ebook img

Review of The Idea of Justice, by Amartya Sen. PDF

13 Pages·2011·0.35 MB·English
by  
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Review of The Idea of Justice, by Amartya Sen.

Book Reviews 1251 Individuals may then be not a collection of static their potential in healthy and satisfying ways. preferences, but a collection, in Davis’s view, of This reflects something of an Aristotelian cast of individual capabilities responding to evolution- mind, at least with respect to Sen’s picture of the ary forces. Stated in this way, the individual again structure of human psychology. Whereas utilitar- disperses into multiple selves, leaving the atom- ians tend to focus on preference-satisfaction and istic definition of individuation unsatisfactory. egalitarians typically traffic in arguments about The question then becomes can a self-organized the distribution of resources, Sen operates with individual be recovered? Perhaps not if different a more fully rounded idea of human well-being. capabilities pull individuals in different direc- But, as with other neo-Aristotelians like Alasdair tions. As such, an individual may be pulled by MacIntyre (1984), Sen resists Aristotle’s view that different potential capabilities or different iden- there is a fixed list of human purposes or virtues. tities in different situations leading to trade-offs. Rather, he thinks that justice is to a considerable In this way, Davis makes the link to identity eco- extent about enabling people to develop and fulfill nomics, social issues of race discrimination, and their own capabilities. This means that, although normative analysis. On this last avenue, the point he has strong egalitarian impulses and often is made clear that without a clear notion of the recommends antielitist policies, Sen is strongly individual, or a clear notion of which utility to committed to the idea that human freedom lies favor, policy prescriptions and welfare statements at the core of justice. Despite his antipathy for are deeply complicated. preference-satisfaction as a moral yardstick, he The reading of this text provides the reader resists appeals to externally identified “interests” with a novel look into the philosophy of e conomic that might trump an agent’s sense of his or her constructions and their relationship with recent priorities and purposes (pp. 376–79). developments in behavioral economics. The Sen’s vision of a better world is one in which author clearly demonstrates a depth of reasoning more people have the freedom and wherewithal and care for the subject that should make the text to achieve their best potential, and he thinks that of interest to a broad audience. The most compel- a large part of the task of a theory of justice is to ling portion of the text, however, is often between identify obstacles to realizing that vision—and to the lines. Welfare statements for nonatomistic point the way to their removal. He has two main individuals are wrought with pitfalls and many goals in this book. The first is to provide a syn- constructions of individualism face nonatomism thetic account of arguments about justice that he in the view of Davis. Recognizing this challenge, has been developing over several decades. The how then to move forward? Recent work dem- second is to establish this view as superior to John onstrates that welfare statements can potentially Rawls’s A Theory of Justice, which Sen rightly be made with choice data alone, obviating some judges (pp. 52–53) to be the most important work concerns. Of course, even with this caveat, the on the subject in a generation.1 The two projects ability to parse definitions of individuation and are inextricably linked because many of Sen’s individuals generates an important foundation for major claims are defined as alternatives to—or at understanding the new economics of identity. least against the backdrop of—Rawlsian claims Charles Sprenger that he finds wanting. My own philosophical pri- Stanford University ors and views about justice are closer to Sen’s than they are to Rawls’s, but I nonetheless think that Sen fails on both counts. His arguments against The Idea of Justice. By Amartya Sen. Cambridge: Rawls are less than telling and, given what he has Harvard University Press, Belknap Press, said elsewhere, Sen’s defense of his own account 2009. Pp. xxviii, 467. $22.95, paper. ISBN 978– 0–674–03613–0, cloth; 978–0–674–06047–0, pbk. JEL 2011–0483 1 Rawls originally published A Theory of Justice in 1971, but he had been developing the central ideas in journal articles for over a decade before that. He con- Amartya Sen’s vision of justice is agreeably tinued refining—and indeed revising—them in articles humane. He sees people as developmental crea- and lectures, leading to the publication of a substantially tures whose well-being depends on achieving revamped second and final edition in 1999. 07_BookReviews494.indd 1251 11/22/11 4:12 PM 1252 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XLIX (December 2011) of justice is surprisingly undeveloped in The Idea theorists like John Locke had construed political of Justice. institutions as the result of a foundational agree- Sen has long—and rightly in my view—been ment made by people in order to protect natural concerned to get political theorists to focus on rights that were believed to be rooted in natural important questions of justice in the real world. law. Individuals were seen as having abandoned Part of why he resists what he describes as Rawls’s the state of nature to avoid the costs of protect- “search for transcendental justice” (p. 101) is that ing those rights themselves, thereby enhancing it can divert attention to difficult (perhaps unan- their freedom and security. Rawls was writing in swerable) questions that are irrelevant to identi- a different age, when agreement on the existence fying severe injustices and deciding what to do of natural law and natural rights could no longer about them. He captured this vividly in a lecture be assumed and in which decades of mordant (Sen 2009) with the pithy image of a man locked criticism had dispatched the idea of a prepoliti- in an unbearably hot sauna who calls urgently to cal state of nature from serious consideration by a friend outside to lower the temperature, but theorists of justice. elicits the response that he must be told the ideal Rawls’s Kant-inspired move was intended to temperature before acting on the request. A neo- revive the social contract tradition while eliding phyte might wonder whether Sen was making a these well-known difficulties. Conceding that point about poor judgment in choice of friends, there had never been a social contract, he none- but anyone who has been raised on the steady diet theless asked what contract people might buy into of abstruse meta-debates, thought experiments, if they were in a position to do so. And, rather and contrived examples that make up so much than prepolitical people, he asked actual peo- professional political philosophy will know what ple—his readers—to consider what they thought he was getting at. people would choose behind a veil of ignorance This review mirrors the geography of Sen’s that shielded them from knowledge of their age, book. I start with his critique of transcendental sex, race, IQ, physical prowess, aspirations, and political theory and the comparative approach other specific facts that would allow them to bias that he proposes in its stead. I contend that he things in their favor. Stripped of such knowledge, overstates his differences with Rawls on mat- people would be constrained to reason in gen- ters of both method and substance, and that his eral terms. In this way, universalizability would alternative appeal to a comparative outlook can- replace natural law as the standard for evaluating not do the philosophical work that is needed to political institutions. sustain his vision of justice. Really his argument Sen is skeptical that people could ever be depends heavily on his appeals to a version of induced to agree on a theory of justice in this Adam Smith’s impartial spectator, but Sen fails to way. Moreover, he thinks it is unnecessary for deal with obvious criticisms of it and he deploys them to try to do so in order to tackle some of it selectively to legitimate positions that he finds the most pressing matters of justice in the real congenial. Last I turn to his claim that democracy world. He observes that being persuaded that the is an important vehicle for advancing the cause Mona Lisa is the best painting in the world, or of justice. This is a significant contribution, but that Mount Everest the highest mountain, is nei- Sen’s account is marred by lack of attention to the ther necessary nor perhaps even helpful in adju- dynamics of democratic politics. As a result, he dicating the relative merits of a Van Gogh and a misses opportunities to advance our understand- Picasso, or the relative heights of Kilimanjaro and ing of when and how democracy is likely to serve Mount McKinley (pp. 101–02). These are, to be the cause of justice. sure, vivid cautions; and Sen’s impulse to focus our critical energy on serious injustice is deeply Against Transcendental Theory congenial—at least to me. But how do Sen’s observations capture what differentiates his proj- Rawls did not use the term “transcendental” to ect from Rawls’s? describe his enterprise, but Sen deploys it to cap- Rawls’s commitment to ideal theory, as he called ture its Kantian flavor. Traditional social contract it, had three distinctive features: he thought that 07_BookReviews494.indd 1252 11/22/11 4:12 PM Book Reviews 1253 we should reason about justice under relatively by this observation to opine that humans might favorable conditions; he thought that we should recognize obligations to weaker people and other mostly ignore enforcement problems until we are species “because of the asymmetry between us,” clear about what justice requires; and he thought rather than from some expectation of benefit. Yet that, if we do this, we will be able to determine the mother–child example ignores the relative which of the various theories of justice on offer strength of familial ties that foster expectations of is best. Specifically, he argued that, behind his reciprocity on the part of adult children toward veil of ignorance, people would embrace a system elderly parents, not to mention a mother’s genetic guaranteeing three things in declining order of interest in her offspring and close relatives (W. D. importance: the most expansive basic freedoms Hamilton 1964). These factors render the exam- that can be given to all, equality of opportunity, ple a poor basis for the claim that people can be and limits on inequalities gearing them to the counted on to act voluntarily on obligations when benefit of the least advantaged. This scheme they have nothing to gain. would be chosen over the going alternatives, pro- The only other example Sen discusses is also less viding an Archimedean standard that we can take than encouraging. This concerns the third cen- to our actual “second best” world to see how it tury B.C. Indian emperor Ashoka who weakened measures up and where it needs improvement. the prevailing system of institutional rules, pun- Rawls’s focus on relatively favorable condi- ishments, and incentives and disbanded the army, tions was meant to restrict the focus to societ- relying instead on Buddhist-inspired exhortations ies that have reached a level that he described to his people to reflect more and behave better. as “ moderate scarcity.” He assumed that people Ashoka was, in many ways, an admirable figure are not so overwhelmed by hunger that they who liberated slaves and indentured laborers, but cannot reason, and he exempted from consider- his vast empire collapsed shortly after his death— ation failed states or societies facing chronic pov- scarcely an advertisement for his approach to erty or famines—which he supposed should be achieving compliance. Indeed the real puzzle is evaluated by reference to different distributive why his empire did not fall apart sooner. As Sen principles than those he defended. Sen has writ- admits, commentators have concluded that this ten usefully elsewhere (1999) about the role of was at least partly because Ashoka failed fully democracy in combating famine, and he restates to dismantle the administrative system of dis- those arguments here (pp. 338–48). Beyond this, ciplined rule that he inherited (see Bruce Rich he does not challenge Rawls’s focus on moder- 2008, pp. 133–36). Sen speculates that another ately favorable conditions, so I do not pursue that likely factor was the “awe in which he [Ashoka] issue here. was held by the people at large” (pp. 75–77). One Sen also has little to say about Rawls’s brack- could debate whether there is a way to ensure eting of compliance questions, perhaps because that great leaders will come to power when they Sen himself pays scant attention to them in devel- are needed, but it is beside the point here.2 If Sen oping his own views. Thus while he argues for is right about that Askoka’s awe-inspiring person- a view of justice in which people have priorities ality held things together during his lifetime, this other than “the single-minded pursuit of our own also militates against Sen’s hope that people can well-being”(pp. 18–19), he has virtually nothing be counted on to comply with obligations that are to say about how that might be sustained in the neither in their perceived self-interest nor backed real world. For instance, in the course of defend- up by coercive institutions—simply out of a sense ing the notion that having the power to mitigate of moral obligation. an injustice brings with it the obligation to do so, Sen cites with approval Gautama Buddha’s opti- mism that people can recognize such claims on the grounds that a mother embraces a responsi- 2 I am inclined to agree with Madison in Federalist #10 that institutions are best designed on the assumption that bility to her child “because she can do things to “enlightened statesmen will not always be at the helm” influence the child’s life that the child itself can- (Alexander Hamilton, James Madison, and John Jay 2009, not do” (p. 205). Like Buddha, Sen is encouraged p. 50). 07_BookReviews494.indd 1253 11/22/11 4:12 PM 1254 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XLIX (December 2011) For all its infirmities, Rawls’s original posi- mountains suggest, we can work with incomplete tion was at least intended to align self-interested orderings. But there is less at stake here than calculation with what he saw as the demands of meets the eye. justice by asking people to reason about what Notice, first, that Rawls deployed both compar- rules they would agree on if kept in ignorance ative reasoning and incomplete orderings in argu- about their particular circumstances, values, ing for his principles of justice. His goal was to and ambitions. And while it is true that Rawls make the case that, behind the veil of ignorance, says that in a just society people can be expected rational people would choose his account of jus- to behave reasonably—in accordance, that is, tice over such going alternatives as perfection- of what justice requires—he is careful, as Sen ism and, most importantly, utilitarianism. Rawls notes (pp. 68, 79–80), to say that this depends sought to do this by showing that, from the stand- on their developing the expectation that others point of the most adversely affected person, the will behave in a like fashion. One could read this principles he advocates would be more appeal- as conceding that, in the real world, behavioral ing than the others. It follows a fortiori that, if adaptation will be necessary for people to live in someone could show that some hitherto unex- accordance with what justice requires, which is amined principle would do even better than his Sen’s position. from that point of view, Rawls would endorse the Alternatively, one could read Rawls, as I am new principle. So it is wrong for Sen to say that inclined to read him, as following the logic of a Rawls purported to offer an account of “perfectly base-closing commission. Congress binds itself just institutions in a world where all alternatives in advance to accept the results of the commis- are available” (p. 11). When Rawls (1999, p. 226) sion charged to decide which military bases characterized his principles as procedural expres- to close and it insulates the commission from sions of the categorical imperative, he was just constituency lobbying—concededly a fair proce- describing the standard by reference to which dure. But everyone knows that the government competing principles should be evaluated—to will have to enforce the results after the process wit, one that requires endorsement even by those is complete, when Representatives of districts most adversely affected by the operation of those that have not fared well will be looking for ways principles. He was not claiming to have set forth to defect. In a like fashion, I read Rawls’s assump- a transcendental deduction of the principles tion on this score to be that, once the principles of themselves. justice have been accepted as just behind the veil Moreover, Rawls has been condemned in the of ignorance, it is legitimate for the government literature for letting this case depend on partial to enforce compliance with them. Otherwise orderings. He famously equated the standpoint his requirement that it is a condition for expect- of justice with that of the most adversely affected ing reasonable behavior of people that they, in representative individual due to his assumptions turn, may legitimately expect others to behave about grave risks. Rawls was enough of a realist reasonably, cannot be met. After all, there is no to acknowledge that there may be no relationship analog, for Rawls, of Marx’s “withering away of between the level of economic development in a the state”—even in a perfectly just society. This country and the condition of people at the bot- might be an unduly charitable reading of Rawls, tom. This meant that, even under the relatively but, even without it, nothing Sen says gives him favorable conditions of moderate scarcity about an edge on the compliance front. which he was writing in A Theory of Justice, for This leaves Sen’s claim that what differenti- a given individual this condition might be dire ates his approach from Rawls’s is his use of com- (Rawls 1999, pp. 134–35). Given that you might parative reasoning rather than a transcendental turn out to be one of those people once the veil of deduction designed to come up with a perfect ignorance is lifted, you had better be concerned account of justice. Sen insists that, if we adopt his about them. Accordingly, Rawls reasoned that comparative approach, we need not settle every behind the veil of ignorance it makes sense to question about justice to settle any question insist that departures from equality operate to the about justice. As his examples of paintings and advantage of the people at the bottom. 07_BookReviews494.indd 1254 11/22/11 4:12 PM Book Reviews 1255 As Sen is aware (pp. 103–04), this insistence preoccupied with questions that divert attention opened Rawls to the criticism that protecting from important matters of justice? It is easy to people at the bottom might come at a consider- resonate with the complaint, but Sen’s various able cost to others, even others who are quite metaphorical illustrations of what he takes to badly off. Rawls tried to blunt the force of this be at stake make it hard to pin down just what criticism by suggesting that helping people at the he thinks is wrong and, more important, how bottom would have positive externalities through- his approach addresses the deficiencies that he out the system, a kind of multiplier effect that identifies. would benefit everyone. But he acknowledged Notice that Sen objects to two different activi- that the ripple effects posited by his account of ties that he thinks are a waste of time. The first, “chain connection” might not occur in fact, main- reflected in the examples of the sauna and the taining that in that eventuality he would nonethe- mountain altitudes, concern trivial but not less stick to his difference principle (Rawls 1999, unanswerable questions. Presumably there is pp. 70–73; Ian Shapiro 1986, pp. 218–34). In an answer to the question what temperature effect this means that Rawls’s argument for the the person locked in the sauna would find most difference principle rests on a partial ordering in comfortable, and it would be possible to record just the same way that Sen’s does when he main- the exact height of every mountain on the planet tains that justice requires intervention in the face (indeed, this has surely been done by now). Sen’s of famine regardless of the costs of that interven- point is that, for many purposes, we just don’t tion to others. need to know the answer—it amounts to worry- In short, when Rawls (1999, pp. 8, 68, 215, 302, ing about things three points to the right of the 309) speaks of a perfectly just society, this is not decimal when the problem at hand is to its left. a world without conflict, scarcity, or (unlike Sen!) When billions live in poverty, debating whether self-interested people. It is a world that operates an addiction to plover’s eggs and pre-phylloxera to the benefit of the least advantaged whose con- claret is a disability that merits compensation dition might be so dire that failing to protect them gives political philosophy a bad name.3 But how would be irrational for someone who might turn does Sen’s call for a “comparative” approach out to be one of them. In making that case, Rawls help? depends heavily on comparative reasoning and Aside from a small number of obvious cases incomplete orderings, with the result that there such as slavery and victims of famine, Sen has is a good deal less disagreement between him virtually nothing to say about how to make the and Sen than Sen seems to realize. Indeed, Rawls comparisons that yield the judgments we should (1999, pp. 234–42) goes so far as to declare him- care about. Thus while he is convincing that we self agnostic between capitalism and socialism should not regard it as indicating the infirmity of on the grounds that it is unclear which of these a theory that it cannot tell us which out of a 39 systems, or possibly some hybrid, best meets or 40 percent tax rate is superior (p. 396), noth- the requirements of justice. Thus when Sen ing in his account supplies the basis for distin- advocates a comparative evaluation of economic guishing between, say, a 35 percent top marginal institutions (“preferring a greater—or indeed tax rate and a 70 percent one. As this example lesser—role for the free market” as an alternative indicates, Sen’s scorn for fussing over small dis- to Rawls’s alleged “transcendental search for the tinctions also fails to capture what is at stake perfect package of social institutions” (footnote between him and Rawls, since Rawls does not 6) he is positing a distinction where there is no fuss over them either. It is true that Rawls never difference. told us how progressive the income-tax code should be (or, indeed, whether we should rely on Sen’s Comparative Theory 3 This is not Sen’s example, but it might as well have If Sen’s methodological differences with Rawls been. See Kenneth J. Arrow (1973, p. 254), Ronald are overdrawn, what of his more general com- Dworkin (2000, p. 49), G. A. Cohen (1989, pp. 1923–24), plaint that political philosophers are too often and Rawls (1993, p. 185). 07_BookReviews494.indd 1255 11/22/11 4:12 PM 1256 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XLIX (December 2011) income taxes at all) but, unlike Sen, he supplies Some of the time Sen’s worry seems to be that, a criterion to decide the matter. The optimal tax because different theories rest on incommensu- rate for Rawls is whatever rate operates to the rable values, their protagonists will be unable to greatest benefit of the least advantaged, and it is agree on the right course of action in a given situ- up to the economists and policy wonks to figure ation. But at other times the problem seems to out what that is. Adapting Sen’s sauna analogy, a be one of intratheoretical indeterminacy. Thus he person paying a 70 percent tax rate might well notes that a utilitarian case could be made for giv- be inclined yell that it is “much too high!” and ing the flute to Bob or Carla if diminishing mar- quickly lose patience with someone who insisted ginal utility or incentives are taken into account on being told what the optimal tax rate is before (pp. 13–14). The same could be said of the agreeing to a cut in their rate. But that impa- egalitarian and libertarian arguments, although tience would scarcely amount to a compelling he does not say so. An egalitarian might give it reason to reduce her taxes. Sen’s real contention to Anne on the grounds that giving all three the is that we should address the most compelling opportunity to enjoy hearing good music mat- injustices in the world first, yet he has surpris- ters more than giving Bob an instrument he can- ingly little to say about just what makes a claim not play, or to Carla on the grounds that “from compelling, or how this is illuminated by “com- each according to her ability to each according to parative” theory. her work” is a sound socialist principle when no Sen’s example of the Mona Lisa and other art- exploitation is involved. Alternatively, the egali- works puts a different set of issues on the table tarian might make them share it. The libertarian because it might be that a group of people who might think that Ann or Bob should get the flute agree that the Mona Lisa is the greatest painting if Carla stole the raw materials or the tools she of all time will never agree on the relative merits used to make it from either of them, or if she is a of a Van Gogh and a Picasso. Their conceptions bully who they fear will jab them in the eye with of what constitutes artistic excellence might just the flute—the child’s equivalent of a Nozickian happen to overlap only concerning the Mona “independent.”4 Lisa. Here the issue is not preoccupation with I was hoping that Sen would eventually deploy trivial but answerable questions that is presumed the flute example to display the attractiveness to be wasting people’s time, but, rather, preoccu- of his capabilities-based approach to justice. He pation with questions to which there is no answer never attempts this however; perhaps because even in principle. Again, while preoccupation it, too, is compatible with giving the flute to any with such questions is an activity that is easily of the children. Is it more important that the condemned, it is hard to see how Sen’s call for capability for flute playing be realized (give it to comparative political philosophy resolves, or even Anne), or to reward the person with the capabil- mitigates the difficulty. ity for flute making (give it to Carla)? Or maybe it Sen spends a good deal of time worrying about would be better to give Bob the flute, since Anne the problems for justice that are presented by and Carla have already developed their capabili- incommensurable values. To illustrate this, he ties and giving it to Bob might motivate him to supplies the example of trying to decide which of learn how to play it. three children should get a flute: Anne, the only one who knows how to play it; Bob, the only one who is so poor that he has no other toys; or Carla who made the flute. Sen reasons that a utilitar- 4 Drawing on the welfare economics literature on compensation from Kaldor and Hicks to Scitovsky and ian would likely give it to Anne, an egalitarian Samuelson, Robert Nozick (1974) argued from libertar- would give it to Bob, and a libertarian would give ian premises that the fear generated by “independents,” it to Carla. He returns to this example repeatedly, who reject the prevailing order, is an externality that can which he takes to illustrate the fact that there is be mitigated if they could be compensated for the rights violation involved in removing their capacity to threaten, no compelling way to choose among appeals to but everyone else would still be better off than they would happiness, economic equity, or entitlement to the have been living in fear of the uncoerced independents. fruits of one’s labor (pp. 14, 201). For discussion, see Shapiro (1986, pp. 169–76). 07_BookReviews494.indd 1256 11/22/11 4:12 PM Book Reviews 1257 Sen emphasizes that it is the opportunity to anyone think an impoverished child’s life is criti- realize capabilities (as distinct from whether they cally reliant on having a flute to play—not least are realized in fact) that is vital (pp. 235–37), when he lacks the capacity to play it? Perhaps the but that helps little here. Does it matter more reason there is no commanding resolution to the that people have opportunities to realize exist- flute trilemma on any of the theories, including ing capabilities or to develop undeveloped ones? Sen’s, is—ironically—that no important question Should we equalize the number of capabilities of justice is at stake. people have the chance to develop or perhaps the proportion of their capabilities that they can real- Plural Grounds ize? Are some capabilities more important than others? Should the overall goal be to minimize Another response to incommensurability that unrealized capabilities? Does it matter if one of Sen explores is to wonder how serious it is in the children could be a better flautist than the real life. Perhaps people with different values others? What, if any, interpersonal comparisons will nonetheless be able to agree on particular are sanctioned in making the relevant judgments? outcomes. An example he gives is the long list of Readers who have found Sen’s earlier formula- alternative (and not obviously mutually compat- tions of his capability-based approach appealing ible) reasons that Edmund Burke adduced to per- but undertheorized will be disappointed that he suade Parliament to impeach Warren Hastings in did not take the opportunity to develop it more 1789. Another is the list of reasons, Sen main- fully in this book. tains, that could be given in support of the propo- Sen acknowledges that his plural conception sition that the 2003 U.S. invasion of Iraq was a of human capabilities (which would presum- bad idea (pp. 1–3). These examples of “plural ably range over the capabilities to play music, grounds” capture the reality that in collective life enjoy toys, or build musical instruments in the people often need not agree on why they support example at hand) runs into questions about a proposition. That they do so may be enough. incommensurability (pp. 239–41), but says it is an Cass R. Sunstein (1995) calls it “incompletely open question how difficult they will be to resolve, theorized agreement.”5 Democracies endorse concluding that the “main task is to get things it implicitly with the secret ballot which shields right on the comparative judgments that can be people from having to explain the reasons for reached through personal and public reasoning, their choices to others. rather than feel compelled to opine on every Notice that appealing to plural grounds scarcely possible comparison that could be considered” differentiates Sen from the mature Rawls (1993, (p. 243). pp. 9–11, 133–72), whose idea of an overlapping But Sen does not tell us how to get the com- consensus rests on the same logic that Sunstein parative judgments right, or even how to think and Sen both invoke to determine what sort of about them. He never tells who should get the agreement is needed to sustain an account of jus- flute. The closest he comes is to say that maybe tice. Rawls’s “political, not metaphysical” move there will be some convergence of prescrip- involved recognizing that, just as hiring commit- tions—if Carla turns out also to be the poorest tees, legislators, and judges routinely agree on child or the only one who knows how to play the outcomes when they could never agree on their flute or if Bob’s poverty “is so extreme, and his dependence on something to play so important for a plausible life, that the poverty-based argu- 5 Sen differentiates his stance from Sunstein’s (and, presumably Rawls’s, discussed below) on the grounds ment might come to dominate the judgment of that Sunstein is concerned with alternative theories that justice” (pp. 396–97). Changing the relative cir- converge on the same conclusion, whereas Sen focuses cumstances of the players is in effect to dissolve on different “perspectives” that can “be accommodated the tensions the example was intended to cre- internally within a capacious theory” (p. 397fn., Sen’s ital- ics). In fact, in his examples of plural grounds (impeaching ate—solving the problem by definition. In any Hastings and the Iraq war), Sen adduces considerations case, plausible as the notion that extreme poverty that could emanate from either or both. As I have already trumps other considerations might be, why would noted, the same is true of the flute trilemma. 07_BookReviews494.indd 1257 11/22/11 4:12 PM 1258 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XLIX (December 2011) reasons for endorsing those outcomes, so there is good. This is a welcome fact because the upshot no reason to require citizens to agree on meta- of those debates was that the conception of neu- physical fundamentals as conditions for accept- trality Rawls sought cannot be found.6 Sen dis- ing a particular set of political arrangements. It is misses that enterprise as a preoccupation with the fact of overlapping consensus, for the mature “closed impartiality” to differentiate it from the Rawls, which supplies the basis for political legiti- “open impartiality” he advocates. This is some- macy. Sen (pp. 2, 12–15, 200–201, 353–54) calls it thing more like benevolent disinterestedness “plural grounding” or “using a number of differ- than neutrality. Sen thinks of it as reflecting ent lines” of argument in support of a proposition Smith’s admonition to adopt the perspective of “without seeking an agreement on their relative an impartial spectator who enables us to view our merits.” It is basically the same idea. sentiments at “a certain distance” from us. The But appeals to plural grounds resolve consider- goal is “to avoid local parochialism of values” by ably less about justice than Sen seems to suppose. taking account of arguments from outside our Consider his discussion of plural grounds in light culture and traditions so that we scrutinize “not of his examples of partial orderings. When Sen only the influence of vested interest, but also says that “we do not need to get all steamed up the impact of entrenched tradition and custom” about identifying the most perfect picture in the (p. 45). As Smith put it in The Theory of Moral world” (p. 101) in order to determine the relative Sentiments, in order to survey our sentiments and merits of the Van Gogh over the Picasso, he over- motives, we must try to see them “with the eyes of looks the fact that it is the difference between the other people, or as other people are likely to view Van Gogh and the Picasso that people are liable them” (Smith 1853, p. 161) Open impartiality for to get steamed up about—not the merits of the Sen (pp. 124–35), is a kind of critical distance. Mona Lisa about which everyone, by assump- Admirable as such a trait might be, it scarcely tion in his example, agrees. In a like vein, people does the work that Sen’s appeal to comparative who knew that Everest was the world’s highest political theory failed to do on its own. He never mountain might well have disagreed over which tells us what makes an observer impartial, other out of Kilimanjaro and Mount McKinley is higher than that the ingredients include distance and, before there were instruments to provide a sometimes, ideas from other cultures. Nor does definitive resolution of their disagreement. Sen’s he tell us how the views of an impartial observer discussion of plural grounds thus lives in consid- would help us decide on the resolution of any erable tension with his claim that we should focus actual contested question about justice. In his dis- on concrete comparisons because it will often be cussion of human rights, for instance, Sen asserts about these comparisons that plural grounding that there is a human right to basic medical care will be lacking. Nothing Sen says indicates how (pp. 367–68; see also pp. 259, 285–86). Perhaps he believes that people should decide whether there is, but he says nothing about what to say to the Picasso or the Van Gogh is better, or which those who contest it or, even if it is granted, how mountain is higher. to resolve trenchant disagreements about who is entitled to how much health care, or in which Impartial Spectators circumstances. In a world in which resources spent on AIDS research could be spent on can- The only additional help Sen offers is his appeal cer research, artificial hearts, dialysis machines, to the idea of an impartial spectator, which he or something else entirely, one reasonably antici- takes from Adam Smith. Sen is careful here not pates some guidance from a theory that champi- to interpret impartiality to mean splitting the dif- ons the focus on concrete comparisons that bear ference among competing claims in a society, as in consequential ways on real-world dilemmas. an arbitrator might perhaps be inclined to do. Sen also does not mean to invoke the notion of neu- 6 The viable defense of Rawls’s first principle, for exam- trality that became the focus of debates spawned ple, is that it embodies the most extensive possible system by the early Rawls’s assertion that his principles of liberties compatible with a like liberty for all, not that it were neutral among rational conceptions of the is neutral. For discussion, see Shapiro (2003a, pp. 131–32). 07_BookReviews494.indd 1258 11/22/11 4:12 PM Book Reviews 1259 Yet nothing in Sen’s account of the impartial of them, and impartiality tends to reside in the observer even hints at how to deal with them. eye of the beholder. This difficulty extends to Sen’s treatment of the nondistributive aspects of justice. For instance, Democracy in illustrating the alleged advantages of open impartiality he remarks that “globally sensitive To this Sen might object that he has explicitly questioning can be more important in a fuller distanced himself from the claim that there are assessment than local discussions on, say, the final answers to questions about justice on the facts and values surrounding women’s unequal grounds that “our best efforts could still leave position, or the unacceptability of torture or— us locked into some mistake or other, however for that matter—of capital punishment” (pp. hidden it might be” and that, as a result, “the 71–72). He returns to the death penalty several nature, robustness and reach” of theories of jus- times, suggesting that once people come to view tice “depend on contributions from discussion it through “the eyes of the rest of mankind” they and discourse” (p. 89). This appeal to discussion will be more inclined to reject it, along with such is central to Sen’s defense of democracy in the other disagreeable practices as stoning adulter- final chapters of the book. Aspects of what he says ous women (pp. 404–05). His text is replete with there are plausible, but his account is disappoint- assertions such as that although many people in ingly rudimentary and marred by missed oppor- the United States or China might be unimpressed tunities to explore the ways in which democracy by the fact that most European countries have can advance the cause of justice. abolished capital punishment, open impartiality Notice, first, that Sen’s appeal to democracy can show them that “there would be, in general, lives in tension with his invocation of impartial a strong case for examining the justificatory argu- spectators since there is no reason to think that ments that are used against capital punishment democratic publics will take their advice. Sen elsewhere” (p. 407). This calls to mind Thurgood characterizes democracy as a system of public Marshall’s confident insistence (without adducing reason and discussion. The image he seems to any evidence) that if only Americans were fully have in mind is an academic seminar writ large, informed about the death penalty they would where the best argument wins. But in demo- agree with his opposition to it.7 I wonder. cratic politics outsiders are easily portrayed as Sen concedes that listening to “distant voices” stooges to some unacknowledged local interest does not require us to accept them, but he says or as having agendas of their own. Think of the nothing about which among them should be “impartial” development plans handed out by the heeded—or why. His repeated assertions to the IMF and World Bank, the Quartet’s roadmap for effect that considerations from elsewhere will Palestinian/Israeli peace, or the climate control “enrich our thinking” never generate a reasoned policies recommended by the IPCC. Moreover, case about why this enriched thinking will take appeals to arguments put forward by outsiders lack us to the destinations that he believes we obvi- democratic legitimacy precisely because of where ously should reach. After a while, his combination they come from. Supreme Court Justice Stephen of cherry-picked arguments from elsewhere and Breyer and State Department legal adviser his hopeful deployment of the passive voice (as Harold Koh have been pilloried for appealing to in the poverty-based argument “might come to a version of Sen’s open impartiality in interpreting dominate the judgment of justice,” p. 397) make American constitutional law.8 If one is going to be the book read more like a manifesto for sensible chaps who agree with Sen than an argument that 8 See Justice Scalia’s remarks to Justice Breyer at might persuade even an open-minded skeptic. the U.S. Association of Constitutional Law Discussion The trouble with spectators is that there are many at American University, http://www.freerepublic.com/ focus/news/1352357/posts. Opposition to Harold Koh’s nomination included a “Coalition to Preserve American 7 See Furman v. Georgia 408 U.S. 238 (1972), at pp. Sovereignty” letter by the Ethics and Policy Center to 360–69. See also Marshall’s dissent in Gregg v. Georgia the U.S. Senate Committee on Foreign Relations (David 428 U.S. 153 (1976). Weigel 2009). 07_BookReviews494.indd 1259 11/22/11 4:12 PM 1260 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XLIX (December 2011) committed both to impartiality and to democracy responses to them because powerful coalitions do as vehicles for advancing justice, some attention not emerge to block those responses. The kind of is needed to the ways in which they conflict. Sen laws mandating disaster relief that are enacted in appears not to notice the problem. the wake of hurricanes, or to compensate victims The most suggestive part of Sen’s discussion of catastrophic terrorist attacks, could never make of democracy turns on his well-known observa- it through the rough and tumble of normal legis- tion that democracies seem to be immune from lative politics. And, because of their exceptional famine.9 This is surely an advantage, but what and, therefore, bounded character, disasters pro- does it tell us about democracy’s desirability vide opportunities for leaders to demonstrate from the standpoint of other features of justice efficacy. The problem can be solved, and it is usu- that Sen prizes? Democratic responsiveness ally clear what is needed to solve it. Politicians to famine has not carried over, for example, to are often held accountable for events over which alleviating chronic poverty or reducing extreme they have little, if any control. Catastrophes can inequalities—despite the expectations of many empower them.11 nineteenth and twentieth century thinkers to Most problems of injustice are not like this. the contrary.10 This difference suggests that at a They tend to be chronic rather than cata- minimum that Sen’s view of democracy as a sys- strophic, systemic rather than episodic, and tem of “public reason” that promotes “govern- rooted in enduring conflicts of interest and ide- ment by discussion” that will facilitate advances ology. Responses to them are less spontaneous toward justice (pp. 321–28) stands in need of than is the case with disasters, and inevitably pruning by reality. more contentious as they become embroiled in Famines, like other disasters, are vivid. They disagreements about causal and moral respon- garner media attention, as Sen notes, making it sibility and the likely efficacy of alternative hard for governments in countries with a free courses of action. They divide people along press—which democracies generally have— coalitional fault lines. How feasible it is for to ignore them. The public drama and media politicians to respond to them will depend on attention surrounding famines make it possible calculations about the chances of success, the to mobilize support for extraordinary action. views of powerful members of their constituen- Moreover, famines and other disasters often strike cies, and related considerations. Sen might with unpredictably out of the blue. This has two fur- profit have explored the implications of these ther implications: they tend not to involve fraught features of democratic politics to illuminate the moral debates about whether and to what extent conditions under which democracies are likely people are responsible for their dire straits, and to be justice-promoting. For instance, if sys- they exhibit a “there but for fortune . . .” logic. temic injustices can be reframed in the public People know that disasters can befall anyone. imagination to be more like famines and other Powerful coalitions are not needed to support catastrophes, more progress might be made with 9 He might have added that democracies do better him to endorse the “parliamentary road to socialism” in than nondemocracies at protecting human rights—indeed hopes that the working class would do through the bal- that democracy is more important from this point of view lot box what they had failed to do at the barricades. The than much trumpeted (at least by American constitutional median voter theorem developed by Harold Hotelling, theorists) role of independent courts and bills of rights Anthony Downs and others also predicts that imposing (see Robert A. Dahl 2006, pp. 152–72; Shapiro 2011, pp. majority rule on a distribution of income and wealth of 68–79). the sort that we observe in the capitalist democracies 10 Classical liberals like John Stuart Mill and Alexis de will lead to significant downward redistribution. For a Tocqueville feared that a universal franchise would lead to review of the literature on why this does not occur in fact, majority tyranny through which the masses would expro- see Shapiro (2003b, pp. 104–45). On the failure of democ- priate the assets of the few. This led Mill to advocate a racy to alleviate chronic poverty, see Dan Banik (2007). second vote for university graduates and Tocqueville to 11 This does not mean that they won’t make a mess of embrace standard republican constraints on majoritarian it, as the Bush Administration did in response to Hurricane politics. In his later years a chastened Karl Marx noticed Katrina’s devastation of New Orleans in 2005. But when that the same possibility from a different point of view, leading happens, they will be seen as inept more than as malevolent. 07_BookReviews494.indd 1260 11/22/11 4:12 PM

Description:
Stanford University. The Idea of Justice. By Amartya Sen. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, Belknap Press,. 2009. Pp. xxviii, 467. $22.95, paper.
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.