematical intuition plays the same active role in theoretical physics except that it is constrained there by the requirement of numerical (experimental) adequacy. The content of a theory consists, therefore, of its numerical predictions and of the form of its equations. The latter may be understood in terms of the group admitted (in Lie's sense) by the equations, and its invariants. Theoretical changes which do not alter either numerical predictions or the form of the theory are inessential. Even essential changes, however, need not be disruptive. Comparability is preserved if, for example, the groups of two apparently rival theories are shown to be subgroups of a third group; such is the case of classical and rela- tivistic mechanics since the Galileo-Newtonian and Lorentzian groups are sub-groups of the affine group, as has been shown by F. Klein. In general, Poincaré's epistemology emphasises the relational nature of knowledge, whether in mathematics or in physics, and the unknowability of objects as such, i.e. apart from their relations to others. It is not equivalent to instrumentalism and might best be Preface xi called structural realism. Since it combines elements of empiricism and rationalism it is a semi-rationalist view. The outlined interpretation of Poincaré's epistemology has the advantage that it does justice to a lot of textual evidence ignored in the traditional interpretation which is in terms of conventionalism to the exclusion of invariantism or structuralism. Moreover, it has immediate implications for the debate over the discovery of special relativity and Poincaré's role in it. Some of the claims made in that debate, for example that owing to his alleged inductivism Poincaré was unable to conceive of a general relativity theory ("general", not in the sense of "general covariance" but in the sense of general principles applicable to more than one specific area of physics), must be seen at once as untenable, to say the least. Poincaré's epis- temology was certainly much more rationalistic than the Machist epistemology of Einstein around 1905. In fact Einstein embraced a semi-rationalist philosophy, similar to Poincaré's, only in his later, post-Machist period. Since the most general concept of relativity theory, in the sense of an invariant theory of most comprehensive groups, was the basic element of the mathematical and philosophical tradition of which Poincaré was a creative member, he was naturally predisposed to apply such mathematical ideas in dealing with the problems in theoretical physics that arose from Michelson-Morley's and related experiments. On the question of Poincaré's role in the discovery of relativity theory, my position (Essay 5) differs both from the established view and Whittaker's controversial claims; it is as follows: the priority for the non-mathematical (experimental) for- mulation of the (special) relativity principle as well as for the state- ment of the limiting and constant velocity of light, are credited to Poincaré; the formulation of the relativity principle in terms of the Lorentz transformations and its mathematical elaboration are claimed to be a case of simultaneous and independent discovery by Poincaré and Einstein, with the latter seeing more clearly the physi- cal implications and Poincaré being superior in the mathematics of the theory (invariants of the Lorentz group, basic ideas of the four-vector formalism, etc.). In the light of what has been said already about the customary narrow interpretation of Poincaré's epistemology, it is not surprising x/7 Preface that its historical background had been seen in a similarly restrictive fashion. Though Maxwell's and Lorentz's theories have figured prominently in the discussions of its origins, little else is usually mentioned and even the role of those two theories is often described in a slanted way. So, for example, Duhem, who was perhaps one of the first to emphasise the role of Maxwell's theory for the genesis of Poincaré's philosophy, saw this role exclusively in the alleged effect of Maxwell's instrumentalist view of (mechanical) models. Poincaré's analysis of the formal analogies between the equations of optics and electricity (in Poincaré's 1895) and his emphasis on their epistemolo- gical importance escaped Duhem's attention. Again, in recent con- tributions to the debate over the discovery of relativity theory, the impact of Lorentz's theory on Poincaré's world-view has been claimed (e.g. by Miller) with little regard for those features of Poincaré's philosophy which are clearly incompatible with Lorentz's realist interpretation of the ether hypothesis and the electromagnetic world view. I felt, therefore, that it was important to draw atten- tion—however unsystematically and tentatively—to those elements of Poincaré's historical background which, though relevant to his philosophy, had been largely ignored. This applies, above all, to the philosophy of the physics of the principles (Lagrange, Poisson, Fourier, Cauchy in France) whose British representative, Hamilton, I also link—hypothetically (perhaps through Larmor and Whit- taker)—with Ramsey (Essay 2). Similarly, though Poincaré wrote only à propos of Joseph Larmor's physical theories, he did pursue in detail Larmor's programme of analysing formal similarities between alternative theories of optics and electricity with important con- sequences for his epistemology (Essays 2 and 5). Gabriel Koenigs's kinematics, based on the theory of transformations, is in itself historically interesting (one of his definitions reads: "Absolute velo- city is the geometrical sum of relative velocity and the velocity of entrainment", where "absolute" and "relative" have "a purely con- ventional sense", 1897, p. 82). Poincaré saw in "Koenigs's theorem", to which he refers repeatedly, the justification of the conventionalist thesis of the multiplicity of theoretical explanations for any set of observational data in mechanics (Essay 5). To my knowledge, this has never been discussed by critics.

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.