SCHOPENHAUER'S BROKEN WORLD-VIEW Science and Philosophy VOLUME 10 Series Editor Nancy 1. Nersessian, Program in Cognitive Science, College ofC omputing, and School of Public Policy, Georgia Institute of Technology, Atlanta Editorial Advisory Board Joseph Agassi, Department ofP hilosophy, York University and Tel Aviv University (Emeritus) Geoffrey Cantor, Department ofP hilosophy, University ofL eeds Nancy Cartwright, Department ofP hilosophy, London School ofE conomics James T. Cushing, Department ofP hysics and Department ofP hilosophy, Notre Dame University Lindley Darden, Committee on the History and Philosophy ofS cience, University ofM aryland Max Dresdent, Institutefor Theoretical Physics, SUNY Stony Brook Allan Franklin, Department ofP hysics, University of Colorado, Boulder Marjorie Grene, Department ofP hilosophy, University ofC alifornia, Davis (Emeritus) Adolf Griinbaum, Department ofP hilosophy, University ofP ittsburgh Richard Lewontin, Museum of Comparative Zoology, Harvard University Thomas Nickles, Department ofP hilosophy, University ofN evada, Reno Dudley Shapere, Department ofP hilosophy, Wake Forest University This series has been established as a forum for contemporary analysis of philosophical problems which arise in connection with the construction of theories in the physical and the biological sciences. Contributions will not place particular emphasis on anyone school of philosophical thought. However, they will reflect the belief that the philosophy of science must be firmly rooted in an examination of actual scientific practice. Thus, the volumes in this series will include or depend significantly upon an analysis of the history of science, recent or past. The Editors welcome contributions from scientists as well as from philosophers and historians of science. The titles published in this series are listed at the end oft his volume. SCHOPENHAUER'S BROKEN WORLD-VIEW Colours and Ethics between Kant and Goethe by PAUL EH. LAUXTERMANN University ofTwente, Enschede, The Netherlands Springer-Science+Business Media, B.V. A C.I.P. Ctalogue record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. ISBN 978-90-481-5566-8 ISBN 978-94-015-9369-4 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-015-9369-4 Printed on acid-free paper All Rights Reserved © 2000 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht Originally published by Kluwer Academic Publishers in 2000. Softcover reprint of the hardcover 1s t edition 2000 No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording or by any information storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner. TABLE OF CONTENTS PREFACE VII INTRODUCTION 1 I KANT, GOETHE, AND THE MECHANIZATION OF THE WORLD-PICTURE 9 a. The mechanization of the world-picture 9 b. Kant and Goethe 18 c. The legacy of Kant and Goethe, and how Schopenhauer received it 27 II FIVE DECISIVE YEARS 41 III COLOURS 53 a. Goethe 53 b. Goethe and Schopenhauer 64 c. Schopenhauer 65 d. Schopenhauer and Goethe 73 IV THE ANTINOMY: CAN THE WORLD BE IN My HEAD, YET My HEAD BE IN 83 THE WORLD? a. Schopenhauer and Kant 83 b. Schopenhauer's physiological epistemology: analysis 91 c. Schopenhauer's physiological epistemology: assessment 94 d. The big question: is the world my representation? 103 e. Conclusions. Schopenhauer and Goethe once again 110 V BIEN ETONNES: HEGEL AND SCHOPENHAUER As PARTISANS OF 117 GOETHE'S THEORY OF COLOURS a. Goethe and Hegel 117 b. Hegel and Schopenhauer as positivist metaphysicians 120 c. Goethe, Kant, Schopenhauer, Hegel, and history 127 VI ETHICS 135 a. Introduction: are there two Kants? 135 b. Kant's moral philosophy 142 c. Schopenhauer's moral philosophy 149 d. Some incidental reflections on the present-day significance of Kant's 158 and Schopenhauer's moral philosophies VII ETHICS AND METAPHYSICS 165 a. Kant's and Schopenhauer's moral philosophies: a critical comparison 165 b. The metaphysical background to Kant's and Schopenhauer's moral 176 philosophies, and its consequences for the problem of freedom VIII THE PARADOX: CAN GOD COMMIT SUICIDE? 197 a. Schopenhauer's great doctrine: Will as Thing-in-itself 197 b. An unrecognized antinomy, and the paradox that results 199 c. Schopenhauer and Buddhism 207 d. Schopenhauer as a precursor of Einstein ... 210 VI e .... or of Freud? 217 f. Schopenhauer's broken world-view: his professed, and his hidden 222 metaphysics IX IN PRAISE OF REALISM 231 a. Schopenhauer's reception after 1848 231 b. Schopenhauer's philosophy and the mechanization-cum-aestheticization 236 of the world-picture c. Schopenhauer's broken world-view: colours and ethics between Kant 249 and Goethe ENDNOTES 261 INDEX 283 PREFACE Why care about Schopenhauer, and (if one does) what is there to say about him that has not been said already? The principal thesis of the present book is that a major, unresolved question about Schopenhauer's work still remains. To anticipate the issue towards which a fairly lengthy argument is to carry us, we shall seek to show that its numerous contradictions compel us to ask in the end: 'What, after all, is here meant to be the real 'Thing-in-itself: 'Will', or Nirvana?' Or, to use somewhat less technical language, 'Is, in Schopenhauer's true view, that which transcends all empirical phenomena to be found in what he (rightly or wrongly) calls 'Will' or rather in a human Intellect capable in the end of extinguishing that Will?' To be sure: the sheer fact that Schopenhauer's work is marked by many a contradiction has often ,enough been pointed out by his numerous, less and more recent, on the whole very able commentators. 'His commentators', not himself; on the contrary, he always vehemently denied ever having committed any. But precisely this circumstance presents us with something of a riddle. For Schopenhauer was an extraordinarily acute thinker, who knew how to express himself in literary prose of high standing and a clarity rarely surpassed, and whose utterances about his Idealist contemporaries in German philosophy display a temperamental impatience with muddle-headedness of any kind. Whence, then, those evident contradictions in his own work - contradictions that may be summed up in one fundamental antinomy (which we have dubbed 'can the world be in my head, yet my head be in the world?') and one fundamental paradox (similarly dubbed by us 'can God commit suicide?')? The aim of the present book, in building upon the accomplishments of previous commentators, is to shed some new light on this problem. Its principal thesis has already been suggested by the superficially somewhat naive-looking question raised above. That thesis implies that there are in fact two ultimate principles in Schopenhauer's philosophy and that his, at first sight, beautifully rounded-off system reveals itself at second sight as the secret arena of two conflicting world views. Whence the conflict? Here our first auxiliary thesis is that an inquiry into the origins of the discord brings to light Schopenhauer's grappling in his own unique way with a problem that is still very much with us, to wit: how to acquire a solid grasp of the world at large (the eternal longing of all metaphysicians of all times) in a manner compatible with all that modem science has validly to say about the constitution of our world? This has become such a problem because, ever since the 'mechanization of the world-picture' in the 17th century, modem science may lay claim to valid knowledge of nature without, however, being able to provide a satisfactory world-view all by itself. VIn PREFACE Our second (closely related) auxiliary thesis concerns the intellectual guides under whose joint patronage Schopenhauer's pertinent effort took place. We shall try to show how his critical allegiance to Kant (who drew dualist conclusions in the domains of epistemology and ethics from the birth of modern science) as well as to Goethe (who sought to point out basic shortcomings of modern science from a monist point of view) carried him towards a philosophical vision of the world as enticing as it is problematic. Our programme, then, is to follow Schopenhauer along his chosen road - to fmd out how he interpreted the legacies of Kant and Goethe (sometimes, but always revealingly so, misinterpreting them); what in these legacies he adopted and what he rejected (often portions of one in view of the other); and what doctrines of his own he went on to construct out of them. We shall follow three lines in particular: a. his transformation (in view of what he held to be Kant's epistemology) of Goethe's doctrine on the nature of colours and how his pertinent effort compares with a somewhat similar exercise undertaken by his perennial foe, Hegel; b. his transformation, in the spirit of his own 'Will'-metaphysics, of Kant's ethical doctrine; c. his construction - undertaken in parallel with an improved (or so at least he believed) Kantian epistemology - of an essentially though not explicitly Goethean epistemology, meant to serve as a kind of propaedeutic to the apotheosis of his entire philosophical enterprise: the gospel of the final redemption from the bondage of'Will'. We carry out this programme of ours by blending, in a perhaps unusual sort of way, the history of philosophical currents with history of science, history of ideas generally, and (in order to elucidate relevant portions of Schopenhauer's biography and intellectual and social environment) German history as well. A more detailed exposition of what all this is going to entail follows presently in an introductory chapter. For now, we wish to express our gratitude to the present and former members of the Department of History at the University of Twente: Petra Bruulsema for ever-ready secretarial help, and Christiaan BOUdri, Floris Cohen, Fokko Jan Dijksterhuis, Marius Engelbrecht, the late Casper Hakfoort, Nancy Nersessian, Hans Sparnaay, Tomas Vanheste and Peter Vardy for their vigilant assessment of ideas in the course of our regular ongoing exchanges (Floris Cohen also revised with care the entire typescript, ensured its camera-ready preparation, and came up with the title). Further, Joachim Aul is to be mentioned, with gratitude, for his workmanlike criticisms based on a shared predilection for Schopenhauer, and Helen Ure for carrying out the 'light editing' recommended by a generous referee. Finally, on a more informal level, I gladly avail myself of the opportunity to thank, above all, Brigitte Mazohl for many stimulating conversations in the course of long years of unabated friendship; among other names that might be mentioned I choose those of Ralph Melville and Claus Scharf PREFACE IX (of the Institut filr europ!lische Geschichte in Mainz) for their lively interest in the author's scholarly development. Quotations are given in English in the main text; unless mentioned otherwise, the translations are all ours. If the text quoted is a translation of an original text in German or French, the latter is given in a footnote. The footnotes also offer substantial excursions beyond the course of our argument, whereas references to pertinent sources and to the literature are provided in the endnotes. INTRODUCTION Bertrand Russell, in the Schopenhauer chapter of his well-known History of . Western Philosophy, charges the protagonist of the present book - apart from a list of other un-British vices like habitually dining well - with having been "extremely quarrelsome". I And so much is certain that Arthur Schopenhauer was a philosopher with a remarkable propensity for being provoked to anger. For example, when a certain Adolph Cornill published a book on his philosophy which seemed to have been written with the specific aim of showing up an impressive number of contradictions inherent in it, Schopenhauer's reaction was as one might expect. In a letter to his faithful 'evangelist' Frauenstiidt of 11 July 1856 he castigated such an attempt as "a stupid, bad trick, such as is often used by knaves", and which was especially ludicrous "with me, the most consistent and monolithic of all philosophers,,:2 And in a letter of 31 March 1854 to the 'apostle' Johann August Becker we read (this time about worthy old Frauenstiidt himself1): "To seek for contradictions in my work is wholly in vain; it is all of a piece."P Cornill's book has fallen into, probably well-deserved, oblivion; but, in spite of the master's warning, commentators have continued (unless they belong to some Schopenhauer-orthodoxy) to be puzzled, rightly or wrongly, by the same phenomenon. This is true not only of such rather unsympathetic commentators as Bertrand Russell, who naturally did not fail in his tum to point out inconsistencies, and who went on to sum up his judgment in the verdict that "Schopenhauer's gospel of resignation is not very consistent nor very sincere".4 It is also true of those who were impressed by the fact that under Schopenhauer's hands, out of such heterogeneous and sometimes (at least apparently) contradictory elements such a philosophically as well as artistically beautiful edifice could have arisen. This kind of commentary tended to show admiration for the wide range of philosophical topics and currents that came together in Schopenhauer's mind rather than to scorn its alleged shallowness (which then should have expressed itself in the 'contradictions' which, mirabile dictu, Schopenhauer had not even noticed himself); and they sought to determine the nature and origins of the varied contributions to the great symphony with which Schopenhauer's system strikingly has been compared.5 Such a search brought his first biographer, Wilhelm Gwinner, to the conclusion that "it was Schopenhauer's vocation to complement not only the physical realism of the sensualists but also the aesthetic realism of Goethe with the • " ... ein dummer, schlechter Kunstgriff, dessen sich die Lumpe oft bedienen"; " ... bei mir, dem konsequentesten und einheitlichsten aller Philosophen". t "Bei mir Widersprilche zu suchen ist ganz eitel: Alles ist aus einem GuB."