Readings in Epistemology : From Aquinas, title: Bacon, Galileo, Descartes, Locke, Berkeley, Hume, Kant author: Potter, Vincent G. publisher: Fordham University Press isbn10 | asin: 0823214931 print isbn13: 9780823214938 ebook isbn13: 9780585195551 language: English subject Knowledge, Theory of. publication date: 1993 lcc: BD161.R342 1993eb ddc: 121 subject: Knowledge, Theory of. Page iii Readings in Epistemology from Aquinas, Bacon, Galileo, Descartes, Locke, Berkeley, Hume, Kant by Vincent G. Potter Fordham University Press New York 1993 Page iv Copyright 1993 by Fordham University Press All rights reserved LC 92-45079 ISBN 0-8232-1493-1 (clothbound) ISBN 0-8232-1492-3 (paperback) Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Readings in epistemology: from Aquinas, Bacon, Galileo, Descartes, Locke, Berkeley, Hume, Kant/introduction and selection by Vincent G. Potter. 2nd ed. rev. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references. ISBN 0-8232-1493-1. ISBN 0-8232-1492-3 (pbk.) 1. Knowledge, Theory of. I. Potter, Vincent G. BD161.R342 1993 121 dc20 92-45079 CIP Printed in the United States of America Page v To MY TEACHERS who taught me to read the great philosophers respectfully but critically Page vii Contents Preface ix Introduction xi 1. Francis Bacon 1 From Novum Organum 3 2. Galileo Galilei 13 From The Assayer 15 3. René Descartes 19 From A Discourse on Method 21 From Meditations on the First Philosophy 35 4. John Locke 55 From An Essay Concerning Human Understanding 57 5. George Berkeley 109 From A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human 111 Knowledge 6. David Hume 129 From An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding 131 7. Immanuel Kant 155 From Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics 158 From Critique of Pure Reason 188 From An Answer to the Question: What is 221 Enlightenment? Appendix: St. Thomas Aquinas 229 From Summa Theologiae 232 Page ix Preface THIS COLLECTION OF READINGS was gathered to fulfill the requirements of a specific course taught at Fordham College, namely, a core course, required of all sophomores, in epistemology. The aims of the course were not only to acquaint the students with the major issues in the philosophy of knowledge, but also to introduce them to that period of European philosophical thought known as the Enlightenment. The authors presented here are mainly from the British Empiricists, with the exceptions of Descartes, "Father of modern philosophy," and Kant, the great critical synthesizer. This in no way implies that the great Rationalists of the period (Spinoza and Leibniz) are not important. The choice represents a preference for what can be covered in the limited time available within a single semester. In some ways the British Empiricists are easier for beginners to grasp; they have a peculiar inner logic of development (from Locke to Berkeley to Hume); and, finally, they have had great influence on so much of contemporary Anglo-American philosophy (for better or for worse!). I wish to thank Dr. Vincent Colapietro, my colleague in the Fordham Department of Philosophy, for his helpful suggestions in selecting texts to be included in this volume. Besides certain passages from Locke, Hume, and Kant, he recommended including something from Aquinas, Bacon, and Galileo. The short piece from Aquinas included in the Appendix makes an important point about the nature of signs as they function in cognition: namely, that they are not usually what is known but that by which or in which something is known. And this is in contrast to what seem to be the representationalist views of some Enlightenment thinkers. The excerpts from Galileo and Bacon introduce the influence of empirical science in shaping the Enlightenment and also make the famous distinction between primary and secondary sensibles which plays such an important role in Locke. I have added no footnotes and have provided Study Questions at the end of each selection simply to help focus the students' attention on the main ideas of each section. The Introduction attempts to situate these philosophers in the broader Page x historical context of Europe from the sixteenth through the eighteenth centuries. At the beginning of each author's selections, there is a brief biographical sketch and a very brief list of suggested readings. The teacher no doubt has his own preferred references adapted to the group he is teaching. Finally, I have provided no critical commentary or evaluation, with the exception of some brief and very general remarks concerning (erroneous) assumptions which the Rationalists and Empiricists of the period held in common. I leave further elaboration (or contradiction) to the teacher. Again, more specific criticism is best left to each one's own particular emphasis and point of view. In the situation in which these readings are a supplement to a regular course in epistemology, the teacher may find that covering them all is too much for this or that particular group. At Fordham the faculty decided that this course should include at least Descartes, Hume, and Kant. VINCENT G. POTTER FORDHAM UNIVERSITY Page xi Introduction THE PERIOD FROM DESCARTES TO KANT (from the end of the sixteenth to the end of the eighteenth centuries) is sometimes called the "classical" period of modern European philosophy. It extends from the close of the Renaissance through the Age of the Enlightenment. Usually the Enlightenment is said to have taken place in the eighteenth century. With the exception of Descartes (who died in 1650), each of the philosophers included in our readings lived during the eighteenth century and all (including Descartes) had decisive influence on the Enlightenment. Whether one ultimately judges the name "enlightenment" to be accurate, whimsical, or ironic will depend upon one's judgment about that period's contribution to the advancement of culture, politics, and society. More generally, the philosopher must ask whether and to what extent the new "light" advanced wisdom and mankind's love of it. In any case, regardless of what history or historians or we ourselves may think of that era, those who lived during it considered themselves "enlightened" (by what and by whom needs to be considered later) and "liberated'' (from what and for what might also bear consideration). During those two hundred years, Modern European philosophy was formed. Descartes is usually credited with beginning the "modern" philosophical movement of which the Enlightenment schools of Rationalism and Empiricism are the major expression. What the differences between these schools were will become evident in the course of our reading. What may slip by unnoticed is what their similarities were their common assumptions, substantive and methodological.
Description: