Reading Habermas in Anarchy: Multilateral Diplomacy and Global Public Spheres Author(s): Jennifer Mitzen Reviewed work(s): Source: The American Political Science Review, Vol. 99, No. 3 (Aug., 2005), pp. 401-417 Published by: American Political Science Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/30038948 . Accessed: 03/01/2012 15:31 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. American Political Science Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The American Political Science Review. http://www.jstor.org American Political Science Review Vol. 99, No. 3 August 2005 Reading Habermasi n Anarchy:M ultilateralD iplomacy and GlobalP ublic Spheres JENNIFER MITZEN Ohio State University States routinely justify their policies in interstate forums, and this reason-giving seems to serve a legitimating function. But how could this be? For Habermas and other global public sphere the- orists, the exchange of reasons oriented toward understanding-communicative action-is central to public sphere governance, where political power is held accountable to those affected. But most global public sphere theory considers communicative action only among nonstate actors. Indeed, anarchy is a hard case for public spheres. The normative potential of communicative action rests on its instability: only where consensus can be undone by better reasons, through argument, can we say speakers are holding one another accountable to reason. But argument means disagreement, and especially in anarchy disagree- ment can mean violence. Domestically, the state backstops argument to prevent violence. Internationally, I propose that international society and publicity function similarly. Public talk can mitigate the security dilemma and enable interstate communicative action. Viewing multilateral diplomacy as a legitimation process makes sense of the intuition that interstate talk matters, while tempering a potentially aggressive cosmopolitanism. How could multilateral diplomacy-"talk" and holding one another accountable to reason if agree- argument among states-legitimate state ac- ments can be undone through future argument, each tion? Scholars, practitioners, and the broader consensus must remain contingent. That is, in its ideal public commonly link an international action's legit- form, argument has the power to undo and remake imacy to the multilateral diplomacy that surrounded social consensus. Yet this power can by its nature lead it. NATO's intervention in Kosovo is widely perceived to violence. In fact, argument is usually a precursor to as legitimate, in large part because of the arguments violence, suggesting that argumentative processes face advanced in the diplomacy before and immediately a potentially slippery slope. Without some constraint after (Johnstone 2004); conversely, the American-led to keep actors committed to resolving their disagree- coalition's Iraq War is widely perceived as illegitimate ments discursively, argument can spill over from the in part because of the way the United States conducted conference table to the street, or even to the battle- its multilateral diplomacy (Rubin 2003). In short, we field. To sustain argumentative legitimation, then, an take for granted that public, interstate talk matters environment must be able to contain the instability of for legitimacy; it is part of our common sense about communicative action. It must permit argument while contemporary world politics. guarding against the potential that argument will de- The problem is that it is not clear how talk could mat- generate into violence. ter for legitimation in an anarchic system, because ar- This makes anarchy a hard case for the propo- gument is an inherently unstable social practice. As de- sition that public talk could legitimate state action. veloped especially by Jiirgen Habermas (1984, 1996), Habermas conceptualizes communicative action in the argument may be defined as the exchange of reasons context of a consolidated democratic state, which by participants who are oriented to reaching consensus blocks the slippery slope to violence. But anarchy lacks and remain open to changing their minds if faced with any such centralized prevention of violence, and as such better reasons. Habermas links argument normatively the slippery slope from argument to violence is very to communicative action, the promise of which is that much in force. Unlike the domestic case, in anarchy consensus resulting from argument will be for the right there is no easy answer to Bent Flyvbjerg's (1998, 80) reasons, i.e., reasons that are good for the collective and question, "Why use the force of the better argument not simply for the most powerful. Importantly, how- when force alone will suffice?" In short, if in anarchy ever, this normative potential rests on a fundamental argument can easily descend into violence, how could instability. Since it only is possible to say speakers are the multilateral diplomacy surrounding the Iraq War, or any interstate talk, be anything other than cheap, a rhetorical veneer to interests and power, incapable Jennifer Mitzen, Assistant Professor, Ohio State University, 2140 Derby Hall, 154 North Oval Mall, Columbus, OH 43210-1373, of "legitimating" anything? [email protected]. Despite the problems with argument in anarchy, in For comments on previous drafts, many thanks go to James recent years a substantial literature has emerged in Bohman, Cosette Creamer, George Gavrilis, Yoram Haftel, Patrick both normative and explanatory theory on argument Jackson, Hans-Martin Jaeger, Zack Kertcher, Andrew Linklater, Patchen Markell, Anthony McGrew, Amanda Metskas, Lee and communicative action in world politics. Norma- Sigelman, Lisa Wedeen, Nick Wheeler, Iris Young, and especially tive theorists have become interested in global public Michael Neblo and Alexander Wendt. Earlier versions were pre- spheres, discursive structures that enable communica- sented at the University of Chicago's Globalization Workshop, tive action beyond state borders. Global public spheres the International Studies Association Conference, New Orleans, hold out the prospect that democratic self-governance, Louisiana, March 2002, and the British International Studies As- sociation Conference, London, England, December 2002. governance that aims for the collective good, could 401 Reading Habermas in Anarchy August 2005 extend to a scale beyond anything humankind has lic sphere. I illustrate the theoretical claims with an known before. Importantly, however, in this work le- example from the Concert of Europe, a case which, gitimation is assumed to take place only among cit- while by no means a fully realized public sphere, is not izens and directed toward states, rather than among as strange for public sphere theory as it might seem. states themselves. It is a vertical, not a horizontal, pro- In conclusion I consider the implications of viewing cess. The interstate dimension plays at most an order- multilateral diplomacy as a legitimation process by sug- ing role, not a legitimating one (e.g., Bohman 1999; gesting how it might affect an analysis of the diplomacy Habermas 1997).1 In contrast, building especially on surrounding the Iraq War. the work of Thomas Risse (2000), empirical theorists of international relations (IR) (e.g., Mtiller 2001; Payne 2001) and international law (Brun6e and Toope 2000; THE GLOBAL GOVERNANCE TWO-STEP Johnstone 2004), have begun to examine interstate ar- gument as a legitimation process. But this literature Confronting the limitations of nation-state democ- on the would-be horizontal dimension of global public racy in conditions of globalization, Habermas (1998, spheres has not come to grips with the difficulty of 2001) and other theorists argue that it is necessary containing argument in anarchy. The institutional pre- today to think in terms of state-transcending-global requisites for horizontal public spheres have not been or cosmopolitan-rather than just national public theorized, and so it is difficult in the end to fully accept spheres.2 This new thinking faces the challenge of that public, interstate argument could legitimate state containing communicative instability, or maintaining action. a context that can permit new and better arguments In my view there are two reasons to consider mul- to emerge without constantly threatening to descend tilateral diplomacy as a dimension of global public into violence. In Habermas' domestic theory, the state's sphere legitimation. Empirically, excluding interstate centralized power plays this crucial role by protect- talk does not make sense of our intuitions that multilat- ing physical safety. Of course, it matters normatively eral diplomacy "matters." If talk in IR is always cheap, whether the state is democratic or authoritarian, and then it is not clear why states would bother to talk at all. some states have no public spheres whatsoever. But Normatively, excluding multilateral diplomacy strips it the existence of a state-a solution to the Hobbe- and the institutions of the states system that enable it of sian problem-is never in question. Argumentative value. If talk in IR cannot legitimate, then it is not clear practices might democratize an authoritarian state why states should bother to talk. Moreover, as we shall (Habermas 1994b), but they never threaten to throw see, excluding multilateral diplomacy permits, if not the population back to the state of nature. This sug- encourages, a potentially aggressive cosmopolitanism. gests what could be called "two-step" reasoning about With these stakes in mind, I confront the slippery global public spheres (cf. Legro 1996). All governance slope of anarchy to conceptualize multilateral diplo- requires both social order and legitimation. When the- macy as the horizontal dimension of global public orized as a two-step, order is considered to be supplied spheres. I propose that, in the contemporary interna- separately or exogenously from legitimation. This is tional system, the instability of communicative action not necessarily bad. Indeed for domestic public sphere is contained by what I call the "forum effects of talk," theory it may make sense to bracket state consolidation which thereby make horizontal argumentative legiti- and assume social order. But in anarchy we cannot so mation possible. The forum effects are sustained by easily take order for granted. The instability of commu- the institutions of international society and by pub- nicative action thus poses more of a problem for global licity, where publicity refers to both opportunities for public spheres, which suggests that two-step reasoning face-to-face engagement and a more mediated visi- would be counterproductive at this level. In this sec- bility made possible by communications technologies. tion, focusing especially on Habermas, I first show how Extant global public sphere theory tends to focus on the state contains the instability of communicative ac- the latter, which has expanded the nonstate audience tion in the domestic context, and then examine extant of state behavior. I focus instead on face-to-face vis- strategies for stabilizing communication in the interna- ibility among states, which in the form of conference tional context. In each strategy, the production of order diplomacy was introduced to the system in the early precedes and remains separate from legitimation. Even nineteenth century when the European Great Pow- where global public spheres rest on interstate coopera- ers decided to jointly manage the balance of power. tion, only arguments by nonstate actors can legitimate The upshot is that global public spheres have two le- state power. Interstate dynamics are associated, at best, gitimation dynamics: a widely recognized vertical one with the production of order. centered on the practices of cosmopolitan citizens and transnational nonstate actors, and a neglected horizon- tal one among states, which I call an "interstate" pub- 2 Global public sphere terminology varies. To simplify, I use "global" to refer to all state-transcending public spheres and propose that 1 I focus on Habermasian theory, but there also is a Deweyian strand global public spheres are characterized by two levels: "transnational" of global public sphere theory (e.g., Cochran 2002), some of which public spheres, constituted by vertical, critical dynamics among non- incorporates interstate processes (e.g., Brunkhorst 2002). Still, the state actors, and "international" public spheres constituted by hori- majority of even that work stresses vertical legitimation. zontal dynamics among states. 402 American Political Science Review Vol. 99, No. 3 Communicative Action in Domestic Governance through public reason is demanding. Public Spheres First, speakers must recognize one another's commu- nicative competence and grant each other the right Communicative action, or the exchange of reasons to disagree. Second, they must approach interaction oriented toward understanding, is the heart of pub- with an orientation to listen-to reflect on others' ar- lic sphere theory. Communicative action builds from guments rather than simply coerce them or engage in the premise that reason is intersubjectively constituted violence. That is, they must commit to the process of and inheres in linguistic communication. In every- argument, which means they will not let the fact of dis- day utterances, speakers raise validity claims-claims agreement destroy the group (Habermas 1984, 36-37; about what is objectively true or morally right for the Habermas 1996, 20-21; White 1994, 35 ff.). With these group-and there is a tacit, shared expectation that, if in mind, it is easy to see that public sphere governance challenged, a speaker can offer acceptable reasons. The places strict demands on the social environment where exchange of validity claims constitutes the process of argument takes place. Perhaps the most minimal con- argument, and consensus resulting from such argument dition is that speakers feel confident of their physical is the ideal form of social integration. Habermas devel- safety. Where individuals face the constant risk of vi- ops this idea to counter the pessimistic, Weberian nar- olence they cannot reflect or listen, much less argue; rative of modernity as the triumph of strategic action all energy is consumed with securing survival (Mitzen and instrumental, technical rationality. For Habermas, n.d.). The public sphere environment must therefore modernity also has given rise to a new emancipatory encourage the orientation to listen, which means that, potential for self-governance based on reason in public while permitting disagreement, it must also somehow spheres. contain it, preventing disagreement from spilling over Communicative action embodies an inherent tension into violence. between social acceptance, or stability, and validity. On Habermas argues that the best environment for pub- the one hand, it can generate stable consensus: a posi- lic spheres is a vast reserve of shared background tive response to a validity claim creates an agreement knowledge. He calls the sphere of interaction organized on a fact and "obligations relevant to future interac- around such consensual knowledge a lifeworld, and tion" (Habermas 1996, 20). But validity claims also includes institutions such as religion and the family, always point beyond a particular context. Because moral norms, and cultural practices. This "culturally ideally, communicative agreements are supported by familiar," unproblematic environment helps "explain the "best" reasons, any achieved agreement must re- how the daily process of consensus building is time main open to "better" reasons in the future. Through and again able to cross the threshold of the risk of dis- social learning and change, over time some reasons sent" (cited in Mtiller 2001, 169). A shared normative can become obsolete. Only where argument can undo context provides safety by giving decision makers the previous agreements is it possible to say speakers are motivation for self-restraint and citizens the motivation holding one another accountable to reason. to participate rather than withdraw or rebel. Histori- In public sphere theory, the public's communica- cally, lifeworld contexts were so fully internalized by tive action, which Habermas calls public reason, can members as to be rarely reflected on. But modernity hold material or social power accountable. In so do- has rationalized them, i.e., differentiated social life in ing, public reason is not just a "check" on material such a way that aspects of the tacit background consen- power but changes its nature. Insofar as political power sus can be brought into public light and debated. This justifies its use according to public reason, therefore, means they can become subject to collective reason and one can say that political power has been drawn out the force of better arguments. Rationalization makes from its material locale and lodged in the communica- public spheres possible by maintaining the safety of the tive power of those affected. This is the emancipatory lifeworld while injecting new potential for reflection promise of public sphere theory. To attain that promise, and argument. public spheres in practice have two dimensions or The problem is that rationalized lifeworlds do not "tracks" (Habermas 1996, chap. 8). The informal or form a thick basis for modern political groups. In- "critical"p ublic sphere is characterized by a vertical dy- stead, modern groups are characterized primarily by namic of subjects holding decision makers accountable; complexity and pluralism. Markets, bureaucracies, and Habermas calls it a "transmission belt" of social powerful political systems embed individuals in a com- concerns to decision-making bodies. The formal or plex web of relations they are not fully aware of decision-making sphere, in contrast, is characterized and cannot extricate themselves from. In one sense by a horizontal dynamic; it exists once a state has this behind-the-back integration is useful: markets and a parliament or congress, which infuses the decision- bureaucracies maintain social cohesion in contexts making process itself with reason giving and justifi- where members would otherwise be "overburdened cation (Fraser 1992).3 In a functioning public sphere, in their efforts at reaching understanding" (Habermas public reason is salient both outside formal decision- 1996, 38). But markets and bureaucracies tend to ex- making bodies and within them. pand and, unlike lifeworlds, neither requires a commu- nicative consensus to function. As these systems come to structure more of social life, Habermas argues that they can squeeze out the potential for public reason. In 3 Fraser (1992) uses "weak" and "strong" to refer to critical and decision-making public spheres. addition, members of modern political groups do not 403 Reading Habermas in Anarchy August 2005 generally share thick lifeworld bonds; they are pation. Thus, not all states can sustain public spheres. "strangers." Strangers might not see consensus as de- Still, the state's centralized enforcement is essential to sirable; they might not recognize one another as ca- the logic. Although the stability law provides differs pable of communicative consensus at all, much less be from that of the lifeworld-its link to communicative willing to listen and reflect on each other's arguments. action is "artificially" produced by sanctions rather Among strangers, the potential for violence is harder than "organic(ally)" produced by "inherited forms of to contain. Indeed, it can be so close to the surface that life" (1996, 30)-Habermas argues that its capacity to argument becomes impossible. Even if an individual secure communicative action and the capacity to com- wants to listen, it is impossible to know the other's pel compliance are as internally or logically related as intentions, and so each claim raised by each side in they are in lifeworld contexts. "A force that otherwise argument raises the specter of violence. stands opposed to the socially integrating force of com- In the modern context, then, sustaining the poten- munication (i.e., centralized coercion) is, in the form of tial for public reason is a serious challenge. Habermas legitimate coercion, thus converted into the means of offers two responses. First, he argues that politi- social integration itself" (1996, 462). In short, the state's cal deliberation should be modeled as a mix of enforcement power is crucial to making public reason moral, ethical, and pragmatic discourses (1996, 165-7). possible in modern political life.4 In political deliberation, decision makers first deter- This emphasis on centralized enforcement might just mine whether to address a given question through be an artifact of the domestic origins of public sphere moral or ethical argument, or through bargaining. The theory. In Habermas' ([1962] 1994b) historical narra- latter is valid where participants determine that no tive, public spheres emerged within existing European general interest or shared value is at stake. Bargain- states with the express purpose of democratizing them. ing is of course not communicative action: here, social It is then no surprise that Habermas' template for power is not "neutralized" but manifest in threats and public spheres assumes a context in which enforce- promises. Still, bargaining can be "fair," and this crite- ment is possible. Still, the role of state enforcement in rion maintains the link between political deliberation Habermas' account is significant for two reasons. First, and moral discourse. If bargaining procedures are de- it analytically separates the production of order from liberative and justifiable in moral discourse, as long the production of legitimacy, making domestic pub- as their outcomes are contingent, then "understanding lic sphere theory reliant on two-step reasoning. Public beyond instrumental-rational agreement is possible" spheres require an already-existing centralized power. (2001, 109). In short, fair bargaining is a normative The theory brackets how that enforcement capacity is achievement, implying deliberation that is constrained formed and reproduced and instead studies its role in by norms. Fair bargaining means that, even in condi- making legitimation possible. Second, Habermas con- tions of complexity and pluralism, political deliberation trasts enforced modern law to customary premodern maintain the normative potential of communicative law and does not consider the possibility of a law in action. modernity that lacks centralized enforcement. This has Second, Habermas anchors public spheres in law, important consequences for how he theorizes global by which he means positive law, law that is legislated public spheres, in effect ruling out a priori the possibil- and enforced. Law is unique in its capacity to convert ity that international law might stabilize social life in normative ideals to social facts. This is because, for an analogous way to enforced law. one, legal rules share the instability of communicative action by maintaining the potential for a gap between Communicative Action in Global the socially accepted rules and the best rules. Although Public Spheres invoked in a particular context, legal rules always point beyond that context to a larger, general interest that The challenge for global public spheres is how to con- can be rendered in moral terms as the common good tain the instability of communicative action where ar- (Bohman 1994, 899; Habermas 1984, 81, 178). But posi- gument is not backstopped by either a shared lifeworld tive law contains this instability, lessening the potential or positive law. Extrapolating directly from the do- that argument will spill over into violence, because law mestic context, global public spheres would require is centrally enforced and as such exists irrespective of world government: a supersovereign power capable whether citizens legitimate it in a particular instance. of enforcing cosmopolitan law. Although at times The legal system therefore can be seen as a safety net Habermas' writings in the 1990s suggest this as a dis- for communicative action. Enforcement allows "con- tant but hopeful possibility, two other strategies for victions to be replaced by sanctions in that it leaves maintaining order figure more prominently in his work the motives for rule compliance open while enforcing and that of other global public sphere theorists: the obedience" (Habermas 1996, 38, 448-9). democratic peace and international regimes (including Habermas' analysis of law is complex and nuanced, international organizations). These three strategies are and certainly he is not arguing that its enforcement not mutually exclusive. Outlining how each operates in (facticity) trumps or opposes its legitimacy (validity). Habermas' theory, it becomes clear that, even as the Indeed, he argues that law can only anchor public spheres if it is democratically generated and if its con- 4 The argument is not without criticism; some commentators ques- tents protect the preconditions for communicative ac- tion whether this template sacrifices the radical potential of public tion such as the rights to privacy, equality, and partici- sphere theory, e.g., Bohman (1994). 404 American Political Science Review Vol. 99, No. 3 positivity condition is relaxed, two-step reasoning per- The Democratic Peace. A second strategy to anchor sists. Because it lacks enforcement, the anarchic world global public spheres, also found in Habermas and of states is seen as a dangerous balance of power where echoed by other theorists (e.g., Bohman 1999; Erikson the most we can hope for is order, not legitimation. and Fossum 2000), is through the spread of liberal Multilateral diplomacy, if factored in at all, is consigned democracy at the national level. In one sense this is an to the realm of order production and plays no role in aggregative logic: public spheres are a democratic ideal, legitimation, which is theorized in purely vertical terms. and so spreading democracy expands public spheres. As democracy spreads, citizen-based associations and Global Positive Law. One strategy for global public nongovernmental organization achieve greater roles spheres suggested by Habermas is to expand positive and reach across boundaries, giving cosmopolitan law at the international level. The premise is that, values increasing prominence (Bohman 1997, 196-7; globally as much as domestically, the protection of Habermas 1997, 125). Such groups and linkages can individual human rights is necessary to contain com- grow only where citizens have political voice and free- municative instability. Because the state is often the dom of association, rights that are associated with lib- culprit in human rights violations, citizens need to be eral democracy. Liberal political culture is the "ground able to make claims against their states, which global in which the institutions of freedom put down their positive law can help ensure. As in the domestic case, roots" and "medium" to achieve that progress, and enforcement is crucial. Therefore, a global "executive can only be forged globally through the proliferation power" is needed to intervene authoritatively where of democratic states (Habermas 1997, 125; Habermas human rights violations have occurred. "The commu- 2001, 111-12). Moreover, the proliferation of states nity of peoples must at least be able to hold its members that enforce democratic rights at the domestic level to legally appropriate behavior through the threat of translates to less need for global enforcement. sanctions. Only then will the unstable system of states But sovereignty complicates any simple aggregation asserting their sovereignty through mutual threat be of national into global public spheres, because, irre- transformed into a federation whose common institu- spective of a state's regime type, as a sovereign state it tions take over state functions: it will legally replace must survive in the competitive, potentially dangerous the relations among its members and monitor their environment of anarchy. As such, expanding the num- compliance with its rules" (1997, 127). ber of democratic states can only create global public Habermas recognizes that a world of enforced in- spheres if the competitive dynamics among states can dividual rights is a long way off. The contemporary be dampened. With this in mind, global public sphere United Nations' (UN's) hybrid status as an institution theory invokes the democratic peace, the finding in premised on both sovereignty and human rights means IR scholarship that democracies tend not to fight one that currently it can have only the minimal agenda of another (e.g., Doyle 1986). Because democracies can preventing war and reacting to human rights abuses be counted on not to fight, they form a "zone of (2001, 107-8). Still, the organization can be strength- peace," the semblance of a transnational community ened. He calls for a stronger UN with a military force (e.g., Bohman 1997, 180-1; Habermas 1998). Indeed, to implement decisions and UN reform to expand the this work tends to associate the spread of democracy role of the Security Council and strengthen the Inter- with deeper, more durable interstate cooperation in national Criminal Court (1999a: 268). An improved all issue areas (see also Slaughter 1995). At the same UN would serve as one leg of a system of multilevel time, between democracies and nondemocracies there governance analogous to the European Union (1998). remains a balance-of-power world where peaceful in- If foreign policy is the realm of unregulated violence, tentions of others cannot be assumed (Habermas 1997, and domestic policy the realm of rights and regulation, 131-2). then the new era would be one of "multilaterally coor- Importantly, Habermas interprets the democratic dinated world domestic policy" (1994a, 23-4). peace as rooted in purely internal or domestic dynam- Two aspects of this argument stand out. First, if ics: cosmopolitan citizens of liberal democracies can- global public spheres ultimately require global positive not be mobilized for war against fellow democracies law, then sovereignty and the states system would seem (1997, 120-1). The peace is therefore induced verti- to be problems to be overcome in global governance cally, by civil societies holding their decision makers rather than essential to its legitimation. Indeed, Haber- accountable, which happens as publics of individual mas' proposals to strengthen the UN would effectively states incorporate "higher order value orientations" end state sovereignty, with increased centralization of into their preferences and press leaders to pursue those military/executive, legislative, and judicial powers at values (1999b, 451-2). Moreover, like the peace, deep the global level. Second, the argument extrapolates di- cooperation more generally among democracies also rectly from the domestic template, which means that has unit level roots. Democracies cooperate well inter- like domestic public sphere theory it brackets how en- nationally because each individually is committed to forcement power is consolidated. Enforcement capac- the rule of law and tends to comply with agreements. ity might expand as a result of deliberative processes, When both parties to an agreement have a domestic as in UN reform. But it could also happen through political culture encouraging compliance, compliance imposition or force, and the use of military force to is more likely. This means the democratic peace, and expand the sphere of enforced rights can be hard for interdemocratic cooperation, need not be consciously others to distinguish from liberal imperialism. constructed or sustained by international institutions. 405 Reading Habermas in Anarchy August 2005 It certainly is true that the spread of demo- Interstate Regimes. Habermas' third strategy to con- cratic regimes would strengthen already-existing pub- tain the instability of communicative action in anarchy, lic spheres, insofar as it would guarantee conditions and perhaps the most popular among other theorists of communication for more individuals than currently (e.g., Bohman 1999; Linklater 1998; Lynch 1999), ex- are able to participate. But because of anarchy and amines public sphere formation in the context of in- sovereignty it is not clear that spreading democracy ternational institutions or "regimes" (Krasner 1983), could create, or that the existence of democracies alone where participating states ideally are, but may not be, could sustain, conditions for global communicative ac- democracies. The strategy builds on the neo-utilitarian tion. In fact, three aspects of the democratic peace logic of rationalist IR regime theory, which shows suggest that it ought not be taken as a necessary pre- how cooperation can emerge in anarchy among self- condition for global public spheres. interested states (e.g., Keohane 1984; Ruggie 1998). First, it is not clear that the democratic peace is But rather than focus on how institutions mitigate the necessary to solve the problem of war. For example, security dilemma, the focus of IR literature, Habermas it is not the case that liberal states maintain a zone of and others stress that, by broadening the audience of peace while nonliberal states inhabit a realist world. state behavior, these interstate institutions can become Stable interstate peace has evolved among states locales for the transnational exchange of reasons and of various regime types, starting in the nineteenth- opinion formation. As Bohman (1999: 500) puts it, century Concert of Europe, and interstate war has regimes provide a "practical foothold" and potential declined systemwide since 1945. Second, as Jos6 infrastructure for cosmopolitan democracy. Insofar as Alvarez (2001, 200 ff.) argues, the zone-of-peace they bring nongovernmental organizations into inter- argument implies greater compliance with interna- state bargaining processes, for example, citizens can tional law among democratic states than in cooper- increasingly hold states accountable for actions on the ation among states of mixed regime types. But the international as much as the domestic stage. empirical record shows that regime type matters lit- But whereas this work acknowledges an important tle for compliance: liberal states are not necessar- role for states in global public spheres in making cos- ily more law-abiding. Finally, relying on a specifically mopolitan democracy possible, it retains two-step rea- unit-level explanation of the democratic peace to an- soning. States themselves provide only order, not legit- chor global public spheres maintains two-step reason- imation. Indeed, for Habermas, international regimes ing, where order is produced separately from legiti- are barely one step removed from the power politics mation. Then, because the order-production logic is of a Hobbesian state of nature. In his words, state de- independent of the states system, it is easy to fo- cisions in organizations such as the World Trade Or- cus solely on bottom-up processes and delegitimate ganization and World Bank are no more than " 'naked' horizontal practices and norms such as multilateral compromise formation that simply reflects back the es- diplomacy. sential features of classical power politics; such commu- Importantly, whereas Habermas relies on a unit-level nication cannot reflect or develop any 'thick' commu- causal explanation for the democratic peace, there is nicative embeddedness" (2001, 109). Even Bohman, in fact a debate in IR about whether the democratic who builds more explicitly from IR's regime theory, peace is rooted in unit- or system-level dynamics. Other essentially comes to the same conclusion that inter- versions of the democratic peace stress systemic fac- state decision making is not linked to communicative tors rather than just internal ones (e.g., Cederman action. Thus, whereas domestic public spheres have 2001). Moreover, it certainly is plausible that inter- two dimensions, vertical and horizontal, global public national law itself helps cause the democratic peace, spheres are characterized only by a vertical dimension. because it is not clear if democracies would behave Interestingly, this strategy for anchoring global pub- peacefully toward each other in a world without it. lic spheres renders political bargaining and compro- Note that this is not a question of whether we can mise among states fundamentally different than at the trust the democratic peace as a real empirical phe- domestic level. As we have seen, at the domestic level nomenon, an issue about which there also is a great Habermas accepts that political deliberation is charac- deal of controversy (e.g., Rosato 2003). The issue for terized as much by bargaining and compromise as it is global public sphere theory is, granting the democratic by argument and moral discourse, but argues that "fair peace, how should we explain it? A unit-level explana- bargaining" maintains a connection to communicative tion treats international law and multilateral diplomacy action and as such is part of public spheres. He does not, as irrelevant whereas a system-level explanation does however, extend this reasoning to interstate bargain- not. ing. Habermas acknowledges that "normative framing In other words, as long as sovereignty remains, the conditions" might shape a state's "choice of rhetoric" choice to ground global public spheres in a unit-level and help structure international negotiations, but the logic that depends on state regime type has the impli- origin of those framing conditions is not clear. Indeed, cation of excluding nondemocratic states from global since he stresses the close link between interstate talk governance. This does little to ground communicative and balance-of-power politics, it would seem that any action between democratic and nondemocratic states norms states follow rhetorically would have to be de- and is vulnerable to the suggestion that forceful inter- rived from and aimed at domestic audiences alone. For vention by existing democracies to create democratic Habermas (2001, 71), communicative action cannot regimes is always justified. take place among states, particularly where states do 406 American Political Science Review Vol. 99, No. 3 not share regime type. International agreements simply question. But, in fact, it is hard to keep order and legit- cannot have legitimating force and can never rise above imation so distinct. Every social order is intimately tied compromise. to legitimation processes, because durable order always Building global public spheres from international rests on a consensus regarding the truth of particular regimes is not itself problematic; indeed my account value claims. Because authoritative decisions implicate of global public spheres similarly begins by examin- these values, legitimation processes always either sup- ing efforts at interstate cooperation. The error is to port or undermine order. This suggests the need to exclude such cooperation from public sphere dynam- look beyond the two-step for other ways to contain ics and conclude that global legitimation processes are communicative instability in global governance. That purely vertical. The problems with that conclusion mir- search, in turn, leads back to the states system. ror those with the democratic peace. First, it maintains two-step reasoning, attributing two separate logics to the production of order and legiti- INTERNATIONAL PUBLIC SPHERES mation at the global level. But note that, again, this two-step rests on a particular, in this case rational- Unlike global public sphere theorists, a number of IR ist, interpretation of cooperation's causes and dynam- scholars have been viewing regimes as sites for com- ics. In fact, as with the democratic peace, there is a municative action (e.g., Ellis 2002; Samhat and Payne debate in IR about how to best understand interna- 2003) and persuasion (e.g., Checkel 2001; Johnston tional regimes. Rather than adopt utilitarian logics that 2001). A few have explicitly explored the preconditions maintain broadly realist assumptions, many IR schol- for communicative action among states (e.g., Miller ars assume that states interact in a normatively much 2001; Risse 2000) and even the possibility of Haber- thicker environment-an international society, culture, masian discourse ethics on a global scale that includes or even a community (e.g., Kratochwil 1989; Wendt dialogue among states (e.g., Linklater 1998). None, 1999). This constructivist approach to regimes sees the however, has directly confronted the instability of com- day-to-day rhetorical practices among states in regimes municative action and the problem of violence it raises, as largely communicative, which suggests the possibil- nor has this work moved beyond two-step reasoning to ity of horizontal legitimation, whereas a utilitarian ap- establish structural conditions for international public proach does not. Second, excluding interstate linguistic spheres. Indeed, the difficulty of containing commu- processes from global public spheres scales back their nicative action in anarchy is a strong theoretical chal- emancipatory potential, because, unlike parliaments lenge to this literature. Anarchy is a harder case for in the domestic case, here global decision making it- communicative action than the literature has acknowl- self does not get democratized. If globally there are edged. Even where states want cooperation, it is hard to at most critical publics emerging from civil societies, secure. A major impediment is mistrust at a structural public reason has at most a reactive, countersteering level: the security dilemma. States cannot be sure of role.5 one another's intentions, and they draw on the same Why is it so difficult for Habermasian global public repertoire of actions to defend themselves as they do sphere theorists to see multilateral diplomacy as a way to aggress. The security dilemma is particularly rele- to legitimate state action? The answer might be nor- vant where legitimation is achieved through argument. mative: they might feel sovereignty is outmoded and How can states argue freely, remaining confident of one ought not anchor global governance. It might be inad- another's nonviolent intentions? The need to contain vertent: they may be simply transposing the existing the instability of communicative action is a reminder public sphere template onto the international environ- not to simply assume public spheres are possible in ment without thinking about the distinctive problems anarchy. of anarchy. Or it might be philosophical: they might With this in mind I develop the conditions of possi- object to the notion that a corporate actor like the state bility for communicative action in anarchy. Public in- could engage even in principle in communicative action terstate talk contains the instability of communicative (see Wendt 2004). It is hard to say, because none of this action. My argument has two elements: a thick notion work treats the issue explicitly. It is simply assumed that of international society, and publicity. First, commu- states cannot engage in communicative action. Into this nicative action requires reliable expectations of nonvi- silence, I have offered a principled reason for the ex- olence among participants who recognize each another clusion of states from public sphere theory, rooted in as equals. Providing a snapshot of developments in core public sphere theory itself, which unifies the literature institutions of international society-international law, and suggests a pathway toward a solution. Namely, the the balance of power, and diplomacy-I argue that, need to contain communicative instability leads theo- between the Peace of Westphalia in 1648 and the rists to two-step reasoning. Where order is produced in Congress of Vienna in 1814, a horizontal normative a different sphere than legitimation, legitimation can order evolved in international politics that organized fail without necessary repercussions for social order: and regulated the use of violence. But this normative the ability to keep the conversation going is never in order is not enough. In the second section I therefore develop the role of publicity in the form of face-to- face, multilateral conference diplomacy. Talking in a 5 Given the empirical preconditions for nonstate actors to have voice public forum produces order while keeping the foun- in these sites, only a privileged fraction of world citizens have even this reactive power (see Fine and Smith 2003). dations of that order open to rational debate. While 407 Reading Habermas in Anarchy August 2005 today interstate forums are taken for granted in global idea of universal Christiandom, and after Westphalia governance, in fact this tool was introduced into the "Europe" increasingly replaced it in diplomatic dis- system only with the Concert of Europe.6 I use that course. Secularization was evident in international case to illustrate the general argument that, in com- treaties: religious oaths and references to natural law bination with international society, the forum effects declined in eighteenth-century legal texts, and states of talk sustain international public spheres. Locating increasingly relied on pragmatic guarantees of various the origins of international public spheres in the com- sorts (unilateral, mutual, third party) rather than reli- municative practices of nineteenth-century autocrats gious ones (Bull 1977, 33; Satow 1925). There still was might seem counterintuitive; I defend my use of the a sense of belonging to a "whole" in whose name all case in what follows. The explanatory argument lays diplomacy was aimed, but that whole was increasingly the groundwork for a normative claim about the role of a secular, European "system" whose stability was se- horizontal legitimation in global governance, removing cured through mutual toleration. the strongest theoretical reason to exclude the states The institution of the state's corporate personal- system from global public spheres. ity was the basis of the doctrine of pacta sunt ser- vanda (sanctity of agreements) which, by obligating the state irrespective of changes in regime, permitted long- International Society term contracting (Anderson 1993, 40; Dunn 1929, 9). The conventional wisdom about the contemporary in- Major legal theorists such as Grotius (1583-1645) in ternational system is that it was created by the Peace the seventeenth-century and Vattel (1714-1767) in the of Westphalia in 1648, which divided Europe into in- eighteenth-century treated states more than individu- dependent sovereign units. From here, interpretations als as the core rights-bearing units in the system. In of anarchy vary considerably. Like many realists in addition, states were increasingly seen as sovereign or IR, Habermas (1999a, 1999b) treats anarchy as es- autonomous rather than penetrated by other authori- sentially norm-free, and the balance of power as the ties. Juridical autonomy gained ground as the premise system's underlying, even natural, logic, making war of diplomacy and politics. For example, as early as the and strategic competition endemic. But this reflects a Utrecht peace negotiations in 1713, precedence con- historically stunted view of Westphalia. First, the ex- cerns were subordinated to pragmatic ones (Osiander plicit goal of that settlement was to mitigate violence. 1994, 108). Respect for monarchical supreme authority Contemplating the devastation of the Thirty Years inside the state was rationalized increasingly through War, sovereigns sought better tools to counter drives the developing framework of positive law, where law for continental hegemony. The solution that they hit is understood as the will or command of the sovereign on, mutual recognition of sovereignty or "anarchy," backed by threat of sanction. Because by definition no was an effort to remove religion as a cause of war. sovereign could be made to obey another, autonomy Second, after Westphalia, institutions to further reg- meant that international law would have to be based ulate violence deepened and became increasingly ra- on consent. Autonomy also meant that sovereigns re- tionalized. I cannot explore the emergence of interna- tained the exclusive right to judge their own case and tional society in detail here (see Osiander 1994), but thus to take the law into their own hands by waging overall these trends mirrored those Habermas ([1962] war (Bull 1977, 28-32; Duchhardt 2000, 283-9). Con- 1994b) describes at the domestic level-the differentia- centrating the right to act-to contract, sign treaties, tion of political practices from an overarching Christian wage war-reduced uncertainty about both violence worldview, and a corresponding decline in the role of and cooperation, in sharp contrast to medieval struc- the sacred. To be sure, as Christian Reus-Smit (1999, tures of overlapping authority and multiple actors. 94) points out, for a long time after Westphalia, inter- Importantly, despite being rationalized through di- national institutions retained "premodern" elements vine right, sovereign autonomy was granted to repub- with order seen as God given and monarchically pro- lican states as well as monarchies. This is evident in tected. Still, institutions adapted in ways sometimes Utrecht diplomacy, and in Vattel's words, echoed in at odds with these values. By 1814, three institutions several legal texts of the eighteenth century: "a dwarf in particular-international law, the balance of power, is as much a man as a giant is: a small republic is and diplomacy-reflected the deepening of a legally no less sovereign than the most powerful Kingdom" constituted horizontal normative order and sphere of (cited in Simpson 2004, 32). From there, as Andreas nonviolent communication among states. Osiander (1994, 87-8) notes, sovereign "equality was the unavoidable corollary of autonomy. The more there International Law. After Westphalia, what became was of the one, the more there had to be of the other." known later as "international law" became increas- Equality was formally recognized as the basis of diplo- ingly secularized and anchored in the corporate body macy and international law at the Congress of Vienna. of the state rather than individual monarchs or the Furthermore, state practice was becoming the au- Church. The religious wars had called into question the thoritative basis of law, competing with and ultimately replacing the authority of a divine or natural order. A sense coalesced in eighteenth-century legal writings 6 Among historians, Paul Schroeder (1994) is particularly known for that the states system was a distinct type of social sys- arguing that the Concert of Europe constituted a transformation of European politics. My argument is indebted to his work, although he tem that operated by its own rules. The legal rules does not conceptualize the transformation in terms of public spheres. of this system were discovered inductively, through 408 American Political Science Review Vol. 99, No. 3 patterns of interaction and treaties. This contrasted ance of power conceived as invisible hand. But this both with how law was treated at Westphalia, i.e., interpretation of how power operates in international mainly as (archaic) custom (Osiander 1994, 48) and politics overlooks important conceptual and historical with natural law, where rules are deduced from nature aspects of the eighteenth-century balance. It certainly and reflect an inherent, universal morality. Although was competitive and war-prone, but not because power some natural law reasoning can be found in his writings, was operating anonymously behind sovereigns' backs. Vattel in particular is seen to mark the shift toward a Patterns of competition and violence were rooted in law of nations based on consent and state practice (Bull and legitimated by shared understandings about the 1977, 33 ff.; Doyle 1992, 269). By the late eighteenth authoritative sources of power and use of force. century it was routine to speak in terms of the pub- As Habermas (1984, 266 ff.) himself argues in the lic law of Europe and "international law" (Suganami domestic context, although both power and money are 1978). media of integration, unlike money, power needs legit- Some might question whether these developments imation. Force alone is a brittle source of integration, constitute a normative, much less legal, order. After all, and Habermas argues that social cohesion ultimately this order eradicated neither war nor dynasticism. The rests on the subjects' felt duty or obligation to submit. eighteenth century was quite war-prone, and status and His argument is agnostic about the particular legiti- succession concerns remained a major cause of war. mating values, i.e., it does not mean that power will be Moreover, because the evolving legal order had neither legitimated communicatively or according to standards legislation nor enforcement, it did not look like law as of reason and equality. The legitimation requirement is we understand it in a domestic context. Still, normative general: whatever the prevailing norms, those in power order is evident, first, in the fact that wars were subject need their rule to be seen as legitimate. to rules-engaged in only by states, fought for limited This certainly was true of Europe's balance of power aims, and not fought for religious causes-that lim- in the eighteenth century, which guided state behavior ited violence, which distinguished them sharply from in ways that were underpinned and rationalized by dy- the organization of violence in the premodern period. nastic and Christian principles. First, the goal of foreign Second, as we saw earlier, a major function served by policy-glory-was a reflection of absolutist norms and law is to articulate rules of conduct in terms of the legitimated competition among sovereigns. War was general interest and to convey those rules to subjects. heroic and associated with ceremony and pageantry, Once law is known, participants are relieved of the and monarchs looked for opportunities to engage in burden of constantly negotiating the fundamentals of it in order to achieve glory for the state. As Martha interaction-who has authority to act, what outcomes Finnemore (2003, 106-7) puts it, force was a "positive can be negotiated; they can fall back on legal norms. good." Legal norms further sanctioned the sovereign's From this perspective, international law as it was devel- right to wage war and to declare his own cause just. oping in the eighteenth century certainly served legal While monarchs often attempted to negotiate disputes, functions. Moreover, decision makers and scholars of the fact that norms legitimated sovereign will was a the period treated international law as law, so that the strong incentive to simply act, and to act quickly, which question of whether it was "really" law never came up. often meant war (Black 1999, 323-5; Gilbert 1951, 7; Notions of law as sovereign will coexisted easily with Hatton 1980, 15). notions of law as rooted in a natural order. The distinc- Second, balancing practices also reflected dynastic tion between law, morality, and state political action did norms. Concerns for hierarchy and relative rank among not harden until the positivist paradigm consolidated sovereigns meant that there was no norm of trust or co- in the nineteenth century (see Vagts and Vagts 1979, operation. Alliance loyalties were bargained according 568). to generally accepted rules of "compensation." Any In sum, the trajectory of international law shows that war involved numerous such transactions. Loyalty was a horizontal normative order took shape in the Euro- not expected; states often were as suspicious of their pean states system. The fact that these actors made allies as their adversaries, and indeed often left al- their power rationalizable according to practice, rather liances midwar if proposed a better deal (Finnemore than rank or archaic custom, was the first step toward 2003, 105-6; Schroeder 1994). Territory that in the pre- making it possible for state action ultimately to become Westphalian period had been seen as held by God's will subject to public reason. was now the monarch's property, which allowed it to become a fungible bargaining chip to restore interstate The Balance of Power. It might seem strange to think equilibrium (Anderson 1993, 47-8). of the balance of power as an "institution" of interna- Third, despite their struggles for individual glory, the tional society. Indeed, references in Habermas' writ- idea of a European balance had normative value for ings (1999a, 1999b) suggest that the balance of power sovereigns: it was their solution to the danger of conti- operates for him as it does for realists in IR: not nental hegemony. Sovereigns agreed that if all pursued as an institution, but mechanically, integrating states equilibrium the continent would remain stable. Thus, through the medium of power, with no normative con- beginning with the first modern invocation of a "just tent. States simply pursue their interests. The system is equilibrium of power" as the goal for European politics governed by an equilibrating mechanism, so that no at Utrecht in 1713, actively pursuing balance took on state need deliberately restrain itself or consciously a normative cast. Utrecht negotiators made efforts to think in terms of a larger interest. This is the bal- link individual goals to the broader systemic goal of 409
Description: