Rhetorical Ethics in the Comedy of Aristophanes A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF UNIVERSITY OF MINNESOTA BY Sean William Larson IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY Advisor: Edward Schiappa May 2014 © Sean William Larson 2014 i Acknowledgments A dissertation draws influence from a myriad of individuals, without whom my analysis and arguments would have been less scholarly, critical, and focused. I am deeply indebted to everyone who has provided instruction or support since I became interested in the mechanics of language and persuasion, from my earliest Latin and Greek classes to the final revisions to the dissertation itself. This project benefited significantly from the efforts and support of my dissertation committee. Ed Schiappa is everything one could ask for in an advisor and more. From the pragmatics of wading into professional academia to the challenges of presenting interdisciplinary research in rhetorical and classical studies, Ed has consistently guided my understanding of the ancient world and how scholars can continue to bring insight into its modern counterpart. From my first course with him on classical rhetoric to the later versions of the dissertation, Richard Graff immediately notices the key issues of an argument and calls attention to how they fit within the current state of scholarship in our field. My analysis and willingness to engage other scholars is a direct result of his efforts. Art Walzer poses the kind of challenging questions that make graduate students blanch, but that ultimately transform them into scholars who can contribute effectively to rhetorical studies. There is no professor I enjoy sparring with more than he! Ron Greene does not research the ancient world, but he is precisely the audience I hope to address in future studies. His focus on the larger issues posed by Aristophanes and what they mean for our understanding of modern rhetoric and ethical citizenship were an invaluable contribution to the project, and a model of how to position and frame future arguments. I would also like to thank faculty and friends who did not serve on my committee for their support leading up to and during the dissertation. Professors Karlyn Kohrs Campbell, Kirt Wilson, and Mary Vavrus provided key guidance as department chair and directors of graduate study. Bea Dehler and Joan Lund were a consistent source of information on policy, keeping the graduate students informed on department changes, and kept my studies funded long enough to span 2 M.A.’s and a Ph.D. Lastly, I would like to thank friends and colleagues who provoked discussion, offered moral support, challenged ideas, and also worked to refine my approach as a scholar. On the rhetorical studies side, I am forever grateful to Kevin Haebeom Vollmers, Tim Behme, Martin Lang, Mariko Izumi, Stacy Fitzpatrick, Peter Gregg, Kristen Swenson, Aric Putnam, and Chani Marchiselli. I must also thank Jim Hamm, Heather Woods, and Christy Marquis for being the definition of collegial as we slogged through the philological trenches. Much gratitude goes out to Jennifer Willis-Rivera, Grace Coggio, Robin Murray, and the other faculty at the University of Wisconsin, River Falls for consistently keeping me balanced between teaching and scholarship. It would be remiss not to mention the outstanding faculty in the department of Classical and Near Eastern Studies, without whom my ability to engage texts in Latin and Greek, along with a corresponding sense of historical context for the ancient world, ii would never have developed fully. In many ways Doug Olson was the classics counterpart to Ed Schiappa, providing candid advice about conference presentations, argument construction, developing a keen eye for textual evidence, and being as skilled a philologist as possible. He was the first to kindle my appreciation for Aristophanes and to show that comedy can be a profound rhetorical force. Doug was a true mentor and educator, whom I have used as the model for leading discussions and constructing assignments in my own courses. Betty Belfiore cultivated an affection not only for ancient philosophy but tragedy as well. My attention to drama as moralizing speech and the ability for narrative arguments to influence audiences is a result of her valued instruction. George Sheets conveyed the importance of text transmission and the weight of intertextuality, demonstrating that texts are deeply connected from one author to another. As the professor of both Greek and Latin composition, my language skills improved markedly with his teaching. Chris Nappa was another challenging presence, cutting to the quick of an argument so that any gaps or weakness would be addressed effectively and quickly. His presence in and out of the classroom was the kind of rare support that few professors can provide, especially when preparing for philological audiences. Steve Smith was a formative influence on my understanding not only on Latin as a language, but also how to teach it effectively. He was often a calming presence during the more intensive points of the semester. Finally I would like to thank the office staff of Barbara Lehnhoff and Victoria Keller, for keeping the department running smoothly, putting out the occasional brushfire, and making sure graduate students such as myself were well funded. It is important to acknowledge the wonderful faculty at Truman State University for setting me along this path many years ago. David Christiansen, Clifton Kreps, Rebecca Harrison, Bridget Thomas, and Alex Tetlak were the bedrock of my introduction to classics. Janet Davis and Kevin Minch then opened my eyes to the worlds of rhetoric and argumentation. This dissertation could not have been written without their friendship and world class instruction. Finally, I would like to thank my family for their unwavering support throughout the years. My parents, Alex and Martha Larson, encouraged me to pursue a budding interest in language from the humble beginnings of my first Latin classes all the way to the completion of graduate school. I hope they can read this project with pride. Last but certainly not least, Ginny Windels was also one of the more crucial factors in the completion of this dissertation. As wife, confidante, and editor, you are as much the author of this project as I. I hope it lives up to your exacting standards, and am forever grateful for your love, humor, and support. iii Dedication This dissertation is dedicated to my parents, Alex and Martha Larson, for showing me the value of curiosity and pursuing knowledge. iv Table of Contents Chapter 1 Introduction………………………………………………………………………………..1 Performance Culture in 5th c. BCE Athens………………………………………..1 The Politics of Old Comedy………………………………………………………5 The Rhetorical Power of Ridicule………………………………………………..13 Aristophanes as Rhetorical Agent………………………………………………..24 Aristophanes as Stylistic Critic…………………………………………………..29 Aristophanes as Critic of Rhetoric……………………………………………….36 A New Direction: Ethical Arguments in Old Comedy…………………………..47 Old Comedy and Kenneth Burke’s Theory of the Negative……………………..54 Chapter 2 Ethical Considerations of Sophistry in Clouds…………………………………………..72 Introduction………………………………………………………………………73 Old vs. New Education…………………………………………………………..78 The Ethics of Old vs. New Education……………………………………………85 Sophistry in Practice: Pheidippides vs. Strepsiades……………………………...99 Conclusions……………………………………………………………………..109 Chapter 3 Judicial Ethics for Orators and Jurors in Wasps………………………………………..118 Introduction……………………………………………………………………..119 Delusions of Grandeur in the Agōn……………………………………………..131 Philocleon’s Benefits of the Juror Lifestyle……………………………………133 Bdelycleon’s Indictment of Demagogues………………………………………142 Conclusions……………………………………………………………………..151 Chapter 4 Ethical Criticisms of Oratory in Knights……………………………………………….157 Introduction……………………………………………………………………..158 A Desire to be Shameless: Arguments in the First Agōn………………….……163 The Ethics of Inter-Orator Debate……………………………………………...169 Bribery and Political Pandering: Arguments in the Second Agōn……………...173 Conclusions……………………………………………………………………..184 v Chapter 5 Conclusions……………………………………………………………………………..189 Summary of Evidence and Analysis……………………………………………189 Implications of Comedic Oratory……………………………………………....195 Implications for Future Research……………………………………………….198 Bibliography……………………………………………………………………………201 1 Chapter 1 Introduction ô despoinai, deomai toinun humôn touti panu micron, tôn Hellênôn einai me legein hekaton stadiousin ariston. O Mistresses, I ask of you this very small favor, Of all the Greeks that I be the best in speaking by one hundred miles. -Clouds, 429-430 Understanding the role of the comic playwright Aristophanes in the history of persuasive speech and performance is no small task. Rhetoric scholars and classicists often consider his plays testimonial documents for the origins and practice of oratory in the late 5th century BCE in Athens; Clouds in particular is regularly treated as contemporary evidence that the sophists were peddlers of logical snake-oil, teaching unscrupulous students how to take advantage of their fellow citizens purely for selfish ends. This point of emphasis reduces Aristophanes to the role of historical witness without giving him credit for his own acts of social commentary and intellectual contributions to the polis. Other attention is given to Aristophanes as pandering moralist, decrying the outrageous and inimical behaviors corrupting a once prosperous city and its many institutions. This avenue of research routinely minimizes the playwright’s influence because his anti-war plays appear to have little practical effect on Athenian politics, and focuses mainly on institutional critique without solutions for the audience to consider. My purpose in this dissertation is to draw attention to Aristophanes as an ethicist who uses comedy to reorient audience values and behaviors. Using Kenneth Burke’s theory of the hortatory negative, I argue that Aristophanes depicts his characters as abhorrent models for oratorical behavior, suggesting implicitly to the audience via inference that an alternative type of speaker may engage in more ethical oratory and thereby provide more effective and beneficial leadership in the polis. As introduction to my analysis in this chapter, I consider the performance culture and politics of Old Comedy, the rhetorical power and advantage of using ridicule over more traditional persuasive forms, review the scholarship of Aristophanes and his relationship to rhetoric and oratory, present arguments about the ethical character of comedy, and conclude with a discussion of Burke’s theory of the hortatory negative and its relationship to Aristophanes. I. Performance Culture in 5th c. BCE Athens Athenian culture in the late 5th c. BCE was marked by an array of intersecting values and practices, all of which fashioned a keen identity for democratic politics and 2 communal welfare. Male citizens were encouraged to take an active interest and participation in the body politic, serving as soldiers, officials, or members of the voting public. They enjoyed and promoted agonistic competitions throughout society, through such varied fora as the deliberative assembly, which established public policy, or by judging plays in the polis-wide dramatic festivals. At the heart of these contexts lie oratorical performance and a budding understanding of rhetorical theory. Citizens engaged in combative arguments before audiences of their peers to carry influence, decide important issues of the day, and construct a uniquely democratic identity based “upon larger habits of thought, feeling, and imagination” compared with other areas of the ancient Mediterranean world (Halliwell “Audience” 141). These values and the democratic ideology they privileged encouraged citizens to adopt certain practices which would fashion them into a robust, ideal member of the polis. Although a person had to possess the proper birthright in order to be granted the benefits of citizenship, active participation in Athenian culture was equally as important and considered a core behavior for this ideal citizen. The number of citizens exceeded the available positions of leadership within the political infrastructure, so the majority of voting-eligible males would contribute by serving as members of audiences. Legislative debates may have been guided by individual orators, but the audience in attendance would make the final determination over which policies were accepted and rejected. Advocacy in the lawcourts would have been a pointless exercise without juries to provide 3 verdicts to cases. Even the plays performed at dramatic festivals required an audience to give opinions about which production had been the most enjoyable.1 It may seem like a pedestrian act to hoot and holler, boo or clap for a play, but this active participation was heavily encouraged for all citizens. Unlike the other oratorical fora, it was more convenient and manageable for citizens to watch tragedies and comedies because the festival environment was a handy justification to rest from work. The additional attendance also creates a more democratic environment because more of the citizenry is represented in the same place (Cartledge 17). Even the poor of Athens could attend the festivals through the Theoric fund, which provided money for citizens to pay the entrance fee if they could not otherwise afford it. This fund was considered so vital to the democratic process and conception of citizenship, that it “was protected by law: it was a prosecutable offense even to propose changes to the fund” (Goldhill “Audience”67). The Theoric fund was such a hallmark of the festival experience that it persisted well into the 4th c., only being abolished by a Macedonia-supported oligarchy aiming to reduce democratic power (Csapo and Slater 287). Even if they were not trained orators themselves, great value was placed on witnessing a speech performance and rendering a judgment on it.2 One could say that political involvement was an ethical imperative for the Athenian citizen. Oratory served as the object of audience judgment in a wide range of contexts. Apart from the direct speaking situations involving an individual policy, court case, or play, the 1 Goldhill (“Audience” 1997) provides a robust discussion of the roles of citizens at the dramatic festivals, including pre-ritual events and the importance of participation (55ff). 2 Cartledge (1997) presents more detailed information about the wages owed to jurors, indicating again the institutional importance of participating as a witness to oratory at political events (10).
Description: