ebook img

Schelling’s theory of symbolic language : forming the system of identity PDF

276 Pages·2014·1.322 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Schelling’s theory of symbolic language : forming the system of identity

OXFORD THEOLOGY AND RELIGION MONOGRAPHS EditorialCommittee j. barton m. j. edwards p. s. fiddes g. d. flood d. n. j. macculloch c. c. rowland OXFORDTHEOLOGYANDRELIGIONMONOGRAPHS PAULTILLICHANDTHEPOSSIBILITYOFREVELATIONTHROUGHFILM JonathanBrant(2012) HINDUTHEOLOGYANDBIOLOGY TheBhāgavataPuraaandContemporaryTheory JonathanB.Edelmann(2012) ETHNICITYANDTHEMIXEDMARRIAGECRISISINEZRA9–10 AnAnthropologicalApproach KatherineE.Southwood(2012) DIVINEPRODUCTIONINLATEMEDIEVALTRINITARIANTHEOLOGY HenryofGhent,DunsScotus,andWilliamOckham JTPaasch(2012) THESALVATIONOFATHEISTSANDCATHOLICDOGMATICTHEOLOGY StephenBullivant(2012) COMEDYANDFEMINISTINTERPRETATIONOFTHEHEBREWBIBLE ASubversiveCollaboration MelissaA.Jackson(2012) THESTORYOFISRAELINTHEBOOKOFQOHELET EcclesiastesasCulturalMemory JennieBarbour(2012) THEANTI-PELAGIANCHRISTOLOGYOFAUGUSTINEOFHIPPO,396–430 DominicKeech(2012) VISIONARYRELIGIONANDRADICALISMINEARLYINDUSTRIALENGLAND FromSouthcotttoSocialism PhilipLockley(2012) REPENTANCEINLATEANTIQUITY EasternAsceticismandtheFramingoftheChristianLifec.400–650CE AlexisC.Torrance(2012) ’ Schelling s Theory of Symbolic Language Forming the System of Identity DANIEL WHISTLER 1 3 GreatClarendonStreet,Oxford,OX26DP, UnitedKingdom OxfordUniversityPressisadepartmentoftheUniversityofOxford. ItfurtherstheUniversity’sobjectiveofexcellenceinresearch,scholarship, andeducationbypublishingworldwide.Oxfordisaregisteredtrademarkof OxfordUniversityPressintheUKandincertainothercountries #DanielWhistler2013 Themoralrightsoftheauthorhavebeenasserted FirstEditionpublishedin2013 Impression:1 Allrightsreserved.Nopartofthispublicationmaybereproduced,storedin aretrievalsystem,ortransmitted,inanyformorbyanymeans,withoutthe priorpermissioninwritingofOxfordUniversityPress,orasexpresslypermitted bylaw,bylicenceorundertermsagreedwiththeappropriatereprographics rightsorganization.Enquiriesconcerningreproductionoutsidethescopeofthe aboveshouldbesenttotheRightsDepartment,OxfordUniversityPress,atthe addressabove Youmustnotcirculatethisworkinanyotherform andyoumustimposethissameconditiononanyacquirer BritishLibraryCataloguinginPublicationData Dataavailable ISBN 978–0–19–967373–5 PrintedinGreatBritainby theMPGPrintgroup,UK LinkstothirdpartywebsitesareprovidedbyOxfordingoodfaithand forinformationonly.Oxforddisclaimsanyresponsibilityforthematerials containedinanythirdpartywebsitereferencedinthiswork. Preface F.W.J.Schelling’sconstructionofsymboliclanguagein}73ofhisPhilosophie der Kunst sheds much-needed light on both the history of the emergence of thesymbolintheGoethezeitandSchelling’sownphilosophicalpracticeofthe time.1Suchisthethesisdefendedinthisbook.Asmyargumentprogresses,it willbecomeclearthatboththepeculiartheoryoflanguageSchellinglaysout in}73andthedistinctivemannerinwhichhesolaysitoutcontributetoanew idealofsystematization.Myargumentthereforeneedstobesituatedinterms of two critical debates: first, historical reconstructions of the symbol; second, philosophicalreconstructionsofSchelling’sproject. The fate of the symbol in the twentieth century has been far from propi- tious. In Musil’s Der Mann ohne Eigenschaften, for instance, the legacy of ‘the romantic symbol’2 is characterized as follows by Ulrich, the novel’s protagonist: What they meant by ‘symbol’ was the great images of grace, which made everything that is confused and dwarfed in life...clear and great, images that suppress the noise of the senses and dip the forehead into the stream of tran- scendence. Such symbols were the Isenheim Altar, the Egyptian pyramids, and Novalis...But they did not state, in so many words, what a symbol was: first, becauseasymbolcannotbeexpressedinsomanywords;second,becauseAryans donotdealindryformulas,whichiswhytheyachievedonlyapproximationsof symbols during the last century; and third, because some centuries only rarely produce the transcendent moment of grace in the transcendent human being. (Musil1995,338) Ulrich’s reflections on the nationalist and racist appropriation of the idea of the symbol act out our post-Romantic unease over the concept. It is a mysterious means of accessing the transcendent, a way of escaping this worldintoanother-worldlyrealmofperfection;itisineffableandsoescapes rational criticism; it is bestowed upon a few world-historical individuals, thereby feeding into early twentieth-century fascistic and proto-fascistic dis- course.Theimplicationisnotjustthatthesymbolisaconservativerelicfrom 1 I use the underdetermined term, Goethezeit, to describe this period of German thought, since the labels ‘Idealism’, ‘Romanticism’, and ‘Classicism’ all suggest an artificial separation betweenSchellingand(forinstance)GoetheorA.W.Schlegel. 2 AsIwillmakeclearinChapter1,Iplacequotationmarksaround‘romantic’inthiscontext toindicatethefactthatforthemostparttheRomanticswerenotinvolvedinthedevelopmentof thesymbol. vi Preface areactionaryera;itisalsopernicious—boththeoreticallyandpolitically.Such isthelegacyofthesymbolinthetwentiethcentury. Inwhatfollows,Imakethecaseforafreshrecoveryofthesymbol.Weneed tore-attendtotheemergenceofthesymbolinGoethezeitGermanytouncover thediversityatitsroot.Notalltheoriesofthesymbolpossessedtheproperties listed above, not all theories of the symbol could be appropriated by the political worldview Ulrich intimates. In fact, during the first few years of the nineteenthcenturythesymbolwasasiteofexperimentation:itwastheorized and re-theorized in radically conflicting ways for radically different ends. What we remember as the monolithic ‘romantic’ symboldid not exist; it isa fiction instituted by our cultural memory at the expense of divergent, even antitheticalformulationsofthesymbol. Isetaboutprovisionallydemonstratingtheseclaims byfocusingonSchel- ling’s theory of symbolic language. Schelling’s theory is suited to this role because it has been so carelessly treated in the past by both historians of the symbol and Schelling scholars alike. Schelling is consistently (and falsely) taken to be a proponent of ‘the romantic symbol’—and a particularly poor proponentatthat.Indeed,itisrarethattheSchellingiansymbolismentioned without accompanying accusations of plagiarism or, at least, unoriginality. Yet,astudyoftheplaceofthesymbol(and,inparticular,symboliclanguage) in his philosophical system of the time (the Identitätssystem) very quickly reveals its irreducible difference from traditional accounts of the symbol. Schellingian symbolic language is distinctive—peculiar, even—and this puts into question any unitary account of ‘the romantic symbol’ and its develop- ment.Schelling’stheoryisillustrativeofthemultipleexperimentsundertaken inthenameofthesymbolinthefirstfewyearsofthenineteenthcentury. The second critical debate in which this book intervenes concerns inter- pretations of Schelling’s philosophy, for my concentration on Schelling’s theory of symbolic language is not merely for the sake of historical accounts ofthesymbolalone,butisalsointendedasaway-intoSchelling’sphilosoph- ical system. This book is, therefore, an attempt to reconstruct Schelling’s philosophy of the time, the Identitätssystem, by means of a focus on the role the symbol plays therein. This period of Schelling’s philosophical output has beenseriouslyneglectedoverthelastthirtyyearsandstandsinneedofcritical attention. To begin to remedy this situation, I provide a detailed reconstruc- tionofthesystemwhichSchellingdevelopedinhiswritingsbetween1801and 1805. Moreover, I go on to argue that the concept of symbolic language illuminates Schelling’s metaphilosophical practice. Unlike Hegel, Fichte, and Maimon, Schelling is often reticent about what he is doing when he writes philosophy; the concept of symbolic language, however, sheds light on this underexploredareaofSchelling’sthoughtbydrawingattentiontohisconcep- tionoftheworkdonebythewordsonthepageofaphilosophytextinforming asystem. Preface vii The contribution that an analysis of }73 of the Philosophie der Kunst can make to these two critical debates (understanding the history of the symbol andunderstandingSchelling’sIdentitätssystem)explainswhyIplacesomuch emphasis in what follows on this short, unassuming paragraph from a set of posthumously published lecture notes. When read in the context of the emergence of the symbol and the monistic rigour of the Identitätssystem, }73 of the Philosophie der Kunst is a hidden gem in Schelling’s output. And whileoneshouldnotmaketoomuchofit(itis,afterall,sketchyondetailsand sometimescarelesslyphrased),Ihopethatbytheendofthebookreaderswill agreethatitdeservesthecentralpositionIhavegivenit. Over the course of the book, I approach Schelling’s construction of symbolic language in }73 of his Philosophie der Kunst in three ways. First, I compare Schellingiansymboliclanguagetoothercontemporarytheoriesofthesymbol andlanguage(inparticular,thoseofGoethe,Kant,andA.W.Schlegel).While Schelling’s theory of symbolic language possesses properties similar to these othertheories(theidentityofbeingandmeaning,organicwholeness,theco- existence of opposites), I show that it differs in how those properties are interpreted. Second, I excavate the metaphysical and epistemological prin- ciplesfromSchelling’sphilosophyoftheperiodwhichunderliethistheoryof language.ThreetenetsfromtheIdentitätssystemarecrucial:formation,quan- titativedifferentiation,andconstruction.TheyilluminatewhySchellinginter- prets symbolic language very differently to his contemporaries. Third, I consider the metaphilosophical significance of Schellingian symbolic lan- guage.Thissignificanceistwofold.First,histheorygivesrisetoaconception of discourse without reference, and so to the notion of a science without reference.3 On this basis, Schelling criticizes current practices of science for remaining too concerned with referring to reality, when what is at stake is ratherthedegreeofintensitytowhichtheyproducereality.Sciencetherefore stands in need of reformation. Second, the way in which the science of theology(inparticular)isutilizedbySchellinginordertoconstructsymbolic language in }73 of the Philosophie der Kunst itself provides a model for reformed scientific practice. I argue that Schelling conceives of the sciences asmaterialforintensifyingtheproductionofreality.Inthisway,anabsolute systemisengenderedwhichhasnoconcernforreferenceorfortheintegrityof particularscientificpursuits. Part I of the book therefore focuses on other theories of language and the symbol formulated in the years leading up to Schelling’s construction of symbolic language in late 1802. Chapter1 considers Kant, Goethe, and A. W. Schlegel’s theories of the symbol, so as to delineate an interpretation 3 ‘Science’ is here used to refer to any knowledge-orientated discourse, in line with the GermanWissenschaft. viii Preface ofthisconceptwhichwasdominantthenandsince(whatIcall,the‘romantic’ interpretation)againstwhichSchellingvehementlyreacts.InChapter2,Iturn to the other element of symbolic language—language—and I outline the various traditions of linguistic thought which provide the context for Schel- ling’sconstruction.Forthemostpartmyfocusrestsonotheraccountsof(or failurestoaccountfor)symboliclanguageintheGoethezeit.4 In Part II, I examine Schelling’s Identitätssystem, and so the metaphysical and epistemological principles underlying his construction of symbolic lan- guage. Chapter3 provides a brief introduction to the Identitätssystem. Chapter4looksindetailatitsmetaphysicalfoundationsbyrehearsingSchel- ling’sanswertothefundamentalmetaphysicalquestion,‘inwhatdoesreality consist?’Chapter5concentratesonamuch-neglectedbutcentraltenetofthe Identitätssystem—quantitative differentiation. I use quantitative differenti- ation to elucidate the doctrine of the potencies (the Potenzlehre). In Chapter6, I turn to Schellingian epistemology and in particular his notion ofconstruction. Part III explores the key sections from the Philosophie der Kunst in which Schellingconstructsfirstthesymbolingeneralandsecondsymboliclanguage inparticular.Chapter7isadetailedcommentaryon}39ofthePhilosophieder Kunst where Schelling constructs his notion of the symbol; I show how he subvertsandmutatesprevioustheoriesofthesymbol.InChapter8,Iturnto someofthemoregeneralquestionsconcerningthestatusandroleoflanguage in Schelling’s Identitätssystem. This chapter is preliminary to my more sus- tained engagement with Schellingian symbolic language in Chapter9. Chapter9 itself is another detailed commentary, this time on }73 of the Philosophie der Kunst. I bring all the preceding arguments to bear in an attempt to fully describe the meaning, role, and significance of the construc- tionofsymboliclanguage. Part IV argues for the metaphilosophical import of this construction. In Chapter10, I draw some general conclusions from Schelling’s philosophy of language and transpose them into the domain of systematic practice. Employing the example of the science of theology in particular, I argue that (a) Schelling’s views on language compel him to critique theology both past and present and consequently (b) Schelling sets about reforming theology (andsoscienceingeneral).Finally,Chapter11takesupthemetaphilosophical 4 Itisworthpointingoutatthispointalacunainmyargument.IdonotdiscussColeridge’s theoryofthesymbol,forexample,orHumboldt’stheoryoflanguage,norinPartIIdoIconsider Hegel’scriticismsofSchelling’sIdentitätssysteminanydetail.Infact,philosophical,theological, andlinguisticdevelopmentsafter1805arenotdiscussedhereatall.Thereadermayfindthisa somewhat frustrating lack, since the question ‘how does this relate to X?’ seems extremely pressingatmanypoints.However,understandingSchelling’sownthought(andthesourceson whichhedrew)istheprimeobjectiveofmyargument,ratherthancomplexcomparisonswith laterthought. Preface ix significance of Schellingian symbolic language from another perspective, concentrating on a specific strategy Schelling practises to make scientific language symbolic: systematic eclecticism. All scientific forms are materials tobeplunderedintheformationofthesystemofidentity. WearelivingthroughaSchellingrenaissance.MarkusGabriel,IainHamilton Grant, Joseph Lawrence, Bruce Matthews, Sean McGrath, Dalia Nassar, and JasonWirth,among others,arerevivinghislegacyand,insodoing,building ontheground-breakingwritingsofadecadeago(byBowie,Courtine,Fisch- bach,Frank,Hogrebe,Vater,andŽižek).Thisbookisthoroughlyindebtedto such innovative Schelling scholarship, even if I take issue with the continual andpathologicalneglectoftheIdentitätssystem.Indeed,onehastolookback to Hermann Zeltner or Klaus Düsing’s work from the 1970s to find the last focusedreconstructionofthisstageofSchelling’sphilosophy. The arguments which follow were forged in conversation with numerous teachers, friends, and colleagues: Pamela Sue Anderson, Jenny Bunker, Nick Bunin,MichaelBurns,JamesCarter,KirillChepurin,RoccoGangle,Douglas Hedley, Tobias Hübner, Judith Kahl, A. W. Moore, Karin Nisenbaum, Joel Rasmussen, Anthony Paul Smith, Sebastian Stein, and Johannes Zachhuber. Crucial to its genesis was the funding of the Arts and Humanities Research Council and the support (in very different ways) of my family, colleagues at the University of Liverpool, support staff at the University of Oxford, Diar- maid MacCulloch, Tom Perridge, and Elizabeth Robottom. Nick Adams’ comments on a draft manuscript were extraordinarily helpful. Most of all, thepatience,attention,andadviceofGeorgePattisonmadeitallpossible.Iam extremely grateful for his wisdom. This book is dedicated to Jenny, sine qua non.

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.