Rousseau and the Ethics of Virtue James Delaney Continuum Rousseau and the Ethics of Virtue Continuum Studies in Philosophy Justin Skirry, Descartes and the Metaphysics of Human Nature David A. Roberts, Kierkegaard's Analysis of Radical Evil Dale Wilkerson, Nietzsche and the Greeks Matthew Simpson, Rousseau's Theory of Freedom Llyod Strickland, Leibniz Reinterpreted: The Harmony of Things Carlos Garcia, Popper's Theory of Science David Roberts, Dialect of Romanticism Andrew Fiala, Tolerance and the Ethical Life Rousseau and the Ethics of Virtue James Delaney continuum Continuum International Publishing Group The Tower Building 80 Maiden Lane 11 York Road Suite 704 London New York SE1 7NX NY 10038 © James Delaney 2006 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or any information storage or retrieval system, without prior permission in writing from the publishers. James Delaney has asserted his right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identified as Author of this work. British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library. ISBN: 0826487246 (hardback) Library of Congress Cataloguing-in-Publication Data A catalog record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. Typeset by BookEns Ltd, Royston, Herts. Printed and bound in Great Britain by Biddies Ltd, Kings Lynn, Norfolk Contents Acknowledgements vii Introduction 1 1 Virtue Ethics Past and Present 7 2 Virtue and the State of Nature 41 3 Virtue as the Cultivation of the Individual 73 4 The Virtuous Citizen and Rousseau's Political Philosophy 103 5 Toward a Rousseauian Theory of Virtue 129 Bibliography 157 Index 163 Acknowledgements After reading Jean-Jacques Rousseau's Discourse on the Origin of Inequality for the first time, I was fascinated. As I pursued this fascination further, reading other works and discussing them with others, I realized quickly that there were many who did not share my zeal for his thought. Rousseau's philosophy has been accused of being unsystematic and contradictory. Perhaps because I was so sympathetic to many of his claims, I wanted to take it upon myself to defend him against some of these charges. In at least some small way, I hope this book serves that purpose. There are so many people whose support and help were invaluable to me in undertaking this project. I owe a great deal to my professors in the philosophy departments at Xavier University and SUNY Buffalo for their guidance and patience. I thank my colleagues at Niagara University for their day-to-day encouragement. I also thank my many students who continue to bring energy, creativity and enthusiasm to the study of philosophy. I must mention by name three people who read earlier drafts of the chapters and whose comments were so incredibly helpful to me. My deepest thanks go to Jeffrey Dueck, Kevin Klipfel and Kenneth Shockley. Finally, I thank my wife Sarah for her constant love and support, and S. Miles Grey, to whom this work is dedicated. Introduction This book is partly a work on the philosophy of Jean-Jacques Rousseau and partly a study of the ethical theory commonly referred to as 'virtue ethics'. My hope is that bringing these two very different subjects together will serve to say something original about both of them. Given their somewhat distinct natures, I think it will be helpful to the reader for me to begin by giving a brief introduction: to Rousseau, to virtue ethics, and to the subjects of the five chapters that follow. Rousseau was one of the most influential, as well as enigmatic, thinkers during the famous Enlightenment period of eighteenth- century France. Originally born in Geneva in 1712, Rousseau had a troubled youth. His mother died only a few days after his birth, and his father fled Geneva leaving Rousseau with an uncle when he was still only a child. After an unpleasant stint as an apprentice to an engraver as a teenager, Rousseau left Geneva and eventually settled in France. One of his great loves was music, and in 1742 he went to Paris to become a musician and composer. It was shortly after this that Rousseau became acquainted with several other famous French Enlightenment thinkers, among them, d'Alembert and Diderot. Shortly thereafter, he began his own philosophical career. In 1750, Rousseau published his first major philosophical treatise, the Discourse on the Sciences and Arts. This work, as well as later ones such as the Discourse on the Origin of Inequality, were widely read but also raised much controversy. One reason for this is that it is difficult to say whether Rousseau is properly classified as a participant in the Enlightenment project or a critic of it. The Enlightenment project prided itself on progress. Building on the advances that had been made in metaphysics and science in the modern period, beginning in the sixteenth century, the