ebook img

Reason and faith : philosophy in the Middle Ages PDF

133 Pages·2007·0.831 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Reason and faith : philosophy in the Middle Ages

Reason and Faith: Philosophy in the Middle Ages Part I Professor Thomas Williams THE TEACHING COMPANY ® Thomas Williams, Ph.D. Associate Professor of Philosophy and Religious Studies, University of South Florida Thomas Williams, Associate Professor of Philosophy and Religious Studies at the University of South Florida, received his B.A. in Philosophy from Vanderbilt University in 1988 and his Ph.D. in Philosophy from the University of Notre Dame in 1994. Before joining the faculty of the University of South Florida in 2005, he taught at Creighton University and the University of Iowa, where he received a College of Liberal Arts and Sciences Teaching Award in 2005. He was the Alvin Plantinga Fellow at the Center for Philosophy of Religion at Notre Dame from 2005 to 2006. Professor Williams’s research interests are in medieval philosophy and theology (with a focus on Augustine, Anselm, Aquinas, and Duns Scotus) and the philosophy of religion. He is the coauthor of Anselm, a volume in the Great Medieval Thinkers series from Oxford University Press, with Sandra Visser. He edited The Cambridge Companion to Duns Scotus and co-edited Thomas Aquinas: Disputed Questions on the Virtues. His translations include Augustine’s On Free Choice of the Will and Anselm: Basic Writings. Professor Williams has contributed essays to four other volumes in the Cambridge Companions series—Augustine; Anselm; Abelard; and Medieval Philosophy—as well as essays for the Cambridge History of Medieval Philosophy and The Oxford Handbook of Thomas Aquinas. Journals where his articles have appeared include Modern Theology, Philosophy and Literature, Apeiron, Faith and Philosophy, Journal of the History of Philosophy, and Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie. He is on the editorial board of Studies in the History of Ethics. ©2007 The Teaching Company. i Table of Contents Reason and Faith: Philosophy in the Middle Ages Part I Professor Biography...........................................................................................i Course Scope......................................................................................................1 Lecture One Faith Seeking Understanding....................................4 Lecture Two Augustine’s Platonic Background.............................9 Lecture Three Augustine on Authority, Reason, and Truth...........13 Lecture Four Augustine on the Origin of Evil..............................16 Lecture Five Boethius’s The Consolation of Philosophy.............19 Lecture Six Boethius on Foreknowledge and Freedom..............22 Lecture Seven Anselm and the 11th-Century Context.....................25 Lecture Eight Anselm’s Proof That God Exists............................28 Lecture Nine Anselm on the Divine Attributes ............................31 Lecture Ten Anselm on Freedom and the Fall............................34 Lecture Eleven Abelard on Understanding the Trinity....................37 Lecture Twelve Abelard on Understanding Redemption..................40 Timeline............................................................................................................43 Map...................................................................................................................46 Glossary............................................................................................................48 Biographical Notes...........................................................................................53 Bibliography.....................................................................................................57 ii ©2007 The Teaching Company. Reason and Faith: Philosophy in the Middle Ages Scope: The great medieval Christian thinkers would all have been bewildered by the idea, widespread in contemporary culture, that faith and reason are fundamentally at odds. Though their philosophical outlooks varied widely, they were in general agreement that philosophical reasoning could and should be used to defend and elucidate the doctrines of the Christian faith. This use of philosophy took three main forms. First, medieval thinkers used philosophical reasoning to prove the existence of God and to establish conclusions about the divine attributes. Second, they used philosophical views about the acquisition of knowledge to determine which Christian doctrines are beyond the scope of rational demonstration. And third, they used philosophical argumentation to defend Christian beliefs against objections and to establish the internal consistency of Christian doctrine by showing the compatibility of Christian beliefs that might appear to contradict each other. In making all three kinds of arguments, medieval Christian thinkers felt free to adopt the views of non- Christian philosophers when those views could be pressed into the service of Christian teaching; and they were confident that the errors of pagan philosophy could be exposed by the use of natural reason, without appealing to faith in a supernatural revelation. This general agreement about the proper roles of faith and reason provided a certain continuity in the history of medieval philosophy, but there were striking discontinuities as well. As new philosophical texts were discovered and new techniques of argumentation introduced, as philosophical schools rose to prominence or fell into eclipse, the ways in which medieval philosophers carried out their project of “faith seeking understanding” changed dramatically. For Augustine, at the beginning of the medieval period, philosophy meant Platonism, but for Thomas Aquinas, in the 13th century, it was Aristotle, not Plato, who was known simply as “the Philosopher.” Philosophers also had to cope with changing fashions in theology, not to mention simple church politics. Thus, Peter Abelard was the target of ecclesiastical harassment for making an argument that Anselm had made, without controversy, a mere half-century earlier. Medieval philosophy began with Augustine (354−430), who was deeply influenced by the fundamental Platonic distinction between the intelligible realm—perfect, unchanging, and accessible only by the mind—and the sensible realm—imperfect, ever-changing, and apprehensible by the senses. In some strands of Platonic thought, these two realms are irreconcilably at odds; the fact that our souls are embodied is a regrettable, if temporary, impediment to human fulfillment. For Augustine, however, the sensible realm is created by God and reflects his goodness. The temporal and embodied character of our experience means that we must rely on authority in our quest for truth. Nonetheless, by ©2007 The Teaching Company. 1 reflecting on the imperfections and mutability of creatures, the human mind can come to understand something of the unchanging perfection of the creator. Precisely because we come to know God as both perfect and creator, Augustine was faced with the perplexing problem of the origin of evil in a world created by a perfect God. Boethius (c. 476−c. 526), writing a century later than Augustine, continued the tradition of pressing pre-Christian philosophy into the service of Christian thought. In The Consolation of Philosophy, Boethius turns to Philosophy, personified as a woman, for comfort and reassurance that the world is justly governed by divine providence. Philosophy argues that there is one God who governs the universe and has power over all things, including human affairs. She also undertakes to show how human freedom and moral responsibility are possible, arguing that because God is eternal—that is, outside time altogether— he does not foreknow our actions (he simply knows them, timelessly) and our actions are therefore not necessary in any sense that threatens freedom or moral responsibility. For nearly 500 years after the death of Boethius, there was little noteworthy philosophical activity. In the 11th century, however, there was a revival of philosophical techniques and their application to theological discussion. The outstanding Christian philosopher of the 11th century was Anselm (1033−1109), who developed an explicit and systematic account of what he called “the reason of faith”: the intrinsically rational character of Christian doctrines in virtue of which they form a coherent and rationally defensible system. Anselm’s most famous contribution to Christian philosophy is his argument for the existence of God, but his account of the divine nature has also had an enduring influence. The leading 12th-century philosopher, Peter Abelard (1079−1142), is often thought of as a theological rebel, but in fact, he was firmly in Anselm’s tradition of elucidating and defending Christian doctrine in accordance with the standards of philosophical reasoning. His controversial treatments of the Trinity and the Atonement show a willingness to challenge received theological wisdom in the pursuit of philosophical rigor. The recovery of the full Aristotelian corpus by the end of the 12th century revolutionized Christian thought in the Latin West. Aristotle’s thinking offered a conceptual apparatus of obvious power and usefulness for philosophy and theology, but many of Aristotle’s ideas were at odds with Christian doctrine. Thirteenth-century thinkers had to figure out how to accommodate this new material. Thomas Aquinas (c. 1225−1274), using the works of Aristotle as his primary philosophical inspiration, developed arguments for the existence of God, as well as an account of the powers and limits of human reason in knowing God. He also drew on Aristotle for his understanding of human nature and ethics. By contrast, Bonaventure (c. 1217−1274) was willing to borrow Aristotelian doctrines when he found them helpful, but he argued passionately against excessive enthusiasm in following Aristotle. Such excesses were 2 ©2007 The Teaching Company. attributed to the integral Aristotelians of the University of Paris, for whom Aristotelian philosophy was a complete, freestanding account of the natural world. This engagement with Aristotelian philosophy, in all its different forms, made the 13th century a particularly lively and inventive period in Christian philosophy. This energy continued through the work of John Duns Scotus (1265/66−1308) and William Ockham (c. 1288−1347). But Aristotelianism did not remain dominant for long. Such thinkers as Nicholas of Autrecourt (c. 1295−1369) and Nicholas of Cusa (1401−1464) marked a turn away from Aristotle and toward a kind of Platonism that would become dominant during the Renaissance. ©2007 The Teaching Company. 3 Lecture One Faith Seeking Understanding Scope: The great medieval Christian thinkers would all have been bewildered by the idea, widespread in contemporary culture, that faith and reason are fundamentally at odds. Though their philosophical outlooks varied widely, they were in general agreement that philosophical reasoning could and should be used to defend and elucidate the doctrines of the Christian faith. They used philosophical reasoning to prove the existence of God and to establish conclusions about the divine attributes. They also tried to determine which Christian doctrines are beyond the scope of rational demonstration by examining philosophical views about how human beings acquire knowledge. They used philosophical argumentation to defend Christian beliefs against objections and to establish the internal consistency of Christian doctrine by showing the compatibility of Christian beliefs that might appear to contradict each other. They felt free to adopt the views of non-Christian philosophers when those views could be pressed into the service of Christian teaching, and they were confident that the errors of pagan philosophy could be exposed by the use of natural reason, without appealing to faith in a supernatural revelation. Outline I. The great medieval Christian thinkers would all have been bewildered by the idea that faith and reason, or theology and philosophy, are fundamentally at odds. For them, both the techniques and the content of philosophy are (by and large) compatible with the Christian faith. A. All of them agreed that philosophical reasoning can and should be used to defend and elucidate the doctrines of the Christian faith. 1. They used philosophical reasoning, in many cases borrowed from pagan philosophers, to prove the existence of God and to establish conclusions about the divine nature. 2. On the basis of philosophical doctrines about the nature and scope of human knowledge, they distinguished between Christian doctrines that can be known by reason alone and those that can be known only by faith. 3. They used philosophical argumentation to defend Christian beliefs against objections and to establish the internal consistency of Christian doctrine by showing the compatibility of Christian beliefs that might appear to contradict each other. B. All of these great thinkers took a generally accommodating attitude toward pagan philosophy. 4 ©2007 The Teaching Company. 1. They felt free to adopt the views of non-Christian philosophers when they could be pressed into the service of Christian teaching, as well as on matters on which Christian teaching was silent. 2. They were (in general) confident that the errors of pagan philosophy could be exposed by the use of natural reason, without the need to appeal to supernatural revelation. 3. They held that Christianity can be shown to be superior to pagan philosophy by the standards accepted by the pagan philosophers themselves. II. In spite of these broad areas of agreement, however, medieval philosophy is far from monolithic. The contours of the accommodation between faith and reason changed as particular philosophical systems and techniques came into widespread use or fell into disfavor. A. In this course, we will examine the contributions of the most influential thinkers throughout the period, both for their intrinsic philosophical importance and as illustrating the development of Christian engagement with issues of faith and reason. B. Augustine is representative of early medieval philosophy in several ways. 1. He is heavily influenced by Platonism, which was the dominant philosophical outlook well into the 12th century. 2. What Augustine takes from Platonism is not so much a set of precise doctrines or arguments but a general outlook. Thus, he is concerned more with elaborating a vision than with articulating precise reasons in support of a thesis. This more visionary or holistic approach is typical of early medieval philosophy. C. Boethius is, broadly speaking, in the same tradition as Augustine— though as the primary transmitter of philosophical logic in the early medieval period, he is more technically minded than Augustine and provides more careful support for Platonic-Augustinian theses. D. Beginning in the 11th century, philosophy becomes more focused on the development of careful argument. This development becomes even more pronounced with the reintroduction of the complete works of Aristotle in the late 12th and early 13th centuries. 1. The 11th century saw a renewed emphasis on careful argument in the service of elucidating and defending Christian doctrine. Anselm defended recognizably Augustinian views, but his method was very unlike Augustine’s: a more-or-less continuous series of precise arguments. 2. In the 12th century, Peter Abelard conceived an ambitious project of reformulating Christian doctrine in a rationally coherent way. ©2007 The Teaching Company. 5 3. The reintroduction of Aristotle in the late 12th and early 13th centuries gave Christian philosophers the materials to develop systematic theories using analytically precise and highly technical methods. At the same time, it posed new problems for the relationship between faith and reason, because Aristotle had put these methods to use in arguing for conclusions that were seen as incompatible with Christian teaching. E. Even in the period of Aristotelian dominance—the 13th and early 14th centuries—a variety of approaches to questions of faith and reason were possible. 1. Bonaventure cast traditionally Augustinian positions in Aristotelian language but generally resisted the claims of Aristotelian philosophy to provide an adequate account of the natural world, let alone the supernatural world. 2. Thomas Aquinas and John Duns Scotus largely agreed in their views about what we can know about God using the methods of Aristotelian philosophy; they also shared a generally Aristotelian view of knowledge. But they drew quite different conclusions from that view in their account of religious language. 3. William Ockham was also heavily influenced by Aristotle, but he was much more skeptical about the prospects for a purely philosophical knowledge of God. F. In the 14th century, as the Aristotelian tradition began to lose its dominating position, new philosophical stances came to the fore and, with them, new ways of understanding the relationship between faith and reason. III. Within the historical narrative just outlined, certain authors and certain topics will receive particular attention. A. Though medieval philosophers wrote on an astonishingly wide range of topics, we will consider only those that have an obvious connection with the central topic of faith and reason: 1. How, in general, do human beings come to know anything? And in light of the answer to that question, how (if at all) can human beings come to know about God apart from supernatural revelation? 2. What are the attributes of God, and how do those attributes bear on other philosophical topics? For example, can divine foreknowledge be reconciled with human free will? 3. If indeed God is unimaginably different from the objects of our ordinary experience, how can we use our language—which is derived from such experience—to talk about God? 6 ©2007 The Teaching Company. 4. Can such Christian doctrines as the Trinity, the Incarnation, and the Atonement be defended against charges of irrationality and incoherence? B. This course focuses on the history of philosophy; we will not be concerned either with matters of revealed theology or with intellectual history more broadly. 1. Revealed theology (or just theology, for short) takes some kind of supernatural revelation as its starting point, whereas philosophy takes its starting point from premises that are accessible to unaided human reason. Natural theology—the project of trying to prove the existence and nature of God by reason alone, without relying on supernatural revelation—is, thus, a part of philosophy and not of (revealed) theology. 2. The chief concern of the historian of philosophy is what people thought and what arguments they brought forward in support of what they thought, whereas the intellectual historian is more attentive to external contextual influences on what people thought. 3. Given the relative isolation of medieval philosophy from broader currents of the time, a history-of-philosophy approach is especially fitting, though we will examine broader contextual matters where appropriate. C. Though many topics receive frequent discussion throughout the period, we will concentrate on particularly influential or striking examples. 1. For example, although nearly all medieval Christian philosophers discussed the claim that God is outside of time, we will examine the discussion of the topic in Boethius’s Consolation of Philosophy, which was particularly influential. 2. Anselm and Abelard made similar arguments against a traditional theory of the Atonement, but only Abelard got into hot water for them; thus, we will consider Abelard’s discussion. Essential Reading: Stephen P. Marrone, “Medieval Philosophy in Context,” in A. S. McGrade, ed., The Cambridge Companion to Medieval Philosophy. Paul Vincent Spade, “Medieval Philosophy.” Supplementary Reading: David Knowles, The Evolution of Medieval Thought. Thomas Williams, “Some Reflections on Method in the History of Philosophy.” ©2007 The Teaching Company. 7

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.