ebook img

Refounding political governance : the metaphysics of public administration PDF

230 Pages·2011·2.208 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Refounding political governance : the metaphysics of public administration

Public Policy, Administration and Management REFOUNDING POLITICAL GOVERNANCE The Metaphysics of Public Administration By Bruce Cutting & Alexander Kouzmin Cover Artwork: Ludmila Kouzmin ([email protected]) Cover Design: Hilary Cutting eBooks End User License Agreement Please read this license agreement carefully before using this eBook. Your use of this eBook/chapter constitutes your agreement to the terms and conditions set forth in this License Agreement. Bentham Science Publishers agrees to grant the user of this eBook/chapter, a non-exclusive, nontransferable license to download and use this eBook/chapter under the following terms and conditions: 1. This eBook/chapter may be downloaded and used by one user on one computer. The user may make one back-up copy of this publication to avoid losing it. The user may not give copies of this publication to others, or make it available for others to copy or download. For a multi-user license contact [email protected] 2. All rights reserved: All content in this publication is copyrighted and Bentham Science Publishers own the copyright. You may not copy, reproduce, modify, remove, delete, augment, add to, publish, transmit, sell, resell, create derivative works from, or in any way exploit any of this publication’s content, in any form by any means, in whole or in part, without the prior written permission from Bentham Science Publishers. 3. The user may print one or more copies/pages of this eBook/chapter for their personal use. The user may not print pages from this eBook/chapter or the entire printed eBook/chapter for general distribution, for promotion, for creating new works, or for resale. Specific permission must be obtained from the publisher for such requirements. Requests must be sent to the permissions department at E-mail: [email protected] 4. The unauthorized use or distribution of copyrighted or other proprietary content is illegal and could subject the purchaser to substantial money damages. The purchaser will be liable for any damage resulting from misuse of this publication or any violation of this License Agreement, including any infringement of copyrights or proprietary rights. Warranty Disclaimer: The publisher does not guarantee that the information in this publication is error-free, or warrants that it will meet the users’ requirements or that the operation of the publication will be uninterrupted or error-free. This publication is provided "as is" without warranty of any kind, either express or implied or statutory, including, without limitation, implied warranties of merchantability and fitness for a particular purpose. The entire risk as to the results and performance of this publication is assumed by the user. In no event will the publisher be liable for any damages, including, without limitation, incidental and consequential damages and damages for lost data or profits arising out of the use or inability to use the publication. The entire liability of the publisher shall be limited to the amount actually paid by the user for the eBook or eBook license agreement. Limitation of Liability: Under no circumstances shall Bentham Science Publishers, its staff, editors and authors, be liable for any special or consequential damages that result from the use of, or the inability to use, the materials in this site. eBook Product Disclaimer: No responsibility is assumed by Bentham Science Publishers, its staff or members of the editorial board for any injury and/or damage to persons or property as a matter of products liability, negligence or otherwise, or from any use or operation of any methods, products instruction, advertisements or ideas contained in the publication purchased or read by the user(s). Any dispute will be governed exclusively by the laws of the U.A.E. and will be settled exclusively by the competent Court at the city of Dubai, U.A.E. You (the user) acknowledge that you have read this Agreement, and agree to be bound by its terms and conditions. Permission for Use of Material and Reproduction Photocopying Information for Users Outside the USA: Bentham Science Publishers Ltd. grants authorization for individuals to photocopy copyright material for private research use, on the sole basis that requests for such use are referred directly to the requestor's local Reproduction Rights Organization (RRO). The copyright fee is US $25.00 per copy per article exclusive of any charge or fee levied. In order to contact your local RRO, please contact the International Federation of Reproduction Rights Organisations (IFRRO), Rue du Prince Royal 87, B-I050 Brussels, Belgium; Tel: +32 2 551 08 99; Fax: +32 2 551 08 95; E-mail: [email protected]; url: www.ifrro.org This authorization does not extend to any other kind of copying by any means, in any form, and for any purpose other than private research use. Photocopying Information for Users in the USA: Authorization to photocopy items for internal or personal use, or the internal or personal use of specific clients, is granted by Bentham Science Publishers Ltd. for libraries and other users registered with the Copyright Clearance Center (CCC) Transactional Reporting Services, provided that the appropriate fee of US $25.00 per copy per chapter is paid directly to Copyright Clearance Center, 222 Rosewood Drive, Danvers MA 01923, USA. Refer also to www.copyright.com CONTENTS Preface i CHAPTERS 1. Introduction 1 2. The JEWAL Synthesis Philosophy of Mind 16 3. The JEWAL Theory of Governance 54 4. Validation in the Literature 68 5. Governance in Society 76 6. Public Administration and Constitutional Power 94 7. Public Administration and Government Decision Making 130 8. Public Administration as a Vocation 177 9. Governance in the Westminster System 191 10. Conclusion 213 References 216 i PREFACE Since Montesquieu’s (1952; 1689–1755) incisive differentiation of the principal forms of governance and their components, the rate at which different theories of governance have been proposed has exponentially grown until now when we have a plethora of different theories on the best way to govern, lead and/or manage. Anyone interested in this topic is confronted with the many conflicting schools of thought, from Weber’s (1948; 1864–1920) theory of the “iron cage” to Wheatley’s (1992) New-Age concept of leadership. This seeming maze of different theories can be seen merely as different perspectives on the overall embracing concept of governance which is, essentially, the holistic conception and explanation of differentiated purposive human systems—about paradigms and systems that have their inception in and are limited by, the human mind. The core challenge, then, is to put some order and rationale into the understanding of this “many-headed” concept of governance. We meet this challenge by mapping out a cognitive framework that is capable of embracing and ordering all the multitudinous differentiated conceptions of human governance experienced at the different levels of society. In essence, this book reformulates the concept of organizational governance in terms of the metaphor of the human mind. The cognitive model of governance formulated can be used to explain how and why different modes of governance are embraced by the different organizations in different circumstances and why this is appropriate and necessary, how and why governance changes over time, and how it is important to institute processes of inquiry, dialogue and reflection in order to know and choose more consciously. Essentially, we reformulate the principles and understanding of organizational governance as an outcome of a process of validating the veracity, realism and prognosticating value of the particular form of institutional archetyping that is based on the metaphor of the human mind. It does this in a three-step process:  First, formulating an expression of the immediate knowing (or seeing, as in aesthetic appreciation) that the essence of an institution’s decision-making processes can be explained in terms of the mind metaphor.  Secondly, the structure and dynamics of the mind metaphor are conceptualised and formulated by a process of reasoning of why and how the philosophical concept of man can be taken as determining the structure and dynamics of the two principal personality typologies.  Thirdly, the true fit, merit and power of the mind metaphor in explaining organizations’ governance is validated by using the cognitive conceptual framework to analyse and prognosticate on the nature and dynamics of governance in the public administration of the political sphere in particular. As a consequence of this scientifically-oriented process, the authors have arrived at a “yes,” or a personal cognitive commitment, to the following key “truths” or “facts” about organizational governance.  The nature and dynamics of governance in organizations reflect the way humans think—OR, the nature, dynamics and development of organizations can be reasonably known, intelligently understood and wisely developed by using the conceptual framework suggested by the metaphor of the mind.  The essence of human thinking results from a process of cognitive differentiation that is faithfully based on hierarchically structured trinities of abstraction (as originally identified by the Greeks and carried forward by the Western scholastic philosophers), which express the different cognitive perspectives that one constructs to perceive, understand and know reality. The key heuristic insight contained within the metaphor of the mind, therefore, is to reinterpret Aquinas’ (1952; c.1225–1274) trinity of abstraction (Lonergan, 1967) as a trinity of cognitive perspectives relevant to a particular aspect of governance. Essentially, the effect of this intellective insight is to transform Weber’s (1949; 1962) ideal types into a newly created concept of a trinity of menetypes (numbered ideal types in an ordered set). The principles underpinning the concept of menetypes facilitate understanding and meaning because the conceptual framework of the mind metaphor can be seen to be based simply on this trinity of menetypes, repeated again and again. Therefore, even though the conceptual framework of governance might seem expansive, fluid and complex, it can be viewed simply as a hierarchically structured, interdependent pattern of cognitive perspectives arranged at each point of focus in the form of the basic trinity of menetypes applicable to that level of thinking. ii  The conceptual framework of the mind metaphor has great explanatory, heuristic and prognostic power and can be used to guide the individual or group process of reaching judgments of fact, assessments of value and decisions of intent. This inherent power of the mind metaphor is validated by the comprehensive, structured and probing analysis conducted into the public administration within the US society. Although the discussion is principally focused at the level of theory and principles, it is clearly evident that the conceptual framework of the mind metaphor does provide a powerful means of analysing the authority, culture and participants within particular real-life organizations. This ability to integrate the analysis of governance over the range of levels of understanding is a key contributor to its explanatory and prognosticating powers. As a consequence of using the mind metaphor to analyse governance in Western society, the key conclusion is that there has been a substantial shift or evolution in thinking from a managerialist mindset to the more abstract politicist mindset (which has alternately been described as postmodernism). This fundamental shift in mindset is pervasive and influences the perspectives taken at many levels in the human governance systems. In particular, this analysis of governance in the US society focuses on the political sphere and concludes that: public administration is only a second-order political power and should eschew any delusions to political equality with the Government’s political arm. Rather, the public administration should be encouraged to maintain and develop further its ethics of clarity, order and loyalty in assisting the Government of the day. Furthermore, public administrators should be developed to work in more abstract, political and interdependent systems of governance. This new, operational environment requires them to develop the capacity to think more politically and at more abstract levels, and to be able to coach others to develop their cognitive powers likewise. This book is a companion book to Refounding Corporate Governance: The Metaphysics of Corporate Leadership, which has also been published in this ‘Public Policy, Administration and Management’ series. Bruce Cutting Alexander Kouzmin Refounding Governance: The Metaphysics of Public Administration, 2011, 1-15 1 CHAPTER 1 Introduction For how shall we know the source of (good governance) between men, if we do not begin by knowing mankind? (Adaptation of Rousseau, 1952: 329)1 Abstract: An introduction is provided to the triadic metaphor of the mind, its depth and its breadth of applicability. A new concept of menetypes is introduced as being based on the triadic conception of human thinking, defined by three psychic levels of abstraction that are enveloped by a conception of the transcendent other. The methodology explains how the triadic conceptual framework gives birth to the JEWAL Synthesis theory of governance - JEWAL being an acronym to signify a synthesis of particular aspects of Eastern philosophical psychology, Western philosophy and depth psychology. INTRODUCTION Governance is taken as the conscious exercise of direction, regulation and control over a human system. At the simplest level there is the governance of the self, and from the earliest Greek times the oracles of society have urged people to “Know Thyself.” But humans do not know themselves in isolation from others as, by themselves, they are very limited and unfulfilled.2 So they join together in purposive groups or organizations that are about pursuing some good, however well articulated or ill-defined it might be. Such groups or organizations need good governance to thrive and to be satisfying enough to the individual members for them to remain within the group—and such governance is orchestrated through and by some members of the group providing leadership of some kind.3 Neither the members of these groups nor the organizations govern themselves in isolation but rather they do so as members of a larger collection or society of people,4 which itself must be subject to some form of governance. ‘No society can subsist without a form of government. “The united strength of individuals,” as Gravina well observes, “constitutes what we call the “body politic”’ (Montesquieu, 1952: 3). Again there are some members of this body politic who take on positions of leadership or governing. The practice and understanding of governance at this highest level of society is much more obtuse, complex and intellectually challenging, as has been evidenced by the attention it has received in philosophical writings since the earliest of times. Governance, therefore, needs to be understood and explained in the context of it being operative in some form at all three levels of the individual, the organization and society.5 Moreover, there is interaction and influence between the different levels of governance, principally because it is people themselves who are involved in all three and are required to balance the often-conflicting demands of each. This book is primarily focused on the middle level, concerning governance within organizations, which are composed of individuals who also need to exercise a degree of self-governance, but which operate within a particular society that lays down principles of overall societal governance. These societal principles determine and shape the form and dynamics of the governance that is exercised within the different organizations. And there are, indeed, a plethora of different types of organization and faces of organizational governance, so much so, that it has been said that ‘there is no such thing as the theory of organizations. Rather there are many theories that attempt to explain and predict how organizations and the people in them will behave in varying occupational structures, cultures, and circumstances’ (Shafritz and Ott, 1996: 4). That is, society’s appreciation and understanding of organizations has become more differentiated and complex, and the dynamics of organizations have become more intricate and subtle. Moreover, change is a fact of life and everywhere the pace of change seems to be accelerating. The social and economic worlds have been undergoing such tumultuous change that modern theory and understanding has largely proved inadequate in the multitude of individual and group mindsets and particular circumstances. This is especially true in the realm of management, which has been subjected to such a dizzying round of short-lived “latest fads” that Bruce A. Cutting and Alexander Kouzmin All rights reserved - © 2011 Bentham Science Publishers Ltd. 2 Refounding Political Governance Cutting and Kouzmin managers are now eschewing the lot just so they can get on and do the job required of them. As Micklethwait and Wooldridge (1996: 18-19) observed: ‘The real problem with management theory is that it is pulling institutions and individuals in conflicting directions… These contradictions within forms reflect a deeper intellectual confusion at the heart of management theory, which has left it not so much a coherent discipline as a battleground between… radically opposed philosophies.’ Therefore, there may not be much mileage in canvassing the vast array of theories or recipes for good management—or good governance. Rather, like Montesquieu (1952),6 we struggle to understand the spirit of governance in organizations. And the obvious common, core principle of organizations is that they are comprised of humans who think and act as though there is an organization, and therefore there is one—irrespective of whether or not there is a physical building, a formal organization chart, or an IT (Information Technology) network connecting all the members together. In essence, the nature, shape and dynamics of any organization are fabrications of the human mind and, in that sense, it looks and acts very much like a more complex, more capable and more power- oriented thinking human.7 As the key to any scientific understanding of phenomena is in the system of conceptual differentiation that is applied in observing and analysing the empirical data, this book searches for an understanding of governance in the structure and dynamics of human thinking or the philosophy of mind. As a consequence, it postulates a philosophy of mind which is used as the basis to view the framework of governance in terms of a metaphor of the mind. The metaphor of the mind is applicable at all three levels of the individual, the organization, and the society, which means that the interrelationships between these three different levels of thinking can be handled in a consistent and reinforcing manner within the one, overall comprehensive framework. The key heuristic development in this book is the reformulation of the meaning and use of ideal types—which, though severely critiqued, have proved to be a useful tool in sociological theory since being introduced by Weber (1962).8 However, their understanding and usage have been unduly limited and their basic conceptual development has essentially withered on the vine. The growth and realisation of their potential have been stunted because Weber (1947; 1962) did not spell out any underlying coherency in the conceptual framework of ideal types9, and nobody since seems to have been able to understand it in such a way as to develop the notion and use of ideal types. An ideal type10 is still regarded essentially as an isolated, theoretical, working hypothesis that describes a situation rather than explains it, and which is not intended to help predict or suggest what decisions/actions should follow as a consequence (Weber, 1962: 14). The concept of ideal types has never developed because the so-defined types always stand alone and no attempt has been made to incorporate an account of their associated dynamics and interactions. Put together in the way explained in this book, “types” can be more than just standalone, descriptive classification schemes; they can represent reality and can be used to inform what action should or should not be taken—and its likely consequences. This book, therefore, develops a radically different approach—yet, it is essentially in keeping with the spirit of Weber’s (1947; 1949; 1962; 1968; 1978a; 1978b) original thinking because the use of the metaphor of the mind provides an integrative explanatory focus on the underlying motivations of the individual participants.11 As with Weber (1962), the underlying premise is that it is individuals who, ultimately, think, decide and act—even if they are heavily influenced by the organizational or societal thinking that they consciously or unconsciously take on board. Instead of proceeding to develop different ideal types for each observed reality, it is much more instructive to begin from the basic understanding that it is humans who think and it is they who, therefore, interpret and explain the reality that they encounter. Is there an identifiable pattern of thinking that can encompass the many and varied perspectives humans can experience? Can some sense be made of the structure and dynamics of such a pattern and can it be harnessed to understand the dynamics of human social action and interaction? Can current understandings of human dynamics be used to inform a metaphor of the mind that can enhance our understanding of governance? The three outcomes from tackling these questions essentially encapsulate the extent of the contribution of original thought proffered in this book, as it:  Encapsulates and articulates a metaphor of the mind that expresses a philosophy of mind that can be seen to have its roots in late Neoplatonic philosophy, and is evident in the work of many Western philosophers/social scientists [including, in particular, Montesquieu (1952) and Weber (1962)] over Introduction Refounding Political Governance 3 the centuries and also in the particular expression of Eastern philosophy that is captured in the personal typology called the Enneagram (Riso, 1987; Palmer, 1991).12 In particular, this book explains how Jungian typology (Jung, 1971; von Franz and Hillman, 1971; Myers, 1980) is an underdeveloped expression of this Eastern philosophy of mind, and how it can be more usefully reformulated in such a way that it corresponds directly to the Enneagram typology—which is captured in the JEWAL Synthesis philosophy of mind (Chapter 2).  Uses the metaphor of mind to develop a theory of governance to explain the dynamic pattern of interrelated rationalities governing motivation and behaviour at the individual, group and societal levels of authority. This theory of governance introduces the concept of menetypes,13 which are a reformulation of ideal types into a “numbered”, coherent, interrelated set of perspectives of a particular aspect of reality—The JEWAL Synthesis Theory of Governance (Chapter 3). BASIC INSIGHTS The basic insights on the philosophy of mind and human governance that are presented in this book are as follows:  All human affairs and the experience of those affairs at each of the levels of the individual, the group and the society have their genesis and fulfilment in the human mind. In particular, an organization is such only because the participating individuals are able to think of it in such a way.  Any view of reality is only ever a partial view and the power of that partial view in experiencing, understanding and knowing that particular reality is critically dependent on the cognitive framework employed by the individual.14 This book is generated out of the mindset moulded by the metaphor of the mind, which is informed by the reworked philosophy of mind explained in Chapter 2. In particular, one is able to think of an organization or a society in the same way as one thinks of an individual, except that the thinking is at higher levels of abstraction.  Humans have the capability or potential to think in any of all possible ways, as the limits of their potential to know are infinite (Proclus, 1963/15th Century: 149). However, if one tries to think of all perspectives at once, one would be pulled in all directions and so get nowhere—and would probably be overwhelmed. This principle of needing one phase of a trinity to dominate can be illustrated by imagining three people of about equal size and strength standing back to back with their arms interlocked. They would each be facing outwards in one of three different directions at roughly equidistant angles around a circle. If they all tried to move forward with the same force there would be no movement. One has to dominate for there to be movement and in that case there will be a secondary individual who is also moving partly forward (in an extreme case this could be in equality with the dominant individual), while the third will need to be repressed and essentially move backwards.  Differentiation and choice is the key. Very early on in life, therefore, one chooses a particular perspective and, in so doing, other conflicting perspectives need to be consciously repressed. Through constant use over time (namely, because it works for the individual), this cognitive dynamic makes for the development of one’s personality. Individuals also exercise this cognitive orienting in the development of their concept of an organization or society, and the result of this is their perceived culture.  With each separate personality or culture found in individuals, organizations or society, comes a patterned set of perspectives, motivation and predictable ways of behaving. This is well captured in the explanatory dynamics of the Enneagram and Jungian typologies as understood in the terms of the insights provided by the philosophy of mind (Chapter 2). The explanatory power of this system of cognitive differentiation has been captured in a conceptual framework of the metaphor of the mind. The key operative principle that informs the structure and dynamics of this metaphor of the mind (Chapter 2) is in the way Aquinas (1952/1225–1274) captures the structure of human thinking in terms of his trinity of abstraction (Lonergan, 1967: 39–43). The key insight is that human thinking can usefully be considered structured in a hierarchy of these three levels of abstraction in much the same way as the Neoplatonists (from the 3rd and 5th Centuries, respectively) Plotinus (1952/3rd Century) and Proclus (1963) did to explain the celestial sphere. The Enneagram typology (Riso, 1987; Palmer, 1991) captures this trinitarian hierarchy within the human psyche and expresses the differentiation between the three levels of abstraction in terms of individuals’ different motivations

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.