Enlightenment project consisted in 2 Rousseau and the Ethics of Virtue large part in applying the same methods to topics in ethics and sociopolitical philosophy. Perhaps there is no greater example of such a project than as it is expressed in the work of Voltaire, who advocated the progression of the sciences and arts with great zeal. It's not at all surprising that Voltaire was one of Rousseau's most outspoken critics. For Rousseau, while he shared some of the Enlightenment project's ideals, also claimed that far from improving life, society, and this supposed 'progress', had actually done more to hurt humanity than to help it. Hence, it is difficult to classify his philosophy: is he an Enlightenment thinker or a counter-Enlight- enment thinker? There is still debate about this among contempor- ary scholars just as there was during Rousseau's own time. Rousseau's public life was certainly marked by conflict and controversy, but his private life was even more tumultuous. He feuded with friends and acquaintances throughout his life, which led to fallouts with Diderot and David Hume among others. Rousseau himself argues that these feuds were the result of people who, either because of jealousy or unjustified contempt, had conspired against him. When we look back at Rousseau's writings, we are left with many puzzles and seeming contradictions. Part of the task that I undertake in this book is to offer something in the way of solutions to some of these puzzles, and clarifications of some of these apparent contradictions. Though it may be subtle, one observes the theme of virtue arising again and again in Rousseau's major works. This I will argue is no accident, and although the ways in which Rousseau uses the term vary in some cases from text to text, there is a common thread that runs through them: one that I hope to articulate in this book. To put it another way, I hope to show that Rousseau's ethical thought is best understood as an ethics of virtue. And this leads us to the second major subject of this book: virtue ethics. Virtue ethics is usually regarded among philosophers, along with deontology and consequentialism, as one of three major competing ethical theories. Very often these theories are associated with their most famous advocates in the history of philosophy. When one thinks of deontology, one usually thinks of the moral philosophy of another famous Enlightenment philosopher, Imma- Introduction 3 nuel Kant (1724—1804). Consequentialism is expressed in the respective utilitarian positions of Jeremy Bentham (1748—1832) and John Stuart Mill (1806—73). These philosophers, it should be noted, lived relatively recently in terms of the Western philosophical tradition. By contrast, the most famous advocate of virtue ethics is Aristotle (384-322 BC). Aristotle's ethics was part of an all- encompassing philosophical system that was the established school of thought when the modern period began. Aristotle's science, particularly his teleological metaphysics, was being discarded in the modern period and was replaced by mechanistic views such as those of Descartes and Hobbes. Enlight- enment thinkers, and those who followed, attempted to formulate ethical systems that would replace Aristotle's ethics in the same way. But more recently, beginning in large part with G. E. M. Anscombe's 1958 article, 'Modern Moral Philosophy', virtue ethics enjoyed a revival. One of the major issues that this revival raised was the possibility of salvaging a basic Aristotelian framework in ethics without accepting a full-blown Aristotelian physics that would fly in the face of modern science. As Rousseau is a key figure in the Enlightenment, I contend that his writings must be examined if we are to understand the tradition of virtue ethics, from its beginnings in the ancient period to the present. Furthermore, since I will argue that Rousseau's ethical thought is best understood as a system of virtue ethics, pulling these two subjects together is a worthwhile project. The book will proceed in five chapters. Chapter One, 'Virtue Ethics Past and Present', presents a very general overview of Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics. Aristotle's ethics begins with the fundamental claim that human beings have a natural end for which they are intended, an end that we all agree is 'happiness'. But while we all agree that happiness is the goal for which we are all striving, there is great disagreement as to what precisely happiness is. Ultimately, Aristotle will argue that happiness is achieved only when one exhibits virtues, or excellences, in the performance of his or her natural function. Some of these virtues are intellectual, such as contemplative and practical wisdom. Others, such as temper- ance, courage and proper anger, are moral virtues. It is only by
Description: