ebook img

Practical Reasoning: The Structure and Foundations of Prudential and Moral Arguments and their Exemplification in Discourse PDF

157 Pages·1963·1.42 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Practical Reasoning: The Structure and Foundations of Prudential and Moral Arguments and their Exemplification in Discourse

Practical Reasoning The Structure and Foundations of Prudential and Moral Arguments and their Exemplification in Discourse DAVID P. GAUTHIER ASSISTANT PROFESSOR DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF TORONTO OXFORD AT THE CLARENDON PRESS 1963 -iii- Oxford University Press, Amen House, London E.C.4 GLASGOW NEW YORK TORONTO MELBOURNE WELLINGTON BOMBAY CALCUTTA MADRAS KARACHI LAHORE DACCA CAPE TOWN SALISBURY NAIROBI IBADAN ACCRA KUALA LUMPUR HONG KONG © Oxford University Press 1963 PRINTED IN GREAT BRITAIN -iv- PREFACE THE first ten chapters of this study are a considerably shortened version of my doctoral thesis, accepted by the University of Oxford in 1961. The remaining three chapters are based on a study of prin- ciples, obligation, and duty undertaken at Oxford in 1961, and financed by a Humanities Research Grant from the University of Toronto. The entire study owes more than may be apparent to Mr. R. M. Hare's excellent book, The Language of Morals, with which I have so often disagreed. It was this book, which I read first as a graduate student at Harvard in 1955, which convinced me that moral philosophy was a profitable field of inquiry, and induced me to begin the investigations of which this is the result. I must express my gratitude to the late Professor J. L. Austin, the original supervisor of my doctoral studies, who clarified my think- ing concerning advice, to Mr. Patrick Gardiner of Magdalen College, who read and discussed with me two drafts of my manu- script, to Mr. Aaron Sloman, who took time from his own studies to read and comment voluminously upon my doctoral thesis, and to my colleague, Professor John Hunter, who read and commented upon an earlier draft of Chapter VIII. I am also grateful for the patience of my wife, who understands, and my children, who are too young to understand, why daddy is sometimes so busy. I should like to believe that I have said something true. But, warned by the fate of others, I shall be content if I have indicated some promising fields for further examination. D. P.G. University of Toronto October 1962 -v- CONTENTS I. PRACTICAL PROBLEMS 1 I.1 Context 1 I.2 Solution 4 I.2.1 Action 5 I.2.2 Decision 6 II. PR ACT ICAL JUDGEMENTS 9 2.1 Formulation 10 2.2 Judgement and Decision 12 2.2.1 'Ought' and Decision 15 2.2.2 Judgement and Reasons 17 2.3 P rudential and Moral 18 III. T HE PRUDENTIAL BASIS 24 3.1 Aristotle on Deliberation 24 3.1.1 The Practical Starting-point 27 3.1.2 Reasoning about Reasons 31 3.2 W ants and Reasons for Acting 33 3.2.1 Impulses 36 3.2.2 Wants and Time 38 3.2.3 Wishes 40 3.2.4. Conclusion 42 3.3 P rudential Inference 43 3.3.1 Logical Validity 45 3.3.2 Demonstrability 48 IV. P RUD ENTIAL DISCOURSE 50 4.1 The Imperative 50 4.2 Advice 53 4.2.1 Advisee's Point of View 54 4.3 O ther Imperatives 57 4.3.1 Instruction 57 4.3.2 Hortation 59 4.3.3 Command 61 4.3.4 Request 62 4.4 A ssent to Imperatives 63 -vii- V. APPRAISAL OF ADVICE 66 5.I Criticisms of the Adviser 66 5.1.1 Competence 66 5.1.2 Title 68 5.1.3 Sincerity 70 5.2 Criticisms of the Advice 72 5.2.1 Applicability 73 5.2.2 Soundness 74 5.2.3 Extrinsic Criticisms 75 5.3 Functional Appraisal 76 VI. T HE MORAL BASIS 81 6.1 The Wants of Others 81 6.2 The Extended Basis 86 6.2.1 All wants. . . 86 6.2.2 . . . of all persons. . . 87 6.2.3 . . . are to be included 89 6.3 Further Extensions? 90 6.3.1 Reasons for Acting 91 VII. LOG IC AND PRACTICE 95 7.1 The Condition of Practical Inference 95 7.1.1 Validity 99 7.2 Justification of the Condition of Practical Inference 103 7.2.1 Justification of the Condition of Moral Inference 104 VIII . TH E RATIONAL AGENT 111 8.1 Kant on Autonomy 111 8.2 Morality as Autonomy respecting Autonomy 115 8.2.1 Autonomy. . . 115 8.2.2 . . . respecting Autonomy 117 8.2.3 The Dual Role of Autonomy 120 IX. C ON FLICTING WANTS 123 9.1 Wants and Persons 123 9.2 Extent of Concern 127 9.3 Direct Opposition 131 -viii- X. MORAL DISCOURSE 135 10.1 The Moral Imperative 135 10.1.1 Moral Counsel and Hortation 136 10.1.2 Moral Counsel and Command 137 10.1.3 Moral Counsel and Advice 145 10.2 Appraisal of Moral Counsel 148 10.2.1 Criticisms of the Counsellor 148 10.2.2 Criticisms of the Counsel 151 XI. P RAC TICAL PRINCIPLES 155 11.1 General Practical Judgements 155 11.1.1 Practical Experience 156 11.1.2 Defeasibility 159 11.2 Acting on Principle 160 11.2.1 Personal Rules 160 11.2.2 Equity 163 11.2.3 Assurance 165 11.3 Principles and Morality 168 11.3.1 R. M. Hare 168 11.3.2 P. H. Nowell-Smith 170 11.3.3 Kurt Baier 171 XII. OBL IGATION 174 12.1 The Uses of 'Oblige' 174 12.1.1 The Context of Objectives 176 12.1.2 The Obliging Factor 179 12.2 Obligation and Morality 183 12.2.1 Thomas Hobbes on Obligation 186 12.2.2 Conclusion 191 XIII . DU TY 193 13.1 The Use of 'Duty' 193 13.1.1 Duties and Roles 196 13.1.2 Duties and Obligations 201 13.2 Duty and Morality 202 13.2.1 Duties and Rights of a Rational Agent 203 INDE X 207 -ix- I PRACTICAL PROBLEMS A PRACTICAL problem is a problem about what to do. In saying this we are using the word 'practical' more widely than in every- day discourse, to characterize all problems, individual and social, prudential and moral, whose final solution is found only in doing something, in acting. Practical problems may be contrasted with theoretical problems, whose solution is found in knowing some- thing, in understanding. Each of us is continually faced with practical problems--some trivial, others important, some easily met, others admitting no satisfactory solution. Examples will suggest their variety: I've put tab A in slit A'; what do I do next? How can I convince her that I love her? Which of these suits shall I buy? For which candidate ought I to vote? Should I read for the law, or consider some other profession?. Ought I to engage in civil disobedience, in support of nuclear disarmament? What shall I do this evening? What shall I do, now that George is dead? I ought to visit my aunt this afternoon, but shall I? I could make a tidy sum speculating against sterling, but should I? 1.1. Context A practical problem is related to a particular context. It confronts a certain person (or group) whose capacities, outlook, and achieve- ments limit his actions. It usually arises out of his particular circumstances, and must be met by action on a specified occasion or situation. On the occasion the person concerned must be able to affect what happens by his action, and, if he is to consider the -1- problem seriously, must judge one possible effect to be more desir- able than another. Theoretical problems do not display this same relation to con- text. A theoretical problem may arise for a particular person, whose ability to solve it is limited, but the solution is not itself thereby limited. And it may arise out of particular circumstances--one wants to explain why the bathroom pipes froze last night--but it does not specify any occasion or situation in which it must be solved. What to do about a theoretical problem may be a practical problem, dependent on the person concerned and his situation, but the theoretical question may be separated from this context. A practical problem is met by action in a situation, or at a certain time. What shall we serve when the Smiths come to dinner? What shall we do this afternoon? When the situation arises, or the time comes, we must do something--even if we do nothing. But what we do need not solve the problem. For we may well do the wrong thing. When I ask 'What am I to do?', I do not want to know what I shall do, but what I should do. Practical problems are solved by doing something--but only by doing the right thing, by performing the correct action. Once the action, whatever it may be, is performed, the possibility of solving the problem is past--if it has not then been solved, it can never be solved. The problem specifies the occasion of its possible solution-- it demands resolution at this time, but may not receive it. The relation of practical problems to their context is of the first importance in considering the methods of practical reasoning. These methods must enable us to solve a problem under the limitations which the context imposes. If we are not able to determine what to do, but only what, had we but known, we should have done, we are not able to solve our practical problems. Thus it is quite mis- taken to employ ideal standards in justifying practical judgements; the standards must relate to the judgement or decision as contri- buting to the solution of the actual problem. The dynamic aspect of the context of practical problems also affects the methods of practical reasoning. Although we consider what to do before we act, yet we act in the light of what we are already doing, of what is presently happening, and of what we propose to -2- do, of what we expect to happen. When confronted with a practical problem, we do not and cannot bring ourselves and our world to rest, and then set everything once more in motion by our actions. This possibility is perhaps most nearly realized if the course of a man's life is brought to a sudden halt--his family is killed, or his business is ruined--and he must consider what to do to begin anew. But such extreme situations are fortunately rare. General formulae for the solution of practical problems, or for the justification of proposed solutions, which do not take account of the dynamic context, can offer little practical guidance to the agent. A rigorous nineteenth-century utilitarian would insist that any question about what to do ought to be answered by considering what action would provide the greatest happiness for the greatest number, or would satisfy some subordinate principles derived from this supreme criterion. But in practice the answer to a practical question must depend, not only on an appeal to a hierarchy of principles, but far more on an appeal to a context of activity, in which the general programme of action is already fixed. Practical reasoning often consists in showing that an action fits into such a context. Rather than a hierarchy of principles, a hierarchy of problems confronts us in practical reasoning. Suppose, for example, that I am undecided about what to do this morning. After reflecting on several alternatives, I decide to work in my garden. I then consider what I shall do there, and settle on weeding the lawn. And after making all preparations, I may hesitate just for a moment, and ask myself where to begin. The subdivision of problems suggested in this example is by no means necessary. I might equally well, on first considering what to do, have settled immediately on weeding the lawn. On the other hand, I might merely have elected to work at home, rather than to go to the university to continue a philosophical paper, or to the railway to watch trains. The individuation of problems within a hierarchy depends on the questions the person concerned actually considers. There is no simple correspondence between actions and problems. One problem may determine, in a general way, an entire sequence of actions (as -3- in the example), or it may--should one decide to do nothing about some matter--determine no actions whatever. One action may be intended to contribute to tee solution of quite independent problems (as those who insist that business may be combined with pleasure assure us) or--as a random or reflex action--to the solution of no problem at all. Problems which belong entirely within a hierarchy, although common, are of little interest in the study of practical reasoning. The arguments used to resolve them, or to justify a solution adopted, do not present considerations of importance. Only when, through failure satisfactorily to solve them, we are forced to recon- sider the context within which they arise, do they give rise to more interesting patterns of reasoning. Most frequently we find, not only a satisfactory, but a definite, conclusive answer to questions such as 'How do I weed my garden?' or 'What do I do after putting tab A in slit A'?' Problems of this type may be termed procedural; they will receive brief further mention in 4.3.1 But many of our problems, even if they begin as procedural, can- not be confined to a simple hierarchy. Having adopted an objective, I consider how to attain it, but, in so doing, issues relevant to other activities in which I am engaged, or objectives which I seek, may arise. Again, such problems may raise quite different issues, such as the effect of my actions upon the activities of other persons, which introduce questions extending beyond my entire range of objectives. When we are faced with problems which cannot be treated as procedural, our reasons for acting are not fully established in advance. Only as we consider what we can do or not do, can we determine what wants and desires, aims and ends, may be affected by our action. As a result of this inquiry we establish practical judgements. 1.2. Solution To clarify the role of practical judgements, it is necessary to consider more fully the nature of the solution to a practical problem. Certain terminological distinctions will prove useful here. The verbal formulation of a practical problem I shall call a practical -4- question. Thus the exemplification of practical problems at the beginning of this chapter consisted of a series of practical questions. An action, or set of actions, performed by the person in the situation specified in the problem, I shall call the solution. A decision taken by the person concerning what to do in the situation, I shall call the resolution. A judgement about what to do in the situation, or an injunction to do something, I shall call the answer to the practical question. Whether these three are completely distinct, and whether each is always present, will have to be considered, as will the dis- tinction between judgement and injunction. 1.2.1. Action However resolved we may be on what to do, however certain we may be of what we should do, unless we do in fact perform the action decided upon, we do not satisfactorily meet our practical problem. The answers to practical questions are intended, not merely to increase our knowledge, but to guide our actions. Decisions, although they end our deliberations and hence our practical worries, are intended only to determine our actions. I may know how to convince her that I love her, but unless I put my knowledge into practice, I shall not convince her, and hence I shall not achieve the objective which sets my problem. Thus it is reasonable to use 'solution' to refer to the action, rather than the decision or judge- ment, provided it be recognized that the solution is, or may be, but a part of our response to a practical problem. We have seen that not all actions that could be performed in the situation envisaged solve a practical problem. If, when I enter the polling-booth, I mark my ballot-paper at random, I have in no way solved the problem of how I ought to vote (unless, for some unlikely reason, I judge that I ought to mark the ballot-paper quite at random). I have voted, but I have not taken any step towards voting as I should, voting for the best candidate, or the candidate of the best political party. The problem, at least as a practical problem, no longer exists because the situation has passed, but I have not met the problem by solving it. One may fail to solve a practical problem fully and satisfactorily in any of several ways. Examples will suggest the most important: -5- i. I judge that I ought to vote for Jones, and do so. In this case, I consider that I have solved my problem, and solved it satisfactorily. ii. I judge that I ought to vote for Jones, and do so. Later, how- ever, I reflect on my judgement, and decide that I was mistaken; I ought to have voted for Smith. I now consider that I erred in solving my problem. iii. I judge that I ought to vote for Jones, and do so. Later, I come into possession of information, which I could not reasonably have known at the time of voting, that leads me to conclude that I ought rather to have voted for Smith. I now consider that, although I did solve my problem, so far as was possible at the time, yet the solution has proved unsatisfactory. iv. I am unable to determine conclusively how I ought to vote, despite my best efforts to do so. I judge, however, that most probably I ought to vote for Jones. I consider that I have solved my problem as far as possible, but not fully. v. I make no extensive effort to determine how I ought to vote, but judge that, on the face of it, I ought to vote for Jones. I consider that I have reached a tentative solution to my problem. vi. I make no effort to determine how I ought to vote, but merely mark my ballot-paper for Jones. I do not consider that I have in any way solved my problem. If I later decide that indeed I ought to have voted for Jones, I do not suppose that in fact I solved my problem satisfactorily, but only that I did the right thing. Compare this last case with a mathematical problem. A man, confronted with an algebraic equation, writes down, as a pure guess, the answer 'x = 6'. Finding this to be the right answer does not lead him to suppose that he has solved the equation. To do the right thing, to get the right answer, is of course achieved by the person who solves his problem satisfactorily, but it may be achieved without solving it at all. 1.2.2. Decision A practical problem is resolved when the person confronted with it decides, or is decided about, what to do. Decision, although it does not in itself solve our practical problems, terminates our con- sideration of them; once we have decided, the problem no longer -6- presents itself as a problem. If asked what we shall do, we have a ready answer. Resolution need not involve the making of a decision. We need not suppose that, to be decided about what to do, we need have come consciously to a decision; it is not unusual simply to find one- self decided. But the process of decision-making is not our concern; it is only the result--the decision itself which enters our argument. When we are decided, we know what we shall do. It is important to distinguish this knowledge from that which rests upon prediction. If, for example, I know that I shall go to a party, because I know that I shall not have the will-power to refuse, I cannot suppose either that I have decided to go, or not to go. If I have decided to go, I need not predict that I shall go; if I have really decided not to go, I can- not predict that nevertheless I shall. When we are decided, we know what we shall do, but do we know what to do? I decide to vote for Jones, not because I know him to be the candidate for whom I ought to vote, but simply to settle the matter. I terminate consideration of my problem, but without satisfactorily answering the question it raises. Resolution would seem not to imply a prospective solution. But is my decision a true resolution of my problem? Perhaps it is more reasonable to say that, just as I must, in some cases, act with- out my action constituting a solution to my problem, so here I decide without my decision constituting a resolution. Although my prob- lem concerns what to do, it is resolved only by deciding to do that which I should do, just as it is solved only by doing that which I should do. Thus the initial statement of this section demands qualification; a practical problem is resolved when the person con- fronted with it: decides, or is decided, to do what he considers will best solve his problem. A resolution, just as a solution, may prove unsatisfactory, and in the same ways. But in addition, it is worth noting the case in which one is unable to do what one decides to do, so that one's sup- posed resolution does not in fact provide a solution--satisfactory or unsatisfactory--to the practical problem. The connexion between practical solution and resolution is quite straightforward. If I perform an action, considering it to be the -7- solution to some practical problem, then I must have reflected on what to do and decided upon that action--that is, I must have resolved my problem If I have not resolved my problem, then, how- ever much I may hope that what I do will prove right, I cannot suppose it to be the solution. Many actions are, of course, performed without prior decision. Frequently I glance at my watch to determine the time without having considered whether to do so; I may rise and dress in the morning without taking thought about the matter. In such cases I should not say that I had decided to perform the action or set of actions, although I should not mean that I was undecided whether to perform them. To act without consideration is to act without the possibility either of decision or indecision. Such action, although it may in fact meet a practical problem, is not performed as a solu- tion to it. Note that the connexion between decision and action may be complicated if one person is subject to the authority of another. A soldier is expected to act on the orders of his superior officer; it is insubordination for him to consider whether or not to carry them out. It is the officer who decides what the soldier is to do, expressing his decision in his order. The soldier's actions may then be intended by the officer to meet some practical problem; the officer resolves the problem, the soldier solves it. In such a case, the problem 'belongs' to the person who resolves it. In so far as what is to be done is my problem, it is for me to decide. And only if I decide, does what is done count as a solution to my problem. -8- II PRACTICAL JUDGEMENTS RESOLUTION of one's practical problems requires decision to do what one considers best. If I decide to vote for Jones, the Labour candidate, and if, in so deciding, I believe that I am resolving my problem, then I must suppose that I have sufficient reason to vote for him rather than to vote for someone else, or than not to vote at all. I must accept the practical judgement: 'In the coming general election, the best course of action for D. P. G. is to vote for Jones.' A practical judgement answers a practical question. 'For whom ought D. P. G. to vote?' 'D. P. G. ought to vote for Jones.' The answer need not, of course, be expressed in the form of a judgement. Several of the questions at the beginning of the first chapter would most naturally be answered by a simple imperative, others by phrases or a word. For example: 'I've put tab A in slit A'; what do I do next?' 'Put tab B in slit B'.' 'Which of these suits shall I buy?' 'The charcoal-grey suit.' 'Ought I to engage in civil disobedience in support of nuclear disarmament?' 'No.' These answers are intelligible only in context; if the problem is not previously specified, the import of the answer may not be clear. The practical judgement, although it sets out the answer to a practical question at greater length than often is required, states it in the fullest and most immediately intelligible manner. Of course, if I am asked why I am voting for Jones, simply to say that I consider I should vote for him is not sufficient. I should, rather than merely state the practical judgement, support it--give the reasons that I consider adequate to justify my decision to vote Labour. Thus the practical judgement need not enter explicitly into a justification of my decision, but my acceptance of it is neces- sary if my decision is to possess rational justification. -9- 2.1. Formulation There is no single formula which can suggest the manifold ways in which practical judgements may be expressed. Therefore, even if a formula may serve to indicate the logical structure of the judge- ment, we must begin with examples of the varied phrasings which actually occur in everyday discourse: The best thing (for me, you, him) to do is to surrender. The only thing to do is to ignore their threats. (I think) sausages would be best for dinner tonight. It is better to love and lose, than never to love at all. I should (you, he would) be best advised to study law. I (you, he) should accept the offer made by Consolidated Cement. I (you, he) ought to visit my (your, his) aunt this afternoon. Jones's plan is the most suitable (most promising) in these circumstances. Jones's plan ought to be adopted in these circumstances. The particular phrasing of a practical judgement will depend on the character of the problem and the type of considerations backing the judgement. For example, when concern is primarily with the relationship between the proposed course of action and the atten- dant situation, it is natural to use such words as 'fitting' or 'suitable'. Especially is this so if the problem is to choose among a more or less fixed number of alternatives: the canvasser seeks the approach best suited to the particular prospect; the guest, the compliment most fitting for his hostess. Although many practical judgements are formulated without them, 'ought', 'should', and 'best' belong to the basic vocabulary of practical discourse. The person faced with a practical problem wants to know what to do given, not only a situation in which to act, but reasons for acting. It is this which is brought out in the use of such phrases as 'the best thing to do', 'what one should do', 'what one ought to do'. Rough equivalences hold between these phrases. 'One ought to do x', 'one should do x', 'x is the best thing to do' are, although not entirely interchangeable, sufficiently similar that the truth of one -10- usually implies the truth of the others, the falsity of one, the falsity of the others.

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.