ebook img

Readings on Edmund Husserl’s Logical Investigations PDF

223 Pages·1977·10.192 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Readings on Edmund Husserl’s Logical Investigations

READINGS ON EDMUND HUSSERL'S LOGICAL INVESTIGATIONS READINGS ON EDMUND HUSSERL'S LOGICAL INVESTIGATIONS edited by J. N. MOHANTY MAR TINUS NIJHOFF / THE HAGUE / 1977 To BANI © 1977 by Martinus NijhojJ, The Hague, Netherlands All rights reserved, including the right to translate or to reproduce this book or parts thereof in any form ISBN-13: 978-90-247-1928-0 e-ISBN-13: 978-94-010-1055-9 DOl: 10.1007/978-94-010-1055-9 CONTENTS Editor's Introduction. G. FREGE - Review of Dr. E. RusserI's Philosophy of Arithmetic 6 J. N. MOHANTY - RusserI and Frege: A New Look at their Relation- n ~. E. RUSSERL - A Reply to a Critic of my Refutation of Logical Psychologism . 33 D. WILLARD - The Paradox of Logical Psychologism: HusserI's Way Out 43 P. NATORP - qn the Question of Logical Method 55 A. NAEss - RusserI on the Apodictic Evidence of Ideal Laws 67 J. N. MOHANTY - HusserI's Thesis of the Ideality of Meanings 76 J. E. ATWELL - HusserI on Signification and Object . 83 R. SOKOLOWSKI - The Logic of Parts and Wholes in Husserl's Investigations 94 A. GURWITSCH - Outlines of a Theory of "Essentially Occasional Expressions" 112 Y. BAR-HILLEL - HusserI's Conception of a Purely Logical Grammar 128 J. M. EDIE - HusserI's Conception of 'The Grammatical' and Con- temporary Linguistics. 137 C. DOWNES - On HusserI's Approach to Necessary Truth 162 G. PATZIG - HusserI on Truth and Evidence . 179 E. HUSSERL-The Task and the Significance of the Logical Investigations 197 Suggestions for Further Reading 216 EDITOR'S INTRODUCTION I Edmund Husserl's Logische Untersuchungen is, by any standard and also by nearly common consent, a great philosophical work. Within the phenom enological movement, it is generally recognised that the breakthrough to pure phenomenology - not merely to eidetic phenomenology, but also to transcendental phenomenology - was first made in these investiga tions. But in the context of philosophy of logic and also of theory of know ledge in general, these investigations took decisive steps forward. Amongst their major achievements generally recognised are of course: the final death-blow to psychologism as a theory of logic in the Prolegomena, a new conception of analyticity which vastly improves upon Kant's, a theory of meaning which is many-sided in scope and widely ramified in its appli cations, a conception of pure logical grammar that eventually became epoch-making, a powerful restatement of the conception of truth in terms of 'evidence' and a theory of knowledge in terms of the dynamic movement from empty intention to graduated fulfillment. There are many other detailed arguments, counter-arguments, conceptual distinctions and phenomenolo gical descriptions which deserve the utmost attention, examination and assimilation on the part of any serious investigator. With the publication of J. N. Findlay's English translation of the Untersuchungen, it is expected that this work will find its proper place in the curriculum of the graduate programs in philosophy in the English speaking world. This, in its turn, it is hoped, will lead to a better and more careful appreciation of Husserl's style of philosophising as well as of the content of his philosophy. The essays in the present volume are put together with the hope of contributing to that process and providing the beginning reader, the graduate student as well as the instructor with material that bring out, both appreciatively and critically, some of the main problems and issues discussed in, and arising out of, the Untersuchungen. There are two Husserl fragments in this anthology: the first one dating 2 EDITOR'S INTRODUCTION from 1903, is a clarification by Husserl of the sense of his criticism oflogical psychologism. The second piece, dating from 1925, is taken from the Phiinomenologische Psychologie; in it Husserl looks back to the achieve ments and limitations of the Untersuchungen and in particular relates them to Brentano and Dilthey. I have also included two influential reviews of Hussert's works: Frege's review of the Philosophie der Arithmetik which is reputed to have led to Husserl's abandonment of his own psychologism (a hypothesis which I have called into question in my essay on the relation between Frege and Husserl). The second is a review of the Prolegomena by Paul Natorp, the influential Neo-Kantian of Marburg, in which Natorp seeks to bring out the extent to which the idea of a pure logic is acceptable but needs to be supplemented by the Kantian problematic. Natorp's review is often credited with having influenced the subsequent development of Husserl's thought. Two of the essays were hitherto unpublished: my "Husserl's thesis of the Ideality of Meanings" and the late Aron Gurwitsch's essay on 'essen tially occasional expressions'. I am indebted to Mrs. Alice Gurwitsch for giving me permission to include the latter piece, and to Professor Lester Embree for first drawing my attention to its existence and also for editing it for publication. For permissions to reprint the various essays in this volume, I am grateful to their respective authors as well as to the editors and/or publishers of the journals or books in which they were originally printed. II Several of the essays included in this volume are critical of Husserl, and succeed in raising problems and issues which need to be taken into account. Arne Naess, who is deeply appreciative of the Untersuchungen, nevertheless questions the claim of phenomenology to yield apodictic knowledge and asserts that every science courts the radical risk of error. Every actual science will be, according to Naess, on the "human side" of the chasm between the real and the ideal and therefore will be subject to the imper fections of the so-called factual sciences. Naess, and also Gunther Patzig, questions the claim of evidence to rule out all doubt about truth. In the words of Naess, "the ultimate meeting of human beings with the Sach verhalt" cannot effectively rule out the claim of others who do not intuit the Sachverhalt but genuinely believe that they do. Likewise Patzig argues that Husserl illegitimately moves from evidence as a phenomenal character EDITOR'S INTRODUCTION 3 of certain judgments to evidence as the consciousness of the actual truth. Patzig's criticism, developed in great detail, has the merit that it also contains an account of the rationale of Husserl's so-called idealistic tum: for Patzig, this tum corresponds to the shift from the early thesis that evidence is reducible to truth to the later thesis that truth is reducible to evidence, and this latter shift is accounted for as being due to the difficulties inherent in the earlier thesis about the relation of truth to evidence. If thus Patzig and Naess question the self-evidence" theory of truth, the paper by Downes (as also Naess's) is concerned with the theory of apodictic truth. Downes seeks to relate Husserl's conceptions of a priori and necessary truth to the contemporary analytical philosophy with which he brings out its basic general agreement. What Husserl's theory lacks is, according to him, a method for investigating the a priori. The method Husserl practises is, at its best, implicitly linguistic. Atwell calls into question the basis on which Husserl's rejection of the referential theory of meaning is grounded; yet one of the central theses of the Untersuchungen, i.e. the thesis of the ideality of meanings, rests on this rejection. With regard to the thesis of ideality, Willard emphasises the influence of Lotze on Husserl. This needed to be pointed out, in view of the widely current view as to Frege's influence: the truth would appear rather to be that both Frege and Husserl were under the influence of Lotze. Whereas Willard shows that the relation between mind (or, mental acts) and meaning, for Husserl, is one of instantiation or exemplification, one may add that Husserl seems subsequently to have rejected the treatment of meanings as species, and the relation is still one of intentionality, the ideal meaning is still the content of the act concerned. The two papers by Bar-Hillel and Edie, are concerned with one of Husserl's most seminal ideas i.e. the conception of pure logical grammar. Bar-Hillel takes Husserl to task for leaving the linguistic level and seeking to explore the realm of meanings with the help of apodictic evidence. He recognises that Husserl's basic insights (especially with regard to the two kinds of meaninglessness) can be preserved in translating his theses into the purely syntactic idiom. He gives Husserl his due as one of the first to empha sise the role played by the rules of formation in the construction of any language. But he looks upon him only as forerunner of Carnap's more mature and developed conception of logical syntax. Edie corrects some of Bar-Hillel's remarks about the fourth Investigation by taking into account the more developed conception of logical grammar to be found in the Formal and Transcendental Logic. In particular, Edie - rightly, I think - insists that unlike Carnap Husserl is concerned, not with ideal constructed 4 EDITOR'S INTRODUCTION languages, but with natural languages. While Bar-Hillel turns to Carnap to bring out the inadequacies of Husserl's seminal conception, Edie turns to transformational grammar to shed light on the Husserlian theme of a uni versal grammar. The beauty of Sokolowski's paper (whose theme has now been developed by him in a larger work, Husser/ian Meditations) is that he takes one central theme from the Untersuchungen, the relation of part and whole, and shows, very effectively, not only that it runs through and determines all the six investigations but also that it permeates the entire Husserlian phenomenol ogy. Sokolowski thus succeeds both in dispelling the belief that the investi gations are a set of disconnected enquiries and themes and in correcting the widely held belief that for the later and the more developed Husserlian phenomenology, they are of no great importance. Aron Gurwitsch builds upon Busserl's admittedly incomplete theory of 'essentially occasional expressions' as formulated in the Untersuchungen, and taking into account the phenomenon of horizontal consciousness, relates the use of such expressions to the organisational aspect with which the perceptual world presents itself and to the three orders of existence which, according to Gurwitsch, always present themselves in our experience. This essay is a good example of Gurwitsch's own style of phenomenology, and also an example of what can constructively be done on the basis of Busserl's suggestive thoughts. III The position of the Logische Untersuchungen in the total structure of Husser lian thought has been a matter of some controversy amongst phenomenol ogists. In fact, this question is part of a wider question concerning the place of philosophical reflections on logic within a phenomenological philosophy. Why is it that Husserl returned to the theme of logic ever anew? Why is it that the breakthrough to pure phenomenology came about in a work on philosophy of logic? Why is it that the first chapter of the early major work introducing pure phenomenology, the Ideas I, is devoted to what he calls "logical considerations"? The chapter from Phiinomeno logische Psychologie which is included in this anthology shows Husserl's own evaluation of the role that the logical Investigations played in the development of his thought, and of various historical influences that bore on them. But these remarks also make it clear that even if "fundamental clarity" had not been achieved in the Investigations and even if their EDITOR'S INTRODUCTION 5 subject matter was limited to logical objectivities alone along with their constitutive acts - yet the theses of the Investigations continue to be the abiding basis for the structure of Husserlian thought. As pointed out earlier, Sokolowski's work substantiates this abundantly well, especially with regard to the conceptual framework of the third investigation. But from a still broader perspective, the thematisation of logic would seem to serve two purposes for Husserlian phenomenology : Formal logic, and its correlate, formal ontology lay bare the form of the world. In this sense, the 'world' was a theme of Husserlian reflections from the right beginning. In the second place, the ideality of the logical is an important moment of the accomplishments of the life of consciousness. The constitutive function of consciousness is not grasped in its entirety as well as in one of its most essential possibilities, so long as the logical is not grasped in its ideal-objectivity and the acts constituting it are not laid bare. The same holds good also of the life-world thematic: the life-world serves as the foundation for the constitution of the higher order idealities, and the possibility of such constitution is not imposed on the life-world ab extra but is inherent in it and in fact defines it as the basis for logical and scientific thinking. The traditional question, if logical thinking distorts reality, is misconceived from the point of view of Husserlian phenomenology. For it is not the case that logic as a tool is found to be there and is taken up by human intellect to engage in its intellectual endeavors to grasp reality. That picture is misleading. Logical forms and objectivities are idealisations of life-world structures and are constituted accomplishments of the life of consciousness. They belong to the total structure of SUbjectivity and have their rightful place in it. They do not exhaust it, nor are they autonomous in the sense of being the 'first,' presuppositionless beginning. But they are not tools of distortion of misrepresentation of an alien reality. For Husserlian phenomenology, then, reflection on the theme of logic reveals the nature of the constitutive accomplishments of the life of consciousness in one of its most essential moments. Graduate Faculty of the J. N. MoHANTY New School for Social Research, New¥ork REVIEW OF DR. E. HUSSERL'S PHILOSOPHY OF ARITHMETIC* by GOTTLOB FREGE (translated by E. W. KLUGE) The author decides in the Introduction that for the time being he will con sider (only) cardinal numbers (cardinalia), and thereupon launches into a discussion of multiplicity, plurality, totality, aggregate, collection, set. He uses these words as if they were essentially synonymous; the concept of a cardinal number is supposed to be different from this. However, 1 the logical relationship between multiplicity and number (p. 9) remains somewhat obscure. If one were to go by the words "The concept of number includes the same concrete phenomena as the concept of mUltiplicity albeit only by way of the extensions of the concepts of its species, the numbers two, three, four, etc .... ," one might infer that they had the same extension. On the other hand, multiplicity is supposed to be more indeterminate and more general than number. The matter would probably be clearer if a sharper distinction were drawn between falling under a concept and subordination. Now the first thing he attempts to do is to give an analysis of the concept of multiplicity. Determinate numbers as well as the generic concept of number which presupposes them, are then supposed to emerge from it by means of determinations. Thus we are first led down from the general to the particular, and then up again. Totalities are wholes whose parts are collectively connected. We must be conscious of these parts as noticed in and by themselves. The collective connection consists neither in the contents' being simultaneously in the awareness, nor in their arising in the awareness one after another. Not even space, as all-inclusive form, is the ground of the unification. The con nection consists (p. 43) in the unifying act itself. "But neither is it the case that over and above the act there exists a relational content which is distinct • Zeitschri/t fur Philosophie und Philosophische Kritik, vol. 103 (1894), pp. 313-332. The translator's notes are indicated. E. tr. first appeared in Mind, LXXXI, 1972, pp. 321-337. Reprinted here with permission. - J. N. M. 1 Henceforth I shall take "cardinal" to be understood. - Trans.

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.