ebook img

Re-Engineering Philosophy for Limited Beings: Piecewise Approximations to Reality PDF

469 Pages·2007·24.26 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Re-Engineering Philosophy for Limited Beings: Piecewise Approximations to Reality

Cartoon by Sydney Harris, Physics Today, February 1988. Courtesy of Sidney Harris and ScienceCartoonsPlus.com. Re-Engineering Philosophy for Limited Beings W PIECEWISE APPROXIMATIONS TO REALITY WILLIAM C. WIMSATT HARVARD UNIVERSITY PRESS Cambridge, Massachusetts, and London, England 2007 Copyright Cl 2007 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Wimsatt, William C. Re-engineering philosophy for limited beings : piecewise approximations to reality f William C. Wimsatt. p. em. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN-13: 978-0-674-01545-6 (alk. paper) ISBN-10: 0-674-01545-2 (alk. paper) 1. Philosophy. I. Title. B29.W498 2007 191--dc22 2006052988 To my generators and support- past: my parents, Ruth and Bill Wimsatt present: my partner in life, Barbara Horberg Wimsatt future: our son, William Samuel Abell ("Upski") Wimsatt Preface In the early 1990s, when I finally decided it was time to put together the papers that would become this volume, the tides of rationalism were near their high-water mark. Game theory increasingly dominated eco nomics and political science, and optimizers in economics were talking to those in biology. Rationalism had been strong in philosophy for my entire professional generation, beginning in the mid-1960s. Natu ralism's hold seemed less certain. Realism seemed on the retreat, not only within philosophy but also with the rise of science studies. Now we see a growing and refreshing empiricism about many things "philosophical," even rationality itself. Traditional idealizations seem less satisfactory on all sides. New disciplines have emerged, intersecting many of our knottiest problems of the biological and human sciences those problems often called methodological or conceptual or philosoph ical, and increasingly described as complex, in the senses of chapters 8, 9, and 10 of this volume. Behavioral decision theory has begun to have its day. Gigerenzer, Hutchins, and others project a more heuristic, col lective, and contextually imbedded image of our intellectual powers. An explosion in the past decade of works on human biological, cognitive, social, cultural, and above all collective evolution have made it only natural to look for our human natures through a historically and so cially informed multidisciplinary scientific perspective. The human sci ences and the Darwinian sciences, cluster terms emerging in the past decade, are both appropriately named and increasingly interpene trating. Perhaps Herbert Simon and Donald Campbell's different but viii · Preface consilient evolutionary visions of our kind will come to pass {see more on this below). But there is also a lively antiscientism abroad opposing this-perhaps largely in response to the excessive reductionism of the past generation. Philosophers like John MacDowell see scientific perspectives on human nature as too coarse, rigid, and insensitive to capture our intentional worlds of mind and culture. Past materialisms have regularly promised urban renewal of these neighborhoods to make room for the latest seemingly spare materialism, bringing a bulldozer when a cultural li aison mission was called for. This is not the form of integrative materi alism now emerging. Scientific-cultural liaisons now blossom, and new progress in all of the human and Darwinian sciences could result from richer and more appreciative interdisciplinary interactions. Hopefully, enough practitioners of traditional disciplines will recognize that it is again time for new infusions for the health of all and will resist the temptation to erect defensive conceptual trade barriers. The ironies of the frontispiece simultaneously document the hubris of a too-simple physics-inspired reductionism, and my commitment to "everything in between." It is thus a singularly suitable way to begin this book. I thank Sidney Harris for permission to use his inspired wry insights on the human scientific condition. The oldest of these chapters goes back more than 30 years; the youngest, only a few months. It has been about 25 years since Lindsay Waters suggested that I put a book of them together, and I'm happy now to surrender my seniority as his longest-standing project though it has evolved from a collection of papers to a more systematic work. He has maintained an ongoing conversation and stream of suggestions (readings as well as modulations) all along. For years I didn't have the right mix, and others developed alongside. These are, I hope, the first of more "right mixes" to come. This collection combines older papers, newer ones (several never before published and written especially for this volume), and substantial new introductory essays. With the older papers (chapters 4-6 and 8-11) I have made only minor stylistic revisions, removed old misprints, and occasionally added new bibliographical references. ChapterS's section on group se lection was reorganized to eliminate redundancies with Chapter 4. These papers have aged well-often anticipating newer directions and still relevant as they stand, though references and descriptions of other positions are occasionally dated. When not central to the argument, I have left them unchanged. I apply a naturalistically conceived ration- Preface · ix ality to the analysis of the complex world we live in, and to what kinds of beings we are that we do so. I hope the collection has the right hooks and balance to interest scientists and philosophers alike. It is a natura listic and realist philosophy of science for limited beings studying a much less limited world. It mines science for philosophical lessons more commonly than the reverse. The key concepts here (robustness, heuristic strategies, near-decomposability, levels of organization, mech anistic explanation, and generative entrenchment) are applied to ex plore the cognitive tools with which we approach the world and our parts in it. Reductionism-the source of past and continuing threats of assault from below on the human sciences and humanities-is both target and resource, as much for its methodology as for its results. The result is a softer, richer vision of our world and our place in it than promised by both sides in the history of the warfare between men talisms and materialisms. It is a more appropriate philosophy of sci ence, I argue, than we have been given so far. Acknowledgments are spread through the chapter endnotes. The new ma terials (chapters 1-3, 7, most of 12, and 13; the part introductions; and the appendixes) emerged during and between several "writing retreats." I thank the staff of Villa Serbelloni, the Rockefeller Foundation Center at Bellagio (in a warm, dry, beautiful, and amicable March 1997), the Franke Humanities Center at Chicago (for another part of that year, and of 2004-2005), and finally the staff and fellows of the National Humani ties Center in Research Triangle Park of Raleigh-Durham, North Car olina, for a glorious year in 2000-2001. Their catalyses were real, though nominally directed toward other projects, now further along and better than they would have been without their help. Some chapters benefited from the support of the National Science Foundation and the System De velopment Foundation, and my students, undergraduate and graduate, played a continuing role as midwives and sounding boards, many even as they developed their own careers. Particularly among these (in temporal order) have been Bob Richardson, Bill Bechtel, Bob McCauley, Jim Griesemer, Sahotra Sarkar, Jeffrey Schank, and Stuart Glennan. Schank and Griesemer coauthored multiple papers (and Schank, software) with me in the process, and were particularly productive for my own thought. Deeply formative influences of Herbert Simon, Donald Campbell, Richard Lewontin, Richard Levins, and Frank Rosenblatt all began for me in the mid-1960s, and have endured. Michael Wade's example and re-

Description:
Analytic philosophers once pantomimed physics: they tried to understand the world by breaking it down into the smallest possible bits. Thinkers from the Darwinian sciences now pose alternatives to this simplistic reductionism. In this intellectual tour--essays spanning thirty years--William Wimsatt
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